Lesson 11: DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS: IMMANUEL KANT Kant’s principles require universalizing one’s contemplated action or policy. Here, we will be asked to consider what constitutes proper treatment of persons as persons. According to Kant, one key characteristic of persons is their ability to set their own goals. Persons are autonomous. They are literally self ruled, or at least capable of being self-ruled. As persons, we choose our own life plans, what we want to be, our friends, our college courses, and so forth. We have our own reasons for doing so. We believe that although we are influenced in these choices and reasons by our situation and by others, we let ourselves be so influenced, and thus these choices are still our own choices. In this way, persons are different from things. Things cannot choose what they wish to do. We decide how we shall use things. We impose our own goals on things, using the wood to build the house and the pen or computer to write our words and express our ideas. It is appropriate in this scheme of things to use things for our ends, but it is not appropriate to use persons as though they were things purely at our own disposal and without a will of their own. LEARNING OUTCOMES After studying this chapter, the students should be able to: 1. Explain the meaning of deontological ethics and categorical imperative; 2. Appreciate and articulate the role of duty in crafting an ethical life; and 3. Create a concept map summarizing Kant’s idea of Deontological Ethics. LECTURE NOTES Immanuel Kant Born 22 April 1724 to a religious and lower middle class family, Immanuel Kant had his education at the local Pietistic Friedrichskolleg of Konigsberg, East Prussia (now Kaliningrad, Russia). His interest in Philosophy started when he continued his studies at the University of Konigsberg. From 1746-1755 Kant worked as a tutor for the rich families of his city until he got an appointment as instructor at his own university. He was an effective teacher and in 1770 was awarded full professorship. "Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe... the ember in the stars and the moral law within." These occupied the studies of Kant that he made a name through his opus writings: General Natural History and Theory of Heavens (1755), Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785). In the photo: Immanuel Kant Critique of Practical Reason (1788), Metaphysics of Morals (1797) and Religion within the Limits of Reason (1792/94). He was never married Photo source: medium.com though he enjoyed a vibrant social life. He died on 12 February 1804 with the last words es ist gut (It is Good). Introduction Franz Kafka once gave voice to the solitude of man and his/her task to find his/her own way. Kafka wrote the story of “an imperial message” directly addressing the reader as the pathetic subject. The story started with the sending of a message from the farthest distance. A dying king ordered his 39 Herald to bring his whispered message. After confirming the accuracy of the message, the Herald was sent breaking down obstructing walls and going beyond the great ones of the empire at first. Eventually, however, he is slowed down by the huge crowd and the infinite distance that lie between him and the receiver of the message. The reader to whom the message is addressed in the end sits by the window dreaming of the message that may come. The reader is directly addressed by Kafka and invited to move out of dreaming and end his/her pathetic passivity, left on his/her won, he/she is tasked to find his/her own way and not give in to dreams of fullness of knowledge that are given to him/her or the discovery of a path that is yet to be revealed. A professor once situation by asking, "If early morning tomorrow you wake up so sure that there is no God, what would you do?" The German thinker Immanuel Kant (1724-1804 proposed a viable human solution to this quandary. His philosophy views man as autonomous and most of himself/herself as not subject to external conditions, results, and mandates. If left to himself/herself, is it possible for the human person to be ethical? Immanuel Kant thinks so. In fact, he was so confident in the ethical system that he came up with what he declares its systematic independence from religion and even asserted that it is religion that is in need of his foundational ethics and not vice versa. Autonomous Reason, Goodwill, and Duty Kant insists that every time we confront moral situations there are formally operative a priori principles that can be brought to the fore. Highlighting these a priori truths can better help the learner of ethics sort through his/her task of living ethically. Kant's research on ethics has named these as reason, goodwill, and duty. These are, for Kant, respectively, the foundation (reason), source (goodwill), and motivation (duty) of ethical living. Human Reason The foundation of a sound ethics for Immanuel Kant can only be the authority of human reason. The voice of God not heard directly today while man is living in this passing world. Voices of ministers and priests who claim to speak for God are but other human beings who make use of their own reason in trying to understand what goes on around them. This common human reason is also what they use as they comprehend the revelation that is said to be the foundation of their particular religion. Given that they share the same humanity with everybody else including the students of ethics, what they say ought to pass through the norm of reason that is internal to the moral subject himself/herself. Otherwise, arbitrariness holds sway in their claim to authority and what they capriciously hold as binding or gratuitously free. The person who acts in accordance to drawn-up lists of what one should do complies through the use of his/her reason that they are indeed an obligation for his/her. The reason, therefore, elects such and such as morally binding and thus acts in accordance with what he/she thinks is so. His/Her reason, therefore, functions as the very effort to think through moral principles and apply what he/she knows to get to the right thing to do. In fact, this internal authority human reason is operative and takes precedence every time the human person confronts a particular moral situation. This is human rationality that is discursive, i.e., humans reason "talking to themselves," according to one of the Philosopher-readers of Kant named Hannah Arendt. What is ethical necessarily always implies the use of reason. Human acceptance of external mandates also makes use of this same reason. Kant then tells us that reason in itself can only be the sensible foundation of what is ethical for man. Kant then bids his students sapere aude that is "dare to think for yourselves." Autonomous reason ventures to know what is ethical not on the authority of what is external to the self but grounded on (reason) itself. The loudness of external authorities cannot bend the autonomy of reason that on its own knows what should be done. What others say in turn is only acceptable if it is found to be reasonable by the use of one's autonomous reason. 40 Goodwill If reason is the foundation of what is ethical for Kant, in turn its source can only be goodwill. This simply means that what is morally binding is rooted in reason as "doable for the human person." The moral authority for Kant is immanent in man, that is, the origin of ethical obligation for man is his/her own goodwill. Instead of looking at the good as external to man, Kant locates the good in the very interiority of the self. The good that is relevant to the person who through his/her reason knows what one ought to do, is that which he/she can do and know as good. This goodwill implies the achievability of what is known through reason. One who claims what one says is a moral obligation can do so by being free of impositions from outside. That is, he/she is of his/her own doing able to carry out his/her obligation. It can only oblige him/her insofar as he/she himself/herself through his/her own reason knows it as an obligation. In the same way that it is an obligation insofar that it is something that he/she on his/her own can manage to do. Duty Kant calls “duty” the obligation that follows what reason deems as the action which is most worthy of our humanity. This duty is founded on human reason, that is, it passes through the sorting out made by our autonomous and discursive reason Our duty is that which the reason determines as our obligation. Inasmuch as duty is the doable obligation for the human person, it is not a duty if it is impossible for man to do it. Duty, therefore, presupposes our ability for otherwise it is only a bother to the human person. Duty, therefore, is a doable good for the human will. Duty, while founded on human reason for determination, is at the very same time originating from the goodwill as a voluntary action that is doable for the human being. Duty or obligation is the motivation for reason and goodwill of the human person. If one asks why he/she had to do what he/she ought to do, the answer can only be because it is his/her duty. Reason tells the human person to do the obligation that is doable for the goodwill again since it is her/ her duty. The good that is reachable for the will of the human person is, therefore, owned by him/her as a duty. This then excludes any other external or internal motivation for the human person for doing what he/she ought to do: whether he/ she likes it or not; be it success or failure; whether it comes with applause or accusation; his/her reason and goodwill simply binds him/her to do what he/she ought to do because it is his/her duty. Kantian Ethics and Religion Immanuel Kant fully established the independence of his ethics from religion via the recognition of reason as the foundation, goodwill as the source, and duty as the motivation of what obliges the human person. In his essay “Religions within the Limits of Reason”, Kant went as far as setting up his ethical system as that which is definitive in the recognition of true religion. A “religion is not true to itself,” according to Kant, if it goes against what man “ought to do” as defined by his/her autonomous reason and goodwill that reaches for universalizability. Only false religion or cult falls unreasonably to superstition and does away with duty as an obligation for his/her goodwill. It is, therefore, such Kantian ethics that is foundational for religion and not vice versa. Kant, however, is not against religion. For him the value of religion rests on its reality as an openness to “what one Can hope for.” Religion for Kant is the very openness of ethics to the complementary strength that is provided by hope. Unlike Aristotle, Kant does not define “happiness” as the motivation for his ethics of duty. What is ethical is indifferent to happiness for Kant and is purely motivated by duty itself. One does the obligation to reach for happiness, that will be self-serving for Kant and self-interest here moves away from the purity of duty. 41 Happiness, however, is understood by the human reason as reasonably related to ethics. “He/She who has lived justly by doing his/her obligation dutifully is the most fitting for happiness.” This truth, the human reason knows and even goes as far as protesting the reality of just men living miserably. “Happiness ought to be related to the ethical task of man,” reason asserts in protest. It is clear, however, that happiness cannot be a motivation for the ethical obligation of man, according to Kant. He, therefore, suggests the determination of “happiness as gift” for the ethical man. That is, “he/she who has lived justly is worthy of the gift of happiness.” Man cannot give this gift to himself/herself and therefore in his/her striving to live ethically opens himself/herself in hope. Kantian ethics, therefore, need not be hard-hearted in the pure preoccupation of duty as obligatory. The ethical person is open to happiness he/she cannot give to himself/herself. His/Her duty can also be an expression of hope that “he/she can make himself/ herself worthy of happiness.” For Kant, the ethical human person is like someone who woos in courtship the person one likes. He/She cannot oblige the other to give him/her a positive answer to his/her offering of love and devotion. He/She can only make himself/herself worthy of a “yes.” Responding to his/her love is a gift he/she can only receive from the other. The answer cannot be forced in the same way that happiness is something one expects to collect after a lifelong striving of doing one’s duty. Happiness is a gratuitous gift that one recognizes as within the realm of how. LEARNING ACTIVITY Answer the following questions concisely in a separate sheet of paper. 1. Why is autonomous reason the only acceptable foundation of ethics for Kant? 2. What is the importance of the Kantian shift from preoccupation with the external good to stress the internal goodwill? 3. How does doing one’s moral duty become autonomous and at the same time universalizable in the Kantian principle of “man as an end in himself/herself”? 4. What is the reasonable relationship between religion and ethics for Kant? 5. Explain hope as the tension between gift and task for Kantian philosophy. TASK Create a concept map summarizing Kant’s idea of Deontological Ethics. Rubric for assessing Concept Maps Identification of concepts Outstanding (5 pts) Acceptable (3 pts) Poor (2 pts) Map identifies the important concepts and provides evidence of understanding of knowledge domain on Map includes most important concepts and provides evidence of understanding knowledge Map includes some of the Important concepts provides evidence of understanding knowledge No Evidence/Inaccurate (1 pt) Map includes few concepts with most important concepts missing and limited or nonexistent evidence of understanding knowledge domain 42 multiple levels domain on some levels Interconnectivity among concepts Evidence of understanding relationships and how all concepts are interlinked with many other concepts Evidence of hierarchical organization and use of examples All concepts are organized hierarchically with clarity and with extensive number of relevant examples and links Critical thinking and communication Map provides evidence of complex and sophisticated critical thinking; most appropriate selection of type of concept map that allows for exceptional level of understanding Evidence of understanding of most relationships and how most concepts are interlinked with other concepts Most concepts are organized in hierarchical order with considerable clarity and with substantial number of examples and links provided Map provides some evidence of mostly complex and substantial critical thinking; appropriate selection of concept map that allows for proficient level of understanding domain on limited or one domain Evidence of understanding of some relationships and how some concepts are linked to other concepts Evidence of understanding of few relationships and how limited number of concepts are linked to other concepts Some concepts are organized in hierarchical order with fair with moderate number of examples and links Limited concepts are organized hierarchical or none at all, and there is a limited number of examples and links provided Map provides evidence of moderate critical thinking; the concept map selected allows for moderate level of understanding Map provides evidence of limited critical thinking; the type of concept map allows for basic level of understanding REFERENCES Pasco, Marc Oliver. Et al. General Education: Ethics. C & E Publishing, Inc.,2018 Kant, Immanuel. Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason and Other Works on the Theory Of EthicS, translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott. Whitefish, NY: Kessinger,2007. Loude, Robert. Kant’s mpure Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. Reyes, Ramon. Ground and Norm 0f Morality. Manila; Ateneo Press, 1989. Savater, Fernando. Apostatas Razonables. Barcelona: Mandragora, 2007. Savater, F ernando. Etica per un Figlio. Roma: Laterza, 2007. 43