Landscape Research ISSN: 0142-6397 (Print) 1469-9710 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/clar20 Can a landscape be a work of art?: an examination of Sir Geoffrey Jellicoe's theory of aesthetics. Ian Thompson To cite this article: Ian Thompson (1995) Can a landscape be a work of art?: an examination of Sir Geoffrey Jellicoe's theory of aesthetics., Landscape Research, 20:2, 59-67, DOI: 10.1080/01426399508706457 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/01426399508706457 Published online: 24 Feb 2007. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 112 View related articles Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=clar20 Can a Landscape be a Work of Art?: an examination of Sir Geoffrey Jellicoe's theory of aesthetics. Ian Thompson Introduction In a profile of Sir Geoffrey Jellicoe, written for the Royal Academy Magazine, Rowan Abstract Moore suggests that virtually alone he has "resurrected landscape design as a serious The article focuses on the art form, as something to be treated on a par with painting" (Moore, 1993). He has theory of landscape design done this not just through his design commissions but also through his writing in put forward by Sir which he puts forward a theory of landscape design. Many admirers of Jellicoe's Geoffrey Jellicoe. Central designs, including many practising landscape architects, confess that they do not to this is the extent to understand his theories. What follows is not intended to be another critical which a designed commentary on Jellicoe's oeuvre. Its focus is narrower, in that it attempts to summarise landscape can be Jellicoe's main ideas and to subject them to a philosophical examination. Does what considered a 'work of art'. Jellicoe has to say make sense? How do his ideas relate to other theories in philosophical Jellicoe makes connections aesthetics? Do they mean that we should be practising landscape architecture in a between landscape design particular way? and the projection of the psyche into its natural Jellicoe's main contention is that landscape architecture is, or can be, a form of art. In order to justify this he must offer an aesthetic theory which explains what art is. environment, and thus it The particular theory he elaborates can be classified as a communication theory of art seems appropriate to relate and, as such, resembles the theory offered by Tolstoy at the end of the nineteenth his exploration of the century and is open to similar criticisms. Similarities may also be found with some subconscious to Jung's of the ideas propounded by the American philosopher, Susanne Langer in her 'psychological system'. influential book Feeling and Form (1953), for as we will see, Langer is much concerned The theories of Tolstoy with the issue of how an art object can be said to embody or express feeling and, like and Langer are also used Jellicoe, emphasises the symbolic function of the art work, but her theory avoids some as critical reference points for the analysis of of the pitfalls of the crude communications theory approach. There is not the space in a single paper to consider every aesthetic theory ever Jellicoe's theories. proposed. I have chosen to focus upon the theories of Tolstoy and Langer because Although Jellicoe's theories they seem to offer the best vehicles for an examination of the strengths and weaknesses appear to be flawed, it is of Jellicoe's ideas.1 In the penultimate section, however, I shall argue that all attempts concluded that he is right to define art in terms of the necessary conditions for its existence or creation are to maintain that landscape architecture can produce misguided. works of art, and that his limitations as a Jellicoe's Theory Jellicoe has never written a full and direct treatise upon his theory of landscape design. philosopher do not We have instead the three volumes of his Studies in Landscape Design (1956, 1966,diminish his design 1970) which collect together papers based upon various lectures and addresses given achievements. in the course of his career. The Guelph Lectures on Landscape Design (1983) provide another important source. Jellicoe's ideas are woven through these studies as The author is a lecturer in incomplete threads. Part of my purpose is to see whether these can be woven together the Department of Town to form a rope sufficiently strong to haul landscape architecture alongside the and Country Planning, recognised fine arts. University of NewcastleThe first point to make about Jellicoe is that he is concerned with meaning rather upon-Tyne than mere beautification. In Landscape from Art, a speech given to the Institute of Contemporary Arts in 1961 and reproduced in Studies in Landscape Design Volume II (1966) he writes "We have in this country at last reached a point when seemliness Keywords as an objective is no longer enough; we can and should make landscape as meaningful communication theory as painting" (p.l). What is it then that most painting possesses but much landscape modernism design lacks? Jungian symbolism Jellicoe's answer is bound up with his Modernism, which owes more to artists like Tolstoy Hepworth and Nicholson than to architects like Gropius or Corbusier. He is less Langer Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 59 concerned with functionalism than with the exploration of the subconscious, as a later passage from the same essay reveals. Talking about modern art he says that "the literary or intellectual meaning of a picture as seen photographically by the eye was subdued and even eliminated in order that the instincts should predominate. This is the basis of abstract art" (pp 3-4). What then are these instincts? Jellicoe's answer is not very clear. He suggests that: "The arts are preoccupied firstly with the new dimension of time and space that has been with us from the start of the century, and secondly with our own primitive origins in relation to these dimensions" (p 4). Subsequently, in the Introduction to his Guelph Lectures on Landscape Design (1983) he suggests that landscape design is "a projection of the psyche into its natural environment" and he provides a model of the way the mind is organised which is related to stages in human evolution. Jellicoe suggests that the psyche has levels, which he calls "transparencies", an analogy which suggests that the earlier and deeper levels are not entirely hidden by the shallower and more recent ones. Our emotional responses to landscape can be accounted for by our evolutionary history as a species. Hence, at the "scarcely perceptible" primaeval level there is Rock and Water, "without a known influence on the psychology of the present day". A positivist would surely protest that if this level is undetectable and without effects, it is no more than an imaginative elaboration. Above this is the transparency that Jellicoe calls the Forester, which is identified with the time that our ancestors spent in the sub-tropical forest and which accounts for all that is sensuous and tactile in our appreciation of landscape, including our love of flowers. Next is the level he calls the Hunter, which was formed on the African savannah and accounts for our liking of the sort of parkland created by "Capability" Brown. This element of his theory seems to have been taken directly from the Savannah Hypothesis propounded by Gordon Orians. On top of this we find the Settler, which represents our transition to an agricultural existence and accounts for our love of mathematical order. A formal garden like Versailles appeals to our instincts at this level. The Forester, Hunter and Settler are all straightforward enough and seem to make sense intuitively. The fifth level, which according to Jellicoe is a contemporary addition, is more problematic. He calls it the Voyager and suggests that mankind is currently on a journey of discovery, but he is thinking not of an outward journey, but of the kind of inward exploration begun by Freud and taken further and deeper, some would say, by Jung. Surely if this is a journey into the unconscious mind, it is going to involve a descent through all previous levels, right down to Rock and Water? Jellicoe's metaphors seem mixed here, for how can a level or a "transparency" also be a journey? Jellicoe and Jung It is never very clear what Jellicoe expects to find in the subconscious, and this is not perhaps very surprising. After all, the delvings of Freud and Jung seemed to produce very different subconscious contents. It is clear from Jellicoe's references to "analytical psychology" (a term coined by Jung and distinct from psycho-analysis) that he believes in Jung's idea of the "subjective unconscious", a storehouse of primitive symbols common to all humanity. In The Landscape of Symbols, in Studies in Landscape Design 111(19 70), Jellicoe discusses the history of the cross, the circle and the spire, admitting in a footnote his debt to Jung's Man and his Symbols (1964). It is not clear how the transparencies are supposed to relate to Jungian concepts; Jellicoe seems to imply that we must make a journey down through the levels of our mind, but just what we are supposed to find at the level Rock and Water, if this is our ultimate goal, is unclear. We might expect some of the symbols identified by Jung to have found their way into Jellicoe's designs. The publication of Michael Spens' The Complete Landscape 60 Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 Designs and Gardens of Geoffrey Jellicoe (Spens, 1994) makes it very easy to look for them. Spens divides Jellicoe's work into three periods. In the early period, 192 7-1960, we find a mixture of Neo-classicism and Modernism, but we also find the emergence of animal forms, which in the Jungian interpretation of dreams are said to represent aspects of the self. The "prehistoric animal form beneath" the hills in Jellicoe's scheme for the Cadbury's factory at Moreton, Cheshire (1954) and the serpent-like shape of the lake at Hemel Hempstead, Hertfordshire (1957-59) could therefore be classed as Jungian. In the second phase, from 1960-1980, we have the hills at the Rutherford High Energy Laboratories, Harwell, Berkshire (1960) which Jellicoe refers to as "a frolic into the expression of a deep-rooted and sinister idea" (Spens, 1994, p 86). The frolic consisted of naming the hills after the Greek gods, Zeus, Themis and Klotho. Jellicoe believes that in doing this he was playing upon the subconscious emotions through association of ideas, but it is surely not much more than a shallow labelling. We also have from this period the Kennedy Memorial at Runnymede (1964-65), where the allegory is derived from Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress, which conceivably is open to a Jungian interpretation. Jellicoe refers to a "journey of life, death and the spirit". However, considering that this is the period during which Jellicoe published the three volumes of Studies in Landscape Design and during which he was working out his philosophy of design, the evidence of successfully implemented Jungian landscapes appears rather thin. The evidence is stronger in the late period, which Spens calls the Full Flowering or Master Period (from 1980). We find it in particular in the designs produced for Stanley Seeger at Sutton Place, Surrey. Here Jellicoe found a wealthy client who would support his artistic vision and he was able to create a grand allegory of "creation, life and aspiration." Jellicoe explains the symbolism at work at Sutton Place thus: "Behind each part with its seductive delights lurks an idea that reflects, or is intended to reflect, either a lighter or a darker mood of the subconscious. Some of these ideas may seem self-revealing. Thus Pluto's grotto is recognisably a return to Greek myth, yet the subconscious appeal is not the myth itself, but the direct analogy with man's place in the cosmos. Similarly, all can see that the lake is in the shape of a fish, but few that the hills around are composed as the man. woman, child complex immemorial in art; and that the whole concept - water into hills into sculpture - is an analogy of the emergence of civilisation" (Spens, 1994, pp 162-63). At the same time as Jellicoe was working on Sutton Place he produced designs for public parks in Moderna and Brescia in Italy, neither of which have been implemented. At Moderna Jellicoe attempted to integrate landscapes based upon his "transparencies", while at Brescia the fish motif appears again in the design of a series of lakes. However, the capping achievement of Jellicoe's long career will be the Moody Gardens, which are currently under construction at Galveston, Texas. Spens writes: "Jellicoe was conscious of the fact that, while at Moderna he was dealing with the collective subconscious (in Jungian terms), while at Sutton Place he was concerned with reaching for the individual subconscious. Now at Galveston he found it possible to link the two Jungian concepts together in striving to express the ultimate unity of man's existence" (Spens, 1994, pp 183). There are many aspects of Jung's psychological system which do not appear in Jellicoe's work. I have found, for example, no reference to the anima or the animus, or to archetypes like the Shadow, the Magician, the Great Mother, or the Wise Old Man (Jung, 1953, pp 90-113). Jellicoe does, however, emphasise the intuitive and mysterious side of the design process and, at the very least, shares Jung's respectful, even reverential, attitude towards symbolism and its place in human life. There is perhaps something of the Emperor's New Clothes in the critical acclaim Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 61 poured upon the designs of Jellicoe's late flowering. Jungian symbolism is an openended bucket, out of which just about anything can be produced. Jung's ideas are sufficiently woolly and mystical that they can be used to support any kind of symbol or allegory. Commentators seem to accept everything Jellicoe has to say about his work as true. No doubt we can find enough plausibly Jungian symbols to support Jellicoe's identification with the psychologist's ideas, but the real question is not whether or not Sir Geoffrey is a good Jungian. On that let us take him at his word. The question is whether the rest of us must be, if we are to produce landscapes that are worthy of the name of art. In Landscape From Art this seems to be exactly what he is suggesting. We might feel justified in asking why this Jungian subject matter should be so important to landscape design? Jellicoe's answer comes in Towards a Landscape of Humanism where he writes: "It would seem that to project into the environment the whole and not merely part of the mind of man, individual or collective, is the highest objective in the creation of landscape as an art." (Jellicoe, 1984). And if we need to be convinced that this is important Jellicoe writes elsewhere that: "the effect upon human beings is the ultimate objective of all landscape design, whether rural or urban. To obtain this impact we have already established that it is necessary to have subconscious as well as conscious appeal" (Jellicoe, 1966, p 7). In The "Movement" Movement in Art and Landscape (Jellicoe, 1973) we find the further thought that this effect on human beings is to be therapeutic. It reconciles the unchanging tempo of our bodies to the increasing tempo of modern life. For landscape design to achieve this, the rational design process must be accompanied by a shadowy process which taps the subconscious. This is how it works in all art, not just in landscape design that aspires to be art. The artist must somehow penetrate his or her own consciousness, then the results of this exploration must somehow be represented in the work in such a way that they can be communicated to an audience. The distinction between the individual unconscious and the collective unconscious need not detain us. In some cases, the artist will attempt to communicate something from his or her personal unconscious. At other times, the artist will succeed in reaching the deep substratum which Jung believed human beings held in common, in which case the recipient of the communication may recognise something already known at the deepest level. A Necessary Condition Jellicoe does not merely suggest that sometimes when landscape design achieves the status of art, such communication of subconscious contents occurs. It is clear that Jellicoe thinks that in successful art it must always occur; in other words he regards such communication as a necessary condition for making landscape designs that are to be considered as art. It is less clear whether he is saying that the occurrence of such a process provides a sufficient condition. Is it possible for an artist or a designer to effect such a communication and yet fail to make a work of art? Jellicoe is not very rigorous about the way he uses the term. Sometimes he seems to be using it in a classificatory way (dividing artworks from other objects), in which case there can be such a thing as bad or poor art; often, however, he uses art as a term of approbation - if something is art it is good, in which case the idea of bad art is self-contradictory. He does not seem to have considered the possibility that a piece of landscape design may communicate something from the subconscious, thereby (according his own theory) qualifying as a work of art, yet still be poor or indifferent. I am in sympathy with Jellicoe's wish to see landscape architecture included in the pantheon of the arts, but in seeking to justify its inclusion by reference to a 62 Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 communications theory of art, he has simultaneously produced a very restricted notion of what art may be. Jellicoe and Tolstoy As I have suggested, there is a strong parallel between Jellicoe's theory and that advanced by Leo Tolstoy in his book What Is Art? (Tolstoy, 1930). Tolstoy's answer was that an object was a work of art if and only if (i.e. a necessary condition) it caused its audience to experience feelings it was intended to by its creator, and its creator had personally lived through the experiences so aroused. In Jellicoe's case what is transmitted is not emotion but some message from the collective unconscious. The first problem with Tolstoy's theory is that there seem to be many works of art which do not seem to embody strong feelings, for example elegant sonnets or meticulously constructed chamber music. Tolstoy would have to say that these could not be considered works of art. If some of Jellicoe's statements are taken at face value, he seems to be regulating landscape architecture in a parallel way. If a design does not tap into the subconscious, we should not call it art. At the time Tolstoy put forward his theory he was a fervent Christian. He supplemented his theory with a second necessary condition; not only must works of art communicate emotions, these emotions have to be worthwhile ones which promote the brotherhood of man. Pride, sexual desire and world weariness will not do. If we were to accept Tolstoy's theory, many of the paintings in the world's galleries would have to be removed from the walls. Giving this sort of weight to the subject matter of art is dangerous; something similar actually happened in Soviet Russia but with a different ideological justification. Geoffrey Jellicoe's humanist ideals are, of course, very far removed from Tolstoy's fundamentalist dogmatism, but the form of his mistake is the same. Jung's theory of the collective unconscious may be a rich and illuminating idea, but for Jellicoe to make it the sole yardstick against which landscape architecture is judged as art is surely wrong; there will be some landscape design which we want to call art, but which has nothing whatsoever to do with Jung, the unconscious, archetypes or whatever. Moreover, Jellicoe's theory about communication from the unconscious is untestable. Even if landscape architecture really can communicate in this way, how can we know that the communication is reliable? If we were listening to a radio transmission we could check it against the script, but what is the equivalent of the script here? Jellicoe says that people who visit landscapes created in his particular way will come to realise a few days later that they have been in the presence of something altogether deeper than they realised at the time. But how can they know that something has been communicated} It is safer surely to explain this phenomenon as a simple causal relationship between the visit and the subsequent thoughts and feelings. I do not wish to suggest that Jellicoe is wrong to believe in the subconscious, nor even to adhere to the Jungian version. I do not even think he is wrong to make this a corner-stone of his personal vision; it has, for him, produced memorable work. I do think he is wrong to make it into the rigid foundation of a theory of art, which in turn must support a theory of landscape architecture. Jellicoe and Langer Susanne Langer's theory is altogether more sophisticated than Tolstoy's, but it also seeks to establish a sole criterion by which we may identify works of art. Langer believes that language is a poor medium for the expression of our emotional lives and that works of art function as "non-discursive" or "presentational" symbols - they somehow capture and articulate some aspects of our experience which cannot be expressed in words. Langer first developed her ideas in relation to music, which she considered to be "a tonal analogue of emotive life". Music is able to function in this way, she suggests, because "there are certain aspects of the so-called "inner life" - physical or mental which have formal properties similar to those of music - patterns of rest, of tension Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 63 and release, of agreement and disagreement, preparation, fulfilment, excitation, sudden change, etc." Music shares a logical form with human feelings, therefore it "articulates forms which language cannot set forth" (Langer, 1957, p.233) From a particular theory about music, Langer went on to create a general theory applicable to all the arts. "Art," she wrote "is the creation of forms symbolic of human feeling" (Langer, 1953, p 40), and thus she maintained that architecture is concerned with the symbolic expression of human life - "the image of life which is created in buildings" (Langer, 1940, p 99). Langer made no reference to landscape design as a distinct branch of the arts, but it is clear from the following passage, in which she quotes with approval from an article by Otto Baensch, that she recognised the potential for feelings to be expressed symbolically by landscape. "The mood of a landscape appears to us to be objectively given with it as one of its attributes, belonging to it just like any other attribute we perceive it to have...We never think of regarding the landscape as a sentient being whose outward aspect 'expresses' the mood that it contains subjectively. The landscape does not express the mood, but has it: the mood surrounds, fills and permeates it, like the light that illumines it, or the odour it exhales; the mood belongs to our total impression of the landscape and can only be distinguished as one of its components by a process of abstraction"(Baensch, 1923, quoted in Langer, 1953, p 19). One difficulty that Langer has to address is that different people will have different feelings when confronted with the same piece of art. This can be as true of a landscape as it is of a painting of a landscape or a Beethoven Sonata. Her way out of this is to suggest that works of art are "unconsummated symbols" that convey something about the morphology of a feeling but do not have determinate content. Charlton likens this to the formal apparatus of algebra: "the same piece of music can be used by different hearers on different occasions as a vehicle for the conception or intuition of different emotions; in this way the elements in a piece of music are rather like algebraical symbols or functions in the mathematical sense than like numerals: a piece of music might be compared with 2( )3 + ( ) which we can fill with our own arguments" (Charlton, 1970, p 26). Once again it is easy to see how Langer's theory could be extended to cover landscape design, for certainly designed landscapes produce emotional reactions in those who visit them, but equally certainly these are different reactions for different individuals or even different occasions. Langer offers us a different account from Jellicoe for the way in which things - including some landscapes - can become works of art. They are analogues for our emotions rather than communications from the unconscious. Langer thinks that even utilitarian objects can become works of art. A craftsman produces goods, but if those objects are also able to function as non-discursive symbols of the inner life, they can also be works of art. Buildings and landscapes can also be seen in this way. The functional landscapes associated with Jellicoe's Settlers, for example, come to have a symbolic import beyond their merely productive role. The similarity between Langer's theory and Jellicoe's lies in the fact that both require the work of art (whether it be painting, musical passage or landscape) to perform a symbolic function, but Langer's view is more sophisticated than a naive communications approach. For Langer the primary purpose of a symbol is not to communicate, but to give form; the ability to create symbols is a vital part of apperception. The similarities, but also the crucial differences, between Langer and Jellicoe become more apparent when we consider that Jungian symbols are also non-discursive. This is something which Langer herself points out, but she quickly qualifies the observation: 64 Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 "... psychoanalysis is not artistic judgement, and the many books and articles that have been written on the symbolic functions of painting, music and literature actually contribute nothing to our understanding of 'significant form' " (p 240)2. Langer is aware of the narrowness and reductive nature of psycho-analytical explanations. Jellicoe makes communication a necessary function of art and asserts that the content of this communication should be something from the unconscious. Langer, on the other hand, insists that an artwork must be a non-discursive symbol, but since the symbol is "unconsummated" it can have different contents and these can be drawn from the full range of our emotional inner lives. For Jellicoe the work of art is a message; for Langer it is a vehicle. Langer's theory is less mystical than Jellicoe's, more rooted in everyday emotional life, and less exclusionary, in that a greater range of objects are likely to qualify as works of art under her criterion than under Jellicoe's. It would be an interesting project to add a chapter to Feeling and Form extending Langer's theories specifically to landscape architecture, working out in detail how the devices of the designer (rhythm, occult balance, framing etc.) might be used to "articulate what is verbally ineffable the logic of consciousness itself (Langer, 1953). Langer's theory, like Tolstoy's, has had its critics, however. It has been pointed out that if an artwork gives form to a previously inconceivable element of experience, artists cannot know what they are making until they finish, but this is hardly borne out by psychological investigations into the nature of creativity. Her theories also run into severe difficulties when they are applied to literature, for to be consistent she must allege that the discursive symbolism (i.e. the language) used in literature gives no insight into human emotions, and that the import of literature lies in the nondiscursive aspects of its form - a conclusion which strikes many commentators as absurd. Like so many general theories in aesthetics, Langer's has ultimately been found wanting. A Misguided Endeavour It will be clear from the above that I am more sympathetic towards Langer's aesthetic theories than to Jellicoe's. However, the entire search for a single criterion by which we can divide works of art from other things may be a mistaken enterprise. Wittgenstein disagreed fundamentally with all attempts at essentialist definitions (Wittgenstein, 1953). Taking the concept of a tool, he asked what quality all tools had that everything that was not a tool did not have? Was it the ability to cut? What about a hammer? Perhaps it was the ability to alter materials? What about a ruler? And so on. He concluded that in the place of a single quality there was a criss-crossing network of similarities which he called "family resemblances". This has proved a very powerful analytical notion which can be applied in all sorts of areas. It can certainly be applied to the concept of art. There is likely to be a whole family of similarities between those things we choose to call works of art. Some will stir feelings, some will not. Some we may call beautiful or sublime, others not. Some may be non-discursive symbols of feeling, but perhaps not all. Some may, quite possibly, reach into the many layers of our subconscious or unconscious minds - but some will not. There may be many ways in which an object can come to be considered a work of art. Some will have stronger claims than others. In terms of landscape, we may feel that Stourhead, which involves the creation of an idealised landscape and includes an allegory drawn from Virgil, has a very strong claim, that the careful arrangement of landform and planting around a reservoir has a weaker claim, and that a screen of cotoneasters around a car park has little to recommend it as art at all. In Art or Bunk (1989), Ground suggests that "Works of art are not simply artefacts which have been deliberately made in order to provoke aesthetic interest. They are artefacts, the essential interest of which consists in this fact." It is not enough for an object to be aesthetically interesting; to be a work of art it must also be aesthetically intelligible, which is to say there must be possible answers to questions about why the Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 65 work was made to look the way it does. Such answers may include explanations in terms of the communication of emotions or subconscious contents, but they will not be restricted to such explanations. Where does all this leave us? The focus of this paper has been deliberately narrow; it has examined Geoffrey Jellicoe's ideas far more closely than it has examined the body of his design work. Many would judge Jellicoe to be an outstanding designer, but my contention is simply that being an outstanding designer does not make him an outstanding philosopher. I am willing to concede that it is rather harsh to judge theories presented in talks and articles written over a lifetime as if they were rigorously argued in a journal of philosophical aestehtics. Nevertheless, it should be said that Jellicoe's ideas are seriously flawed. In particular he is wrong to make the communication of subconscious contents a necessary condition for creating works of art. Nor can such communication be regarded as supplying a sufficient condition. Jellicoe's ideas are wrong, but they are not pernicious. They are unlikely to cause any harm in the world, and have served him well enough in his own art. Seen as a personal philosophy rather than a general theory in philosophical aesthetics, they have value. It is naive to expect great artists, whether they be composers, poets or landscape architects, to be profound or consistent thinkers. Second, though Jellicoe's theories do not make complete sense, and in some respects are plainly wrong, he is surely right to maintain that landscape architecture can produce works of art. My purpose in this paper has not been to evaluate Jellicoe's landscape designs, but I would not disagree with the view that many of his own designs would count as art. Third, we will never find a single criterion against which to judge those things that aspire to be works of art, and we are mistaken to look for one. It will probably benefit landscape architecture if at least some of its products are considered to merit the appellation "work of art". To this extent its status is more than an academic question. There is not, however, one right or guaranteed way of producing such work. Some will see that as a problem, others as a liberation. Which schemes are works of art, which are not, and which lie on the borderline, will always remain matters of judgement and debate. Notes l.The book I have found most valuable in preparing this paper has been Philosophical Aesthetics edited by Oswald Handing for The Open University (1992). I would recommend it to anyone seeking a fuller discussion of rival aesthetic theories. 2.The term "significant form" used here by Langer was coined by the critic, Clive Bell, in his book Art (1915). There has not been the space within this paper to consider Bell's formalist theory of art. Essentially he took "significant form" to be the defining quality of all works of art. It was to be recognised by the presence of a particular kind of aesthetic emotion. Bell's theory has been severely criticised as an example of vicious circularity. If the only thing that makes form significant is that it evokes a particular sort of emotion, we are entitled to ask how we recognise this aesthetic emotion. The unsatisfactory answer is by the presence of significant form! The two ideas are defined in relation to one another. Moreover, Bell's theory over simplifies the nature of aesthetic experience, for it is not really possible to throw a cordon around formal properties and say that they are all that matters in art. Considerations of the symbolic meaning of a work, its context, its place in the artist's canon, its connection with human affairs, must all be given their weight. I have argued in this paper that all attempts at essentialist definitions of art are misguided, an argument which applies just as much to Bell as it does to Langer, Tolstoy or Jellicoe. 66 Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 References Appleton, J. (1975) The Experience of Landscape, London, John Wiley and Sons Bourassa, S. (1991) The Aesthetics of Landscape, London, Belhaven Charlton, W. (1970) Aesthetics, London, Hutchinson Ground, I. (1989) Art or Bunk, Bristol, Bristol Classical Press Hanfling, O. (ed.) (1992) Philosophical Aesthetics, Milton Keynes, The Open University Press Jellicoe, G.A. (1959, 1966, 1970) Studies in Landscape Design, Volumes I, II and III, Oxford, Oxford University Press Jellicoe, G.A. (1983) The Guelph Lectures on Landscape Design, University of Guelph Jung, C.G. (1953) Two Essays on Analytical Psychology, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul Jung, C. G. (1964) Man and his Symbols, Aldus Books Langer, S. (1953) Feeling and Form, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul Langer, S. (1957) Philosophy in a New Key, Harvard University Press Moore, R. (1993) The Senses Engaged, in the Royal Academy Magazine, Number 38, Spring edition Spens, M. (1994) The Complete Landscape Designs and Gardens of Geoffrey Jellicoe, London, Thames and Hudson Tolstoy, L. (1930) What is Art? Oxford, Oxford University Press Wittgenstein, L. (1966) Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, edited by Barrett, C., Oxford, Blackwell Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, Blackwell Landscape Research 20(2) 1995 59-67 67