Why We Should Be Virtuous Since the budding times of human civilization, society has been concerned with ensuring human life is filled with peace and prosperity. As such, society has constantly tried to dictate how individuals must act to achieve said peace and prosperity. Every aspect of our lives is regulated by laws and principles that tell us how to live and act to reach that goal. In such a world, why should a person seek to be virtuous? They can blindly follow the rules of society as they believe it helps ensure the greater good. However, individuals need to find their own moral compass. Even though we live in a regulatory and law-based society, every human being must strive to become virtuous because it is the path to true happiness. We must strive to be virtuous since it is the action that assists us in achieving the ultimate benefit of happiness. According to Aristotle, every action and decision we take aims to accomplish some good, end, or purpose (Aristotle 1). For instance, we eat food to satisfy our hunger and we work to earn money for a better life. By that logic, we would have multiple ends because each action is different and aims to reach a different end. The end we obtain from eating food is different from the end we achieve by working. Aristotle claims there is a hierarchy to the multiple goods and the ultimate good at the top of this hierarchy is happiness (Aristotle 8). In that case, if happiness is the best end we achieve from an action, then what action do we take to attain the end known as happiness? This action, according to Aristotle, is to be virtuous. Happiness is an activity of the soul in accord with reason. Furthermore, the best thing we can do with that reason is to be virtuous. With that in mind, every human being must strive to become virtuous if we want to achieve the ultimate good known as happiness in life. Even though we must be virtuous to obtain happiness, it might be possible to achieve happiness without virtue because people who are evil or dishonorable are able to show happiness. For instance, when a robber plans to rob a bank, they feel a certain level of happiness when their heist is successful. In this case, the robber was able to attain happiness even when they aren’t being virtuous. Similarly, when a scammer is able to successfully deceive someone of all their money, they are also able to obtain some happiness when their ruse works. Again, even though the scammer was being dishonest, they can feel some sort of happiness or elation when their scam succeeds. In these cases, even though the robber and the scammer were being dishonest and committing non-virtuous acts, they were still able to achieve happiness. What does this mean? We stated that if we want to obtain happiness, we must first be virtuous. Yet it stands to reason that people can still obtain happiness even when they are not virtuous and carry out non-virtuous acts such as fraud and robbery. However, even though people who are not virtuous can achieve happiness, this happiness obtained can only be considered as temporary and fleeting happiness. It cannot be considered true happiness. In Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle describes happiness as an end that is choice worthy, complete, and self-sufficient. He explains that sometimes we pursue some ends to reach or achieve another end. There are also other ends that we pursue to achieve simply for their own sake. The latter end is known as a complete end. Socrates believes that happiness is a complete end. He states, “Now happiness, more than anything else, seems complete without qualification.” (Aristotle 8). To continue, if happiness is a complete end, that means it is self-sufficient and choice worthy. Self-sufficiency here means that the end is good in itself and that when we achieve this end, we do not need anything else. In other words, a self-sufficient end makes a life lack nothing else. However, these characteristics do not apply to the happiness gained from nonvirtuous actions. For instance, in the case of the scammer, the result they get from the scam is money. However, they use that result (money) to pursue another end such as a better quality of life, or some other form of pleasure. This end is not self-sufficient, as without money the happiness of the scammer cannot be guaranteed. This happiness is also not complete because the scammer did not pursue that happiness simply for its sake. They first pursued money and used that money to reach happiness. Thus, this cannot be considered true happiness because it is not complete and choice worthy. The only way we achieve such true happiness is when we choose to be virtuous because virtue pursues happiness for its own sake (Aristotle 9). Happiness achieved by non-virtuous deeds is only temporary. But if a person engages in the activity of study, Aristotle believes that they will achieve true permanent happiness, even though the person may not necessarily be virtuous. Aristotle claims that happiness is an activity of our soul, more specifically the rational part of our souls. Reason is a part of the rational part of our soul, and the best thing we can do with our reason is to study. Simply put, studying gives us happiness. When we study, we contemplate, understand, and acquire knowledge, and this understanding gives us happiness. Thus, if the happiness gained from non-virtuous acts is temporary, it stands to reason that a non-virtuous person can gain true permanent happiness from studying. This is because a person’s ability to study and contemplate is not affected by them being virtuous or evil. If a bad person can study, contemplate, and reach understanding, then they can achieve true happiness in that process. Thus, it is possible for a non-virtuous person to achieve true happiness. It may be possible for a non-virtuous person to achieve happiness through studying. But the act of studying itself is considered the supreme virtue, and by performing this virtue (i.e., studying) we can achieve the ultimate good of true happiness (Aristotle 193). If a non-virtuous person reaches true happiness, they only gained that happiness through studying, even though they may be doing other non-virtuous acts. These acts did not bring the non-virtuous person happiness. But studying, which is an act of supreme virtue itself, was what brought them happiness instead. Therefore, to achieve true happiness, the non-virtuous person had to perform an act of virtue. This proves that the only way to achieve true happiness is if we become virtuous. Thus, we must strive to become virtuous even in our society today if we want to be happy. BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Third Edition, Trans. with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary by Terence Irwin, ISBN 978-1-62466-815-9