Pop Art: A Reactionary Realism Author(s): Donald B. Kuspit Source: Art Journal, Vol. 36, No. 1 (Autumn, 1976), pp. 31-38 Published by: College Art Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/776112 Accessed: 01-09-2015 02:03 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. College Art Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Art Journal. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Pop Art: Realism Reactionary A DONALDB. KUSPIT In parodythe implicationis the perverse,and I feel that in my own work I don't mean it to be that. BecauseI don't dislikethe work that I'm parodying.... The things that I have parodiedI actuallyadmire. - Roy Lichtenstein LawrenceAllowaywrites that "Pop art is neither abstract nor realistic, though it has contacts in both directions."' This article explores its contacts in the realistic direction, even taking it as a political articulation.Jean Cassou insists that "a realistic movement in art is always revolutionary."2This article shows, on the contrary, that insofar as Pop art is realistic, it is reactionary,and evades the social responsibility it at first glance seems to show. Cassou's remarkis based on the assumption that the main thrust of modern realism is the unmasking of reality to show its "ugly" truth, which is repressed in ordinary recognition. Realism is not simply "bound to a concrete situation at a given moment,"3 nor does it only intend to showthat, in Goethe's words, "no object of the broadest world and the most manifold life will be any longer excluded as unpoetical." Going beyond these superficialconditions, modern realismat its best causes us to re-cognize reality, denying its appearances any "fictional finality,"to use Alfred Adler's expression. Realism is not only directed towards true reality, and as such radical, but is directed against the idealism of much art, which mediates a presumed ultimate sense, and reinforces the resistance of consciousness to the real sense of things by giving them ideal meanings. (Realism is thus a debunking of the idealistic approach to art in general, which looks for absolute meanings in its appearances.) For revolutionary realism, no perception can become a metaphysical resting place; there is a perpetual transcending of the given in the name of its sense, which in the course of being disclosed loses its mysterious- ness and becomes the new reality. Modern realism involves a restless, relentless pursuit of the meaning of appearances: on face they are not so much faithfully reproduced-taken value-as charged with fresh import. They are grasped as physiognomies disclosing important social and personal truths, rather than simply cannily yet neutrally mirrored. In a sense, the attempt only to imitate reality, as if the question of its meaning was not part of its appearance or was settled, shows resistance to the truth about it, if not outright repression of that truth. Now any contemporary American attempt to tell the truth make appearances tell the truth about appearances-to about reality-seems handicapped from the beginning by the mass media attempt to control appearances, for the specific purposes of commerce and the more general goal of social control. It is as though Pop art knew that all appearances are corrupted by their possible media look: as though everything American was waiting, as it were, to make a guest ar.pearance on a media outlet, and become patently memorable.4 It is the lurking presence of this expectation-of suddenly becoming, simultaneously, newsworthy and glamorous (they seem reciprocal), and thus a celebrity-that had to be considered in any attempt to communicate an American content. The question is: how did Pop art come to grips with this fact in the life of appearances in America? Did it, in its well-known use of them in a way media images-of visual clich6s-transform which showed them up, indicating critical detachmentthe world that created them? mental independence-from The answer, I hope to show, is no. Pop art did not simply accept the media cliche image as a kind of lingua franca, the inevitable communication code of a business society. For all its supposed irony, Pop art endorsed and embraced these mass images for the American world they signified-the infinite reproducibility of the images suggested the inescapability and omnipresence of the world-thus putting an artistic 31 FALL 1976 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions stamp of approval on the American status quo. The only sense of parody, as Lichtensteinspoke of it in the quotation at the beginning of this article, arises from the fact that the pictorial slang of popular culture images should enter high art: Lichtenstein'sfeeling of parody is caused by this coming together of incommensurates, by his high-style treatment of low images (Fig. 1). Lichtenstein does not feel this parody is perverse, and he feels free to express his admirationfor his mass media American subject matter, because the possibility of "communion" between the worlds of high art and the mass media, which are usually thought of as having nothing to do with one another, if not intending to negate each other, is guaranteed by what Alloway has characterizedas the contemporary fine art/popular culture continuum.5 This continuum presupposes the existence of fine art and popular culture as "parallel" or, at least, alternative modes of communication of the same culture. As such, there is nothing forbidding transactions between them, even their interpenetration, for they emerge from and are expressive of the same matrixof ideas and events. In a sense, Pop art is based on the discovery that fine art and popular culture are free to emulate and even borrow outright from one another, not only in the name of greater over-all success of communication, and not only because they often have the same information content and point to their methods, but because underneath their apparent differences they are in the service of the same ideal of psycho-social control. They both exist as cultural "exhibitions"-mediums for making public-of the same ideology of control, based on assurances of the exclusive excellence of things American. Fine art and popular culture have the same underlying logic: they are superstructures simultaneously disguising the realworkings of the world they originate in-workings that show it is not the best of all possible worlds-and generating allegiance to it. They offer pseudorevelations of realitydesigned at once to please the individual sense of critical understanding of the given social order, and to promote group loyalty to it. Fromthis point of view, the boundaries between fine art and popular culture seem to blur; they seem aspects of a larger cultural "continuum." They cannot be qualitativelydifferentiated because their subtlety and efficacy are recognized as similar. In a sense, the discovery of their mutuality, and thus ability to assimilate each other, is a way of furthering this subtlety and efficacy: the use of the one by the other increases the influence of both. However, from the point of view of a revolutionaryrealism which would want to understand the full implications of the social order from which they both emerged, the fine art/ popular culture continuum is frustrating. It supplies readymade, one-dimensional media meanings, or labyrinthine, self-adumbratinghigh culture meanings, neither of which is clearly grounded in the social order which they both presuppose. The fine art/popular culture continuum does even more: it instills the idea of predictable, certified meanings, foreclosing any further investigation of the "truth." Such meanings have effect-take hold-just because they do not pretend to be true, only certain: they afford a sense of security, of the thoroughly known, which is a satisfactory substitute for the difficult truth. Such meanings, seemingly absolute, are socially approved, "ideal," because they form a clear ground for action; they are in effect a kind of propaganda, generating strong belief and foreclosing on intellectual curiosity and inquiry. Pop art, while it shares in the fine art/popular culture continuum, first makes itself apparentas a communication of media clich6 images ratherthan of fine art ideals. However, its use of the media clich6 image gives that image a spontaneous fine art-"higher"-meaning. The spectator, who initiallyviewed the media cliche image as telling a kind of truth about the real world or at least in some sense corresponding to it, finds that "truth" hypostatized, raised to seemingly absolute status, by Pop art's location of it in a fine art context. Pop art gilds an already gilded lily, seemingly making it sterling gold. Instead of enlightening the spectator by debunking the media clich6 image as an instance of false consciousness, Pop art gives it back to him writ large, with the sanctity of an art aura around it, as though it were an iconthe image over the altarpiece of a commercial society. This generates some shame and self-preservative amusement ("camp"), some minimum irony at one's own expense: it is strange to see everyday idols in a position of overt power, exhibited for "aesthetic" appreciationas well as information. But on the whole such exhibition causes no trouble, stirs no souls to their depths, except among the self-styled cognoscenti of the art world, the "purists" or aesthetes who still want an exclusive culture, not realizingthat their culture is as much a social disguise as popular culture, perhaps even more so. Fig. 1. Roy Lichtenstein, Blam, 1962. Privatecollection, New York. ART JOURNAL, XXXVI/1 32 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Thus, the spectator is thrown into society's arms by Pop art, where he was before, but now the embrace crushes and strangles; it cannot even be evaded mentally. The standardized, "media-ted" appearances of things are taken as truly significant because they have become art-significant: a standard, clich6 appearance is for all practical and theoretical purposes a true appearance. Pop realism thus unconsciously keeps the spectator from questioning media cliche images, as to either their motivation or construction. The unmediated reality they mask is overlooked, or not looked at closely enough; the media do not encourage the close look, but on the contrary are designed to discourage it by satisfying, to the point of satiation, any looking the spectator might want to do. If the spectator has a quasi-realistic urge to establish continuity between the media cliche image and unmediated actuality, he is usually only attempting to "justify" the media cliche image by showing it to be imitative of reality-or rather, showing unmediated actuality to be imitative of it. For Pop art encourages him to view the media cliche image as a kind of dream realization or self-fulfilling prophecy about the actual, given world: the way it looks on the media is the way it was meant to look, for that is the way it truly is. Pop art in effect encourages the assumption that the world as known through the mass media fatalistically confirms the actual world. The media seem to say: this is the world, make the best of it, for it cannot be changed, since it has already happened. It can only be made newsworthy and glamorousonly celebrated, for better or worse. In Pop art this celebration of the inevitable is itself celebrated. As Lichtenstein writes, The world is outside. Pop art looks at it and accepts this environment, which is neither good nor bad ... and if you ask me how one can love moronization, how one can love the mechanization of work, how one can love bad art, I answer: I see it, it's here, it's the world.6 In Pop art "fine art" functions initially as the meta-medium confirming the "fateful truth"-the unavoidable givenness of the world-implicitly communicated by media images. But Pop art mediates these already mediated images-mediates the given world once more-so that they and the given world seem not only the case, for better or worse, but potentially tragic or comic. The media images and the world they reflect are made to seem not simply inevitable, but dramatically inevitable, because they are lifted onto the plane of art, with its "great expectations." The "art" of Pop art is a deus ex machina descending to the stage of the given world, already self-consciously reflected in its media, already communicating its reality to itself through the distorting mirrors of its media. The "art" not only takes the fatal vanity of the world as self-reflected or mediated for granted, but dramatizes it. Approved by art, the cliche state of affairs seems a preordained, ultimate situation; and the media cliche images, brought into the higher world of art and given "style," seem magnificent, or fraught with meaning, unexpectedly profound. They, in fact, seem to keep the real world running. As Karl Kraus wrote, happenings no longer happen; instead, the cliches operate spontaneously. Or, if things should nevertheless happen without being frightened off by the cliches, these happenings will stop when the cliches have been smashed. A rot has set in, and the cliche has started it.7 Pop art, which seems to function Dramatized-staged-by like a theodicy, the clich6 acquires a transcendental aura, confirming the stability of the world it mediates. This world is also implicitly idealized by art; the cliche becomes its halo. So idealized by Pop art, it becomes frozen in its cliche image, denying it the possibility of process; on the contrary, its image implies that it ought to remain the same, so that it can be transcendentally significant and "beautiful." Supplied by Pop art with a pair of art-wings, the media image of the American world seems its true revelation, its final codification, its set form. Art-mediation does not only not essentially change the media cliche image, but affords no deeper understanding of the world it mediates. This is why Pop art is reactionary: it celebrates, by fetishizing, American society's self-image in its media; this self-image cannot be thought about further, for it has been made glamorous-its appearance is given the illusion of being a fine art. The fine art of Pop appearances does no more than crystallize the world they mediate as a finished product. Pop art thus furthers what Adorno calls "the standardization of consciousness" by society-its attempt to master our inner life for its own purposes.8 It may be, as Alloway says van Gogh believed, that clich6s (visual or otherwise)-the instrument of the standardization of consciousness as well as the form and content of such false consciousness-are "the authorized expression of mankind, a kind of common property that especially binds us together." But they are also controlled thoughts, or modes of thought control-stereotyped ways of viewing reality, and as such false to its process. They inhibit our penetration of social and personal reality, and repress our re-cognition of it. They restrict our search for its meaning to prescribed paths, and deny us any critical insight into its purposes. A key statement, valuable for an understanding of the workings of Pop art, and showing it to share in the propaganda purposes of the media, is Allan Kaprow's assertion that "publicity can in its own way create an equally magnificent image of a Buick as the Church once created an image of God." "Publicity" is the method of methods for Pop art. Picturing a thing for the purpose of publicizing it is to fetishize it into a "magnificent image" worthy of worship. It is to create an iconic image: Pop art takes images with wide circulation-and thus so familiar they seem commonplace-and fetishizes them into icons by placing them in an art context.9 Art seems thereby to mock itself, but it is actually fulfilling a traditional purpose: the "idealization" of the actual into an absolute so that it seems memorable (venerable and valuable). The fact that the actuality used by Pop art is standardized seems to imply that singling it out and raising it up for special attention is ironic. But this element of parody, noted by Lichtenstein, is superficial. A parody is critical of its subject matter; Lichtenstein is not critical of his American content, but admires it. His sense of parody seems a defense against a hidden envy of the well-publicized character of his American content, which gives it a "hold" over its consumers that Lichtenstein would like his art to have. He in effect appropriates this hold by using an American content, with its easy familiarity and its everyday desirability. He thus puts one FALL 1976 33 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions on the same easy, unthinking terms with his art as one is with the everyday American content, which seems paradoxical (this is what Lichtenstein in fact means by "parody") because one expects to approach art with uneasy awe, as though one were in the presence of something with self-evident authority. But of course art does not have any self-evident authority, whereas the American content does; Pop art uses it because we are already convinced of its "value." In effect, Pop art wants the same hold-instant and superficial, yet bindingon its spectators as well-advertised American subject matter wants on its consumers, and in part for the same purpose: to sell itself. As Adorno notes, The well-remarkedshowmanship of the new artists, their exhibitionism, is in fact the gesture by means of which they bring themselves as commodities to the market.10 By using the same publicity methods as advertising, and by using a publicized American content-by publicizing the alart assures itself of a hold on the ready publicized-Pop American public, for its audience is potentially everyone who wittingly or unwittingly attends to advertising and publicity, rather than simply a few aesthetes and purist art cognoscenti. Pop art's exhibitionism consists in its obvious Americanism, and it becomes obviously American in the name of commercial success: in the 1960s it still seemed as if America "spontaneously" sold. Pop art is art as a hard sell; its essential technique is idealizing a visual clich6 into a luxury product, which "sells" both because it is already well known and because it has art-status. This combined hold, of the takenfor-granted or commonplace (an unconscious hold) and the elite-superior (a conscious hold), is almost overwhelming in its irresistibility, as many critics have discovered.11 This hold serves propaganda purposes, both for society and art. Jacques Ellul describes "the aim of modern propaganda" as no longer to modify ideas, but to provoke action. It is no longer to change adherence to a doctrine, but to make the individual cling irrationallyto a process of action. It is no longer to lead to a choice, but to loosen the reflexes. It is no longer to transforman opinion, but to arouse an active and mythicalbelief.12 "Propaganda ceases," writes Ellul, "where simple dialogue begins"; Pop art, while it may be a system of communication plugged into a larger system, is not dialogue. (One cannot have dialogue with works of Pop art, or rather enter into the dialogue between their form and content, because, as many articles have noted, their formal transformation of their content is minimal, or at least predictable in terms of the media character of that content.) Now, much as advertising wants to "loosen the reflexes" so that the consumer will respond, ideally in Pavlovian fashion, to the publicized products, so Pop art loosens the reflexes of the spectator so that he will take to the picture (the art product) without resistancebefore his critical awareness begins to function. In both cases the attempt is to get a hold on the consumer before he can re-cognize the product. That is, the attempt is to sell the product before its character can be carefully questioned. The attempt is to avoid critical conflict by creating an "active and mythical belief" in the product. Both advertising and Pop art prey on the individual weakness for "easy solutions," caused by his vulnerability. In this sense, both are profoundly propagandistic. As Ellul says And the individual does not want information, but only value judgments and preconceived positions. Here one must also take into account the individual'slaziness, which plays a decisive role in the entire propagandaphenomenon, and the impossibilityof transmittingall informationfast enough to keep up with developments in the modern world. Besides, the developments are not merely beyond man's intellectualscope; they are beyond him in volume and intensity. ... Faced with such matters, he feels his weakness, his inconsistency, his lackof effectiveness. He realizes that he depends on decisions over which he has no control, and that realization drives him to despair. Man cannot stay in this situationtoo long. He needs an ideological veil to cover the harsh reality,some consolation, a raison d'etre, a sense of values. And only propagandaoffers him a remedy for a basically intolerable situation. Succinctly put: "to furnish the collective ideological motivations driving man to action is propaganda's exact task." It seems, in such a situation, that "critical realism" is impossible. Yet existentially, on the level of individual existencepotentially the level of dialogue-it is necessary for survival, and it first makes itself apparent as personal sceptical opposition to collective ideology, and its instrument of fetishization. Against the inscrutability that is created by fetishization-against the unenlightened attitude generated by advertising and Pop art-a critical attitude arises in the very process of consumption of ordinary and art products. Against the fetishized dailiness-in Heidegger's sense of the termof these products, anxious doubt becomes the weapon of psychic freedom. Publicity, as a propaganda factor, creates false idols, images meant to be worthy of worship because they can make life magically meaningful. So long as these images remain true believer feels idolized-effectively ideological-their imbued with their magnificence. However, the moment faith is disturbed, and the image seems to lose its magnificence, because it no longer seems to make life meaningful, its ideological power collapses. Why should it ever be shaken? How does the true believer come to doubt its magical efficacy, its special truthfulness? Simply by consuming what it signifies. For the actual experience of what the image signifies is ordinary, contradicting the image's magnificence. Awareness of the discrepancy between the two is the beginning of doubt of the image. Much as bread and wine are not in fact the body and blood of Christ, so first-hand, actual experience of what the image signifies strips it of its implications-of its magnificence. The belief that there is still significant correlation between the image and what it represents is purely mythical, the vestige of an ideological hold. Pop art, as noted, depends heavily on this hold, but its power collapses the moment one realizes, by personal re-cognition-by diabanality of what these images logue with its images-the still One may represent. give allegiance to it for the sake of its "art"-for the fineness of art-but one can no longer give allegiance to the world it implies. Similarly, in realizing the ordinariness of the products one consumes, their advertised appearance loses its hold, although one may still abstractly admire the prowess of advertising techniques. The ordinariART JOURNAL, XXXVI/1 34 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ness of experience, with its true discoveries about the advertised reality, undermines the magnificence of the publicized look, showing it to be an ideological facade on a commonplace reality. In nuce, the image debunks itself in the very process of its consumption, for the logic of the process demands that what it represents also be consumed, immediately giving rise to awareness of the difference between the magnificent image and the experienced reality. Public and private separate, the one becoming abstractand ideological, the other becoming painfully concrete and sceptically personal. An ironical relationship exists between the image and the reality, art and experience, ideology and actuality, but this has nothing to do with the parodythe Pop artist imagines he feels when he draws his magic circle of art around the already artful media cliche image. Pop art, like advertising, is ultimately indifferent to the realityit enshrines in a magnificent image. A full awareness of this reality, with all its implications and relations, would interfere with the process of publicizing it, which involves only minimumdisclosure of realityand maximumcelebration of its appearance. Pop art thus deals in illusions, and the Pop artist is essentially a publicity agent for already familiarillusions-illusions which seem about to dissipate, but by their art codification gain renewed vigor. Transformedfrom transitory appearances into quasi-permanent icons, Pop art shows them in full ideological war-paint, on the psychic make. In a sense, the Pop artist is simply a superior craftsman-a grandercommercial artist-refining an accepted content into superior significance, but with no understandingof its actual significance. Advertising presupposes ignorance and inexperience; it is most successful with the uncriticalbeliever. As has been said, good advertising can sell anything-but only to those who accept things at face value, and thus who can hardlycomprehend what it means to search out the truth about things. The magnificent images created by advertising, art, and the Church are designed to create in the consumer, spectator, and believer, false consciousness of the reality signified by the image-a consciousness which is reconciled to it before it knows what it is. Advertising turns things into signs of themselves, and then adumbrates these signs so that they seem attractive, suggesting the ideal. Pop art adumbrates these signs further, into absoluteness, giving them the transcendence and sanctityof art, makingthem objects of lasting ratherthan momentary belief-giving them an "eternal present." The Church connects these absolutized signs-signs with the halo of art around them-to an absolute object, confirming their divinity. The Church is an institution confirming the "validity"-giving "ontological necessity"-to artfully conceived reality. Advertising validates, or "institutionalizes," commodities, Pop art validates advertising, and the Churchvalidates Pop art. As Kaprowsuggests, the proper name of the Church is capitalism;Pop art confirms its look, it confirms Pop art's commodity value. The tautologous relation established between advertising, Pop art, and capitalism is at the core of Pop art's hitherto unqualified success. Adorno writes: Wellthen, so the workof artis derivedfromthe fetish-are the artiststo blameif they relateto theirproductsa littlefetishistically?'3 Adorno has in mind Marx'stheory of the fetish character of commodities; the work of art is, from an economic point of Fig. 2. Tom Wesselmann, Bathtub Nude Number3, 1963. Cologne, Wollraf-RichartzMuseum, Collection of Peter Ludwig. FALL 1976 35 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Fig. 3. James Rosenquist, Lanai, 1964. Privatecollection, New York. view, another commodity, and as such subject to fetishism. As Marx writes, I i AmovII In the mist-enveloped regions of the religious world ... the productions of the human brain appear as independent beings endowed with life, and entering into relation both with one another and the human race. So it is in the world of commodities with the products of men's hands. This I call the Fetishismwhich attaches itself to the products of labor, so soon as they are produced as commodities, and which is therefore inseparable from the production of commodities.14 Pop works of art share-to a fault, as I have shown-this general characteristic of all commodities, as well as of all religiously conceived productions. But the fetishistic character of Pop works of art goes even deeper-into the narcissistic depths implied by Adorno's wry observation. From an anthropological point of view, the fetish is an object believed to have sacred power, as such enjoying a privileged social position, and treated with special respect. Pop art cashes in on the dignity given to ordinary phenomena by their mediation; the controlled attention and look they get on the media seemingly stylizes them. Pop art raises this dignity to the nth power by giving it the dignity of an art context. Simultaneously, it enhances the dignity of the art medium by appropriating for it the privileged, respected (simply by reason of the attention they are given)- in a word, fetishized - phenomena of the mass media. In general, the anthropological conception of fetishism confirms the economic and religious conceptions. The sexological point of view adds the conception of a fetish as an object by means of which the lover's attention is diverted from the central focus of sexual attractionto ... the peripheryof that focus, or is even outside it altogether, though recalling it by association of contiguity or of similarity.15 Sexual fetishization, in other words, gives an erotic charge to a non-erotic object. Sexual fetishization by contiguity is an almost standard device in Rosenquist's associations, and by similarity in Oldenburg's visual punning.'6 Pop art's typical- Fig. 4. Claes Oldenburg,DormeyerMixer,notebook drawing, 1965. if disguised or latent-erotic character is explicit in Wesselmann's streamlining of the female body itself into a sexual fetish object, replacing it as a "central focus of sexual attraction" with diffuse attention to its form. That is, Wesselmann deconcretizes the female body, making it into an abstract form rather than a realized substance (Fig. 2). It is generalized into a glamorous object, despite the exaggerated, superficially physical specificity Wesselmann often gives breasts (especially nipples) and pudendum. These seem central by reason of their exaggeration, yet this same exaggeration makes them comical and unapproachable, if not repulsive. Wesselmann destroys them as sites of feeling, and recreates them as freakish, grotesque phenomena, in no way contradicting his general grotesque objectification of the female body, on a calendar art model. In general, Wesselmann's ART JOURNAL, XXXVI/1 36 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions detailing of the female sexual object is pseudo-sensational. It seems to exist more to contradict, with an ironical touch of quasi-raw sexual reality, the advertised slick image of the female nude which is Wesselmann's point of departure, than to enhance the nude's allurewith some "excited" imagery. But more to the point is the sexual fetishization, also originating in publicity for form rather than substance, of such non-sexual objects as the automobile (Fig. 3). Until recently one of the prizes in the American game, it was worthy of erotic desire, for embracing it was in effect embracing the American dream. Oldenburg was obsessed with the airflow Chryslerbecause its stream-line gave it an erotic look, implicitly evoking the female form. The automobile is openly glamorized in Rosenquist'sSilverSkies (1962),but this is only to advertise it as it has always been advertised.17One last point about the sexual fetishization of non-sexual ob- jects: Oldenburg's food images seem to me a more daring example of sexual fetishization than any use of the automobile, as does the softness and giganticism of many of his objects. He, in effect, demonstrates that anything consumable becomes susceptible to sexual fetishization, for it becomes a gross object of appetite which calls for a "consuming" relation with itself (Fig. 4). In general, Pop art reflects the fact that in capitalist society publicity attempts to create a consuming relation with commodities, and tends to view every reality as a commodity. Thus, one is supposed not only to be consumed by publicized reality, but to experience it strictlyobjectively, with the exaggerated objectivity created by fetishism. This objectivity is reflected in the presumably"cool" look of Pop art. Such a look is the proper accompaniment to the apathy, the state of feelinglessness, that underlies Pop art, having to do with its Fig. 5. Andy Warhol, LavenderDisaster, 1964. Privatecollection, Greenwich, Connecticut. 37 FALL 1976 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ultimately bland acceptance of the American reality and advertising modes of experience and ideals. This is reflected perhaps most explicitly in Warhol's "classicizing" of cliches through seriality, creating a blank wall of monotony preventing any penetration to the reality signified. Warhol, simply by them ad nauseam and arbimanipulating signs-repeating trarily-makes us immune to their particular meaning and indifferent to their larger import, to the context of events and ideas from which they emerge (Fig. 5). Warhol enforcespolices-our moronization, rather than leading us out of it, and thus shows a peculiarly technological kind of fascism. As Clement Greenberg and Dwight Macdonald said, fascism is a combination of technological methods and socially reactionary attitudes.18 Warhol's mass production of cliches for an art purpose perfectly exemplifies both. Lichtenstein's art-"organized perception" in no way redeems the neutrality of Pop art in general, for as Lenin said, there is no such thing as neutrality, which is the ideology of reactionaries sure of their power and unconscious of its effect. Pop art shared in the power of the moronic, mechanical world Lichtenstein noticed was "here," worshipped the bitch goddess of success William James said was the American deity-worshipped her at a time she seemed secure. Pop art was thus part of that "organization of optimism"19 so essential to consumer capitalist society, and had nothing to do with the derision of that society socialists imagined they saw in it.20 U 1 Lawrence Alloway, American Pop Art, New York, 1974, p. 7. All further quotations from Allowayare from this source, unless otherwise noted. 2 Jean Cassou, "Artand Confrontation,"Artand Confrontation,Greenwich, Conn., 1970, p. 18. 3 Linda Nochlin, Realism, Baltimore, 1971, p. 33. Alloway's definition of realism, designed to distinguish it from Pop art-which is "about signs and sign-systems"-conceives it as "concerned with the artist's perception of objects in space and their translation into iconic, or faithful, signs." Like Nochlin's definition, this one also ignores the revolutionary and critical motivationof realism-its preoccupation with ideological issues-and takes it as essentially descriptive in purpose. 4 Warhol'sview that we are entitled to fifteen minutes of media fame exploits this expectation. 5 Lawrence Alloway, "Network:The Art World Described as A System," Artforum,Sept. 1972, p. 28. 6 Quoted by Aldo Pellegrini,New Tendencies in Art, New York, 1966, p. 227. See also John Coplans (ed.), Roy Lichtenstein, New York,1972, pp. 52-53. 7 Quoted Ernst Fischer, Art by Against Ideology, New York, 1970, p. 118. 8 Theodor W. Adorno, MinimaMoralia, Frankfurt/Main, 1964, p. 298. 9 Nicolas Calas, "Pop Icons," Pop Art, New York, 1966, p. 170. '1 Adorno, p. 287. 1 As Lucy Lippard,"New YorkPop," Pop Art, pp. 82-83 notes, the common complaint against Pop art was that it was too vulgarlyself-evident, and as such perversely attractive. One knew the subject matter before one fully experienced the work, and the subject matter predisposed one to take the work in a set way. 12Jacques Ellul, Propaganda, New York, 1965, p. 25. All subsequent quotations by Ellul are from this source. 13 Adorno, p. 284. 14 KarlMarx,Capital, Chicago, 1933, vol. I, p. 83. 15 Havelock Ellis, Erotic Symbolism, Philadelphia, 1920, p. 1. 16 There is no absolute consistency to Rosenquist's associations, but his poster for his retrospective at the National Galleryof Canada (1968) seems particularlytelling. The poster superimposes a rose on spaghetti, combining the romance and the reality of American life-both cliches to the point of idyllicism. But the combination is also of vaginal and phallic symbols-in a sense, of the simultaneityof the poetic and prosaic in sex. Classic examples of Oldenburg's visual punning are his ray-guns, which resemble penis and testicles, and his conversion of a Dormeyer Mixer into pendulous breasts, and then into penis and testicles. Itcan be argued that Oldenburghas moved from sexual to bisexual imagery, in which a work is no longer hard or soft, but softly hard and hardilysoft. 17 Other key works are Rosenquist's Lanai (1964) and U-Haul-It(1967). An unglamorous, openly sexual automobile appears in Kienholz's Back Seat Dodge-38 (1964). Ingeneral, much early Pop imageryinvolvesexplicit as well as impliciteroticism. 18 Clement Greenbergand DwightMacdonald,"10 Propositions on the War," Partisan Review, 8, 1941, p. 271. 19 Fischer, p. 160. 20 E.g., MichelRagon, "TheArtistand Society," Artand Confrontation,p. 31. Donald B. Kuspit is Professor of Art at the Universityof North Carolina at Chapel Hill. He is in the process of completing a book on contemporary Americanart criticism. ART JOURNAL, 38 This content downloaded from 129.78.139.28 on Tue, 01 Sep 2015 02:03:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions XXXVI/1