Uploaded by Lucia Ines Santagada

07. Academic Writing 1 - Guidelines

advertisement
Academic Writing
1- Why do you write?
2- How do you write?
3- To whom do you write?
The Paragraph
4- Paragraph Format
Some Notes on Punctuation
Punctuation and other graphic conventions have to be formally taught while learning to
read and write. Punctuation has two main functions:
•
It separates units of grammar: for example, words are separated by a space,
sentences by a combination of mark + space, paragraphs by a new start to a line.
•
It indicates a specific grammatical or other function: for example, the
apostrophe indicates the genitive ending or the omission of a letter.
There are many differences in punctuation practice. American and British publishing
traditions differ, as do individual publishers. Individual writers also differ in their
preference for light or heavy punctuation, especially in the amount of the use of the
comma.
•
In fact I’ll go in the old red bus this time. (light)
•
In fact, I’ll go in the old, red bus, this time. (heavy)
5- Types of Paragraphs
Narrative Paragraphs
Descriptive Paragraphs
Expository Paragraphs
6- Organisation of Paragraphs
The Topic Sentence
Supporting Sentences
The Concluding Sentence
7- Coherence
David Crystal defines COHERENCE as ‘the underlying functional or logical
connectedness of a use of language.’ M.A.K. Halliday states that ‘for a text to be coherent,
it must be cohesive; it must be systematically appropriate, with lexico-grammatical
realisations to match, i.e. it must make sense; and it must have a structure.’
Chronological Ordering
Spatial Ordering
Explanatory Ordering
Types of Reasoning
There are two types of reasoning: INDUCTION and DEDUCTION (or inductive
reasoning and deductive reasoning). Virtually any piece of reasoned discourse
involving more then one or two logical steps will ordinarily include both types. The
two are interdependent, and the two are basically different. In order to deal
systematically with the elementary principles of logic, we shall consider each one
separately.
INDUCTION. Induction is that kind of reasoning which proceeds from the
particular to the general. That is, in induction we begin with a number of particular
facts and formulate a general statement or principle which covers them or indicates
what they all have in common.
Thus induction is commonly based directly on facts. These may be drawn from
personal experience, or they may be derived from second-hand sources. More often
both kinds of facts enter into the process: our own experiences are corroborated by
those of others, and the inductive conclusion is reinforced by the additional
evidence.
Two special types of induction are reasoning by analogy and reasoning by cause
and effect.
In reasoning by analogy we follow the inductive method in a special way. We
observe particular similarities between two things and then we generalise: we infer
that the two things are similar in other ways, too. We should remember that
reasoning by analogy never constitutes genuine proof, but only indicates that the
conclusion is likely to be true.
Closely related to reasoning by analogy is reasoning by cause and effect. This is based
on the assumption that like causes produce like effects, or that if we have often
previously seen cause A followed by effect B, the next time we see A we may expect
to see B again. Here we observe particular connections between things and infer a
more general relationship. In other words we may reason from cause to effect. We may
reason also from effect to cause. The classic illustration is a doctor diagnosis: from the
symptoms (effect) the doctor infers the nature of the disease (cause). Another
example is a crime investigation. Furthermore, we may reason also from effect to
effect. We do not know what the cause is, but we reason that if the effect has
appeared frequently, the effect is likely to appear again.
DEDUCTION. Deduction is that kind of reasoning which proceeds from the
general to the particular. That is, in deduction we begin with a general statement
or principle and apply it to a particular case. Presumably this generalisation was
itself arrived at previously on the basis of observed particulars; that is, the
generalisation was the product of induction. But the generalisation itself is the
starting-point for deduction. Deduction, as well as induction, is based on facts.
A single specimen of deductive reasoning can be expressed in the form of a
syllogism. The syllogism consists of three parts: (1) the major premise, stating the
general principle on which the reasoning is based; (2) the minor premise,
indicating the particular case to which the general principle is applied; (3) the
conclusion, which completes the logic of the application.
The bulk of all possible mistakes in reasoning, i.e. fallacies, actually fall under a
comparatively small number of types.
Common
Fallacies in
Inductive
Reasoning
Common
Fallacies in
Deductive
Reasoning
Inadequate Sampling or Hasty
Generalisation
The fallacy may occur when we generalise on
the basis of too few particulars or we ignore
other particulars which may show our
generalisation to be unsound.
Faulty Analogy
The fallacy may occur when from particular
similarities between two things we infer a
further or more general similarity which
does not really exist.
Faulty Casual Relationship
The fallacy may occur when the cause-andeffect relationship that is inferred does not
actually exist or, more frequently, when
more complex relationships are involved.
Faulty Premises
If there is something wrong with either or
both of the premises in a syllogism, then the
conclusion may be false even if the logic
itself is airtight.
Non Sequiturs
(Latin for ‘it does not follow’)
Unlike the use of false premises, fallacy is an
error in the logic itself, in the relationships
among the ideas. In other words the
conclusion does not follow from the
premises.
False and Irrelevant Issues
The fallacies which belong to this category
occur (1) when, although a piece of
reasoning may be logically sound, it proves
something else besides the point at issue, or
(2) when it does not really prove anything at
all because the reasoner assumes in his
argument the truth of what he is trying to
prove. The reasoner argues in circle.
8- Cohesive Devices
David Crystal defines COHESION as ‘the formal linkage between the elements of a text or
discourse.’
COHESION
GRAMMATICAL COHESIVE DEVICE
REFERENCE
Function
Endophoric Reference
Anaphoric Reference
Cataphoric Reference
Exophoric Reference
Category
Personal Reference
Demonstrative Reference
Comparative Reference
SUBSTITUTION
Nominal Substitution
Verbal Substitution
Clausal Substitution
ELLIPSIS
Nominal Ellipsis
Verbal Ellipsis
Clausal Ellipsis
LEXICAL COHESIVE DEVICES
REITERATION
Repetition
Synonym
Superordinate and Hyponym
General Words
COLLOCATION
Opposites
Related Words
LEXICO-GRAMMATICAL COHESIVE DEVICES
CONNECTIVES
Additive Connectives
Adversative Connectives
Causal Connectives
Temporal Connectives
9- Unity
10- Completeness
11- Bibliography
Crystal, D. (2003). The Cambridge Encyclopaedia of the English Language.
Cambridge: CUP.
Crystal, D. (2004). Rediscover Grammar. London: Pearson Education.
Frydenberg, G. & Boardman, C.A. (1990). You're in Charge!: Writing to
Communicate. New York: Addison Wesley Publishing Company.
Halliday, M.A.K. (1994). An Introduction to Functional Grammar. London:
Edward Arnold Ltd.
Low, O. (1986). Proficiency in English Course. London: Edward Arnold Ltd.
Download