Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory Author(s): Turan Kayaoglu Source: International Studies Review , June 2010, Vol. 12, No. 2 (June 2010), pp. 193-217 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The International Studies Association Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40730727 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms The International Studies Association and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to International Studies Review This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms International Studies Review (2010) 12, 193-217 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory Turan Kayaoglu University of Washington In the past 10-15 years, an increasing number of revisionist schola have rejected the most significant elements of the argument about centrality of the Peace of Westphalia (1648) to the evolution and st ture of international society. At the same time, the prominence of argument has grown in the English School and constructivist inter tional relations scholarship. I deconstruct the function of the Westp lian narrative to explain its pervasiveness and persistence. I argue th was first developed by nineteenth century imperial international ju and that the Westphalian narrative perpetuates a Eurocentric bias international relations theory. This bias maintains that Westphalia ated an international society, consolidating a normative diverg between European international relations and the rest of the inter tional system. This dualism is predicated on the assumption that w Westphalia European states had solved the anarchy problem eit through cultural or contractual evolution. Non-European states, lack this European culture and social contract, remained in anarchy unt the European states allowed them to join the international society - upon their achievement of the "standards of civilization." This Westphalian narrative distorts the emergence of the modern international system and leads to misdiagnoses of major problems of contemporary international relations. Furthermore, their commitment to the Westphalian narrative prevents international relations scholars from adequately theorizing about international interdependencies and accommodating global pluralism. The centrality of the Peace of Westphalia (1648) to the evolution and structure of the international system is a familiar theme in international relations scholarship. Countless references to these treaties have led to the formation of a frame- work for understanding international history and politics that I call the Westphalian narrative.2 Among the chief elements of this narrative is the idea that the Peace of Westphalia instituted, or at least embodied, the principles of sovereignty and secularism. On sovereignty, the Peace is credited with limiting the hegemonic aims of the Holy Roman Empire, thus allowing the newly sovereign rulers to establish exclusive territorial domains. Westphalian arrangements *I would like to thank Katie Baird, Priya Chacko, Rob Farley, Michael Forman, Lucas Freire, Ahmet Kuru, Kate Marshall, Jon Mercer, Chuck Rowling, Jason Scheideman, Mike Struasz, and Charles Williams for their criticisms and suggestions on this essay. I would also like to express my gratitude to the journal's anonymous reviewers for their comments. I presented an earlier version of this paper at the 50th Annual Convention of the International Studies Association, New York City, February 15-18, 2009. 2For a classical statement of the Peace of Westphalia's place in the development of the international system, see Gross (1948). © 2010 International Studies Association This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 1 94 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory are said to enable the states to monopolize the means of violence within their territories and their control of foreign policy instruments such as war and diplomacy. Moreover, the notion of respect for each other's sovereignty (political tol- erance), out of which international law has emerged, has been traced back to Westphalia. On secularism, the Peace allegedly curtailed the universalist claims of the Catholic Church and made possible the separation of the public domain of the state from that of the private domain of religion. Furthermore, the principle of non-intervention on religious issues together with a newly instituted spirit of religious tolerance led to peaceful coexistence within and among states. Taken together, these so-called Westphalian principles and institutions were idealized as engines responsible for transforming early modern Europe into a society of states. Once this "Westphalian" international society - shared ideas and institutions grounded in political and religious tolerance - had consolidated itself in Europe, European colonization then expanded this framework worldwide; this process is described by Bull and Watson (1984). This Westphalian narrative has its critics. In the past 10-15 years, an increasing number of scholars have rejected significant parts of this narrative; Osiander (2001), Beaulac (2004), and Teschke (2003) have even called it a myth. These critiques have argued that many norms and institutions attributed to the Peace of Westphalia emerged much later, in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. They have identified some Westphalian anachronisms. For one, "Westphalian sovereignty" is a misnomer; Swiss jurist Emerich de Vattel (1714-1776) was the first to develop the idea that state sovereignty requires the exclusion of external authority structures from domestic politics (Krasner 1999; Beaulac 2003, 2004). Some major nonstate political entities, including the Holy Roman Empire, sur- vived until the early nineteenth century (dissolved in 1806) (Krasner 1993, 1995/96; Osiander 2001). In addition, until the late nineteenth century states continued to share the means of violence with a plethora of non state groups such as privateers, pirates, and merchant companies (Thomson 1994). European states often deviated from the norm of territorial jurisdiction and claimed extraterritorial jurisdiction in non-Western states and kept their consular courts there well into twentieth century (Kayaoglu 2007, 2010). The constituent principles of secularism - the separation of church and state and the acceptance of religious tolerance - had little to do with the Peace of Westphalia and they materialized, albeit imperfectly, in Europe in the nineteenth century (Kaplan 2007). High- lighting the anachronisms associated with the Westphalian narrative, these scholars discounted the role of the Peace of Westphalia for the origins, evolution, and structure of international system. But the Westphalian narrative has been resilient. Among many others, Wendt (1999), Jackson (2000), Philpott (2001), and Clark (2005) have presented arguments emphasizing the prominence of the Peace of Westphalia to understand international relations. So far Westphalian critiques have not explained the persistence of the Westphalian narrative in and its implications for international relations scholarship. To this end I deconstruct the Westphalian narrative to suggest that it in part substantiates a perspective of European exceptionalism. This exceptionalism idealizes the European/Western order and elevates its ideas and ideals in international relations scholarship. The Westphalian narrative allows scholars to reinvent an framework of normative hierarchy depending on where Western and non-Western societies placed in the narrative. Western states produce norms, principles, and institutions of international society and non-Western states lack these until they are socialized into the norms, principles, and institutions of international society. In this perspective, international society is a normative hierarchy assumed to reflect the natural division of labor in international relations. From its early sponsors to its present day supporters, there have been remarkable similarities in the use of the Westphalian narrative. These similarities could This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 195 be grouped as practical, histor that it has, albeit arguably, es development of international the origins of contemporary i account of the international classes. It is historical in tha approaches to the study of i century jurists used it against it against behavioralist scholar realist and neoliberal theorists) lished an understanding of l political and religious toleran political vision. It is this thir article. Essentially, I argue that the Westphalian narrative was first developed by German historians and usurped by international jurists in the nineteenth century. According to its earliest formulation by German historians, the Peace of Westphalia allowed European states to establish an international order based on mutual independence, political tolerance, and the balance of power. These alleged Westphalian sovereign vision stood in stark contrast to the menacing Napoleonic imperial vision. Nineteenth-century jurists added an external dimension to the Westphalian narrative: lacking a Westphalia-like arrangement, non- European societies remained in political disorder and religious intolerance. When these societies "fulfilled" the so-called "standards of civilization," the European states then "admitted" them into "international society." English School scholars in the 1960s-1980s revived the narrative of the centrality of Westphalia. With the cultural turn in international relations scholarship in the 1980s and 1990s, constructivists brought the Westphalian narrative into the literature on international norms. But it is time for international relations scholars to do away with the Westpha lian narrative for four reasons: (i) it distorts our understanding of the eme gence of the modern international system, (ii) it leads to misdiagnoses of majo aspects of contemporary international relations, and (iii) it prevents intern tional relations scholars from theorizing cross-civilizational and cross-regional interdependencies and (iv) it thwarts the accommodation of pluralism in a increasingly globalized world. First, by exaggerating some, down-playing other and ignoring some other aspects of the development of international society, th narrative has allowed the construction of an essentialized and over-generalized history. In this stylized understanding, Western societies' achievement of reli- gious and political tolerance originated with Westphalia and was furthered subsequent treaties and conventions while non-Western societies' lack of religious and political tolerance was shaped by their intolerant and despoti past. This "historical" vision is often invoked to justify cultural and legal arguments for guaranteeing the intellectual and political superiority of Europe in international relations scholarship. More perniciously this intellectual construct became an ideological tool t excuse the coercion used by Western states over non-Western states as a necessary evil, required in order to get them to conform to the rules of internationa society. For example, in the process of Europe's colonial and imperial expa sion, policymakers and scholars invoked Westphalian-grounded principles to jus tify acts of brutality and subjugation in the name of the privileged position of states that were deemed "civilized" in spreading the rule of law, tolerance, and civilization. Similar to other European-invented narratives (Hobsbawm an Ranger 1992; Hodgson 1993; Patterson 1997; Goody 2006), the Westphalian narrative allows for the continued imagination and invention of Europe' This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 196 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory intellectual and political superiority, treating the West as a perennial source of political and religious tolerance in international society. Once different societies are placed in the Westphalian narrative, this slanted history becomes a perspective and an interpretative technique that distorts our understanding of contemporary issues. Starting with the assumption of the centrality and the normative value of the Peace of Westphalia in international society cause observations become what I call "narrative-laden" when analysts focus on historical practices that either largely confirm, in few cases disconfirm, the narrative. This problem of selection bias is similar to the problem of "theoryladen" observations when analysts focus on cases that confirm the theory rather than falsify it. While international relations scholars are arguably alert for the limitations of the theories and the methodologies they employ, they rarely pay attention to the limitations and biases of the historical narratives they employ. This omission is particularly troubling given the centrality of history to the study of international relations (Elman and Elman 2001). Moreover, the selection bias is confounded with an interpretative bias: behav- iors are interpreted differently depending on a state's place in the narrative. The Westphalian narrative produces an interpretive dualism analogous to different modes of explaining intergroup relations: an in-group's desirable behavior is attributed to the in-group's character while an in-group's undesirable behavior is attributed to the external conditions. Similarly an out-group's undesirable behavior is attributed to the out-group's character while out-group's desirable behavior is attributed to external conditions (Mercer 1996: chapter 2). Mercer's insight sheds some light onto the in-Westphalian and out-Westphalian interpre- tative rationale the Westphalian narrative perpetuates: it creates a dualism between Western and non-Western states akin to in-group and out-group identity in a normative hierarchy. Thus, Westphalia-confirming European practices, for example, political and religious tolerance, are attributed to Europe's inher- ent superiority; Westphalia-disconfirming European practices, for example, lack of political and religious tolerance, are attributed to either conditions not- inherent to Europe, conditions European states could not stop, or used as evidence for the evolving practices of the Westphalian order. Conversely, Westphalia-confirming non-Western practices are attributed to conditions external to non-Western states, such as their socialization by European states; Westphalia-disconfirming non-Western practices are attributed to non-Western states' inherent inferiority and an example of the challenge thy pose the Westphalian order. This hierarchy has been used to justify the notion that Western states should follow different norms and principles toward non-Western societies as these societies have different norms, principles, and institutions. While non-Western socie- ties were gradually admitted into international society, international society continues to expand its normative scope, reaching higher levels of religious and political tolerance. Paradoxically, the Westphalian international society has deepened more rapidly than it has widened: the normative gap in the origins of the emergence of international society between Western and non-Western societies and the disparities of progress between them means that non-Western societies must perpetually chase the progress of Western states and the European order. The normative divergence will persist because Western societies continuously evolve faster than the non-Western states are socialized by adopting the existing norms, principles, and institutions. Perpetual progress of the Western normative order will continue to sustain a normative hierarchy in which the non-Western tortoise will never catch the European hare. Three caveats are necessary before further elaborating my argument that reducing the origins and structure of international society to the Peace of Westphalia reflects a Eurocentric bias in international relations scholarship. To This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 197 begin with, I do not offer an alt the inconsistencies that I claim offer a historiography of Westp invention by nineteenth-centur lish School scholars and some constructivist scholars. Furthermore, while refer- ences to the Westphalian narrative also exist in other international relations theories, such as neorealism and neoliberalism, I do discuss these theories. Because the presumption of Westphalia does not occupy a central position in these theories and they emphasize other aspects of the international system - like anarchy and the distribution of power for neorealism and interdependence and rational-choice for neoliberalism. Finally, I do not dispute the existence of inter- national society - shared ideas and institutions based on political and religious tolerance - or the importance of international society in achieving international peace, development, or human rights. Rather, I argue that international relations scholars must move away from a Westphalian-based, and thus Eurocentric, notion of international society to one that more thoroughly accommodates global diversity and plurality. This shift in narratives can bolster the legitimacy and efficiency of international society. I develop my argument regarding the Eurocentrism endemic to the Westphalian narrative in international relations scholarship in the following three sec- tions. These sections offer a chronological view of the notion of Westphalian international society. The chronological order also allows me to illustrate how later generations of scholars inherited and re-invented the ethnocentrism of past scholars. First, I examine the origins of the Westphalian narrative: nineteenthcentury international jurists' attempts to build a Westphalian narrative to support their claims for the existence of international law. Second, I discuss the English School's concept of international society and its relation to the Westphalian narrative. Third, I explore the current constructivist international relations litera- ture, tracing the durability of the Westphalian myth to the presence of Eurocentrism in current international relations theory. The Construction of the Westphalian Narrative The construction of the Westphalian narrative postdates the Peace of Westphalia (1648): it was the product of nineteenth-century intellectual and political developments. The initial sponsors of this narrative were German historians and international jurists of the nineteenth century - not the rulers of the seventeenth century. There is good reason why the Westphalian narrative did not emerge until the nineteenth century: natural law, which had been the dominant international legal discourse until the late eighteenth century, did not need to rely on a historical incident or treaty to justify the existence of international society and law. Connecting law, justice, and morality, natural law posited that the content of law is set by a transcendental source above states. Jurists of natural law pointed to numerous sources for the law: religion, human nature, nature, and finally, in the age the Enlightenment, natural reason. Since the transcendental quality of law made it valid everywhere and for everyone at all times regardless of political boundaries, any treaty, including the Peace of Westphalia, was insignificant for the legal and political order envisioned by the natural law theorists envisioned. The universalist assumptions of natural law allowed these scholars to assume the existence of an international society, preventing them from clarifying discriminatory doctrines such as sovereign recognition and sovereign territoriality, and thus making the issues central to the Westphalian narrative marginal to these scholars' theories. 3Hodgson (1993) provides some preliminary ideas as to what such a history might look like. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 198 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory But in the nineteenth century, this was to change. The transformation from natural law to legal positivism occurred in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century (Nussbaum 1954:157-185). Emer de Vattel's The Law of Nations, first published in 1758, was one of the important bridges from natural to positive law. Deviating from the earlier naturalist "law of nations," Vattel made sover- eignty central to his framework of international law by adding an external dimension to the domestic sovereignty developed by Hobbes and Bodin. The external dimension of sovereignty entails two qualities: the sovereign state's privi- lege as the sole representative of a country's population, and the exclusion of what the ruler considers "external" from domestic authority structures. With this external dimension, now known as Westphalian sovereignty, sovereign states became the sole representatives of their populations and the sole subjects of the law of nations (Krasner 1999:20-21; Beaulac 2003). Like other Enlightenment thinkers, Vattel (1916: Book 3, Chapter 3, §47) referred to the "societal" qualities of Europe using the term republic: Europe forms a political system, an integral body, closely connected by the relations and different interests of the nations inhabiting this part of the world. It is not, as formerly, a confused heap of detached pieces, each of which though herself very little concerned in the fate of the others, and seldom regarded things which did not immediately concern her. The continual attention of sovereigns to every occurrence, the constant residence of ministers, and the perpetual negotiations, make of modern Europe a kind of republic, of which the members - each independent, but all linked together by the ties of common interest - unite for the maintenance of order and liberty. Hence arose that famous scheme of the political balance, or the equilibrium of power; by which is understood such a disposition of things, as that no one potentate be able absolutely to predominate, and prescribe laws to the others. Although Beaulac (2003, 2004) implicitly and Krasner (1999:20-1) explicitly credit "Westphalian sovereignty" to Vattel, and as the quote suggests the parallels between the Vattel's argument for the uniqueness of Europe's political systems and the argument of Westphalian system are striking, surprisingly, Vattel linked neither his argument of sovereignty nor the uniqueness of European political order to the Peace of Westphalia. In The Law of Nations, he invokes Westphalia only five times on issues such as the papal rejection of treaties (Vattel 1916: Book 2, Chapter 15, §223) and the rights of German states against the Holy Roman Empire (Vattel 1916: Book 4, Chapter 6, §59). The incidental and infrequent references to Westphalia in Vattel is striking compared with the treatment Westphalia receives by one of the most prominent international jurists of the nineteenth century: Henry Wheaton. Wheaton starts his section on "The History of the Modern Law of Nations" in the History by stating: "The Peace of Westphalia, 1648, may be chosen as the epoch from which to deduce the history of the modern science of international law. This great transaction marks an important era in the progress of law of nations"; Wheaton then lists numerous fundamental changes he attributes to Westphalia (Wheaton 1973 [1845] :70). The Napoleonic Wars were mostly responsible for the emergence the Westphalian narrative. As Edward Keene has persuasively demonstrated, the earliest form of the Westphalian narrative was product of early nineteenth-century German historiography. The initial purpose of the Westphalian narrative was "to stigmatize the French Revolution, and especially the Napoleonic imperial system, as unlawful interims of the traditional principles of European public law and order" (Keene 2002:16). Elucidated by the German historians W.C. Koch and A.H.L. Hareen, this historiography developed the idea that the Peace of Westphalia established a decentralized system of mutually independent sovereign states and thus distinguished medieval Europe from modern European politics. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 199 The moniker attached to the originating from the Peace of The counter-revolutionary the Westphalian narrative. Th anteeing the mutual independ traditional liberties of Germa now under a similar threat fr like Vattel, also supported th torians could not easily rely o ral law, would find revolution violated the fundamental p than natural law, these Germ European systems. legal systems, These focus scholars arg foundation of the European l had been "constantly refresh Revolution" and the Peace w (Koch cited in Keene 2002:20). half of the nineteenth centur that the significance of the sy of the German states' territor German states as barriers bet phalia secured both the mut balance of power (Keene 200 Upon the foundation invente the nineteenth century built ical and legal order of Europe tion of "Westphalian" intern trend of nineteenth century, spective, European societies an past and to the rest of the w teenth-century European un A wide range of academic d jurisprudence, and sociology their own episteme of Euro ism, what was "law" to John Sir Henry Maine, "capitalism" ics" to Max Weber, was "West of European normative exclusi with the creation of inferior what was "custom" to John A to Sir Henry Maine, "Asian M Weber, was "anarchy" to inter In addition to this intellectua rative with its emphasis on tr law was instrumental in the in international law when legal n natural reason, became unt 2005:40-52). The ascendance phers such as J. Bentham, J. teenth and early nineteenth natural tivists, law the an unacceptable state was the ju ultima ing authority to state legisl adjudication, and the reductio This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 200 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory denied the existence of any law outside and above the state. The rise of positivist jurisprudence in international law was slow, incomplete, and contested; though not every jurist was a positivist or equally committed to its principles (Koskenniemi 2001; Slyvest 2007), every Anglo-American jurist did take the positivist critique of international law seriously. Since the late nineteenth century, all major international law texts have addressed the legal positivists' denial of international law, usually focusing on the critique offered by John Austin (2000 [1832]). In response to the earlier positivist claims that international law is not proper "law," nineteenth-century Anglo-American jurists, like Wheaton (1973 [1845]), Twiss (1884), Hall (1894), Westlake (1894), and Holland (1898), developed two lines of justification - a dualism, arguably, that still characterizes the major doctrinal and interpretative disagreements in international law (Koskenniemi 2005 [1989]). Despite the differences between these two justifications, both routinely invoked Westphalia to ground international law in European thought and practices. The first justification was a historical one that attributed the origins of international law to customary law. According to this perspective, law emerged from the spontaneous functioning of a society, in addition to the enactments of a sovereign. Much of European law was customary in that it had emerged spontaneously to regulate inter-European relations. Essentially, historical jurists reduced law, including international law, to the product of a European consciousness and culture. The second justification was an analytical argument with an emphasis on the positivist and contractual qualities of law. The analytical school justified international law based on the sovereigns' explicit consent to it. Convinced of the necessity of sovereign will in the creation of law, these jurists argued that international law is law because the collectivity of states enacted the international law, and each states enforced it through its domestic courts. States act with their sovereignty when they agree on treaties. The treaty ratifications, marking the sovereign legislative will, elevate treaties and conventions into a form of positive law, thereby internationalizing positive law. For both the historical and analytical schools, the Westphalian narrative was indispensable. For the historical school, it represented the growth of a cultural revolution triggered by Protestant religious ideas then combined with preWestphalian legal and political ideas. Philosophers like Grotius, Bodin, and Hobbes offered robust theoretical justifications for sovereignty; theologians and philosophers, like Luther, Costello, and Locke provided strong arguments for religious tolerance, and both groups provided intellectual and cultural frameworks for customary international law. For the analytical school, the Westphalian narrative represented the establishment of a clear break from the feudal system of overlapping authority structures wherein rulers vied with the Holy Roman Emperor and Catholic Church in a system of exclusive territorial sovereignty. The narrative corresponded to a structure of contractual relationships, one between the rulers and their subjects sanctifying religious tolerance, and another among rulers for upholding political tolerance. It turned the political stalemate among the political and religious groups unleashed by the Reformation into an affirmation of political and religious live-and-let-live policies, ending the Thirty- Year Wars. Once these Westphalian constitutional principles and institutions became well-established in Europe, European rulers signed additional treaties and conventions to further develop international law. Essentially, international law of the late nineteenth century became a "Westphalian" international law whose historical development and sources were closely linked to the Peace of Westphalia and subsequent European treaties and conventions. The writings of nineteenth-century jurists provide many examples of the "Westphalian" international law. As mentioned earlier, Wheaton, possibly the most prominent jurist of the first half of the nineteenth century, was particularly influential in integrating a Westphalian narrative to explain the development of This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 201 European legal and political o Onuf observes: "Wheaton adop actual international society" bu as far as I have been able to a specifically juridical basis 2000:6). While Christian law, Wheaton heritage Westphalia regarding in was the the international tell for also most law. lia, an avowed positivist, starts by citing legal positivist Austin (2000 [1832]:147-148): "It has been very justly observed that 'international law is found only on the opinions generally received among civilized nations, and its duties are enforced only by moral sanctions; by fear on the part of nations, or by fear on the part of sovereigns, of provoking general hostility and incurring its probable evils, in case they should violate maxims generally received and respected.'" Agreeing with the claim that international law could be seen as an international morality, Wheaton moves on to explaining European distinctiveness regarding international law. According to Wheaton (1973 [1845] :70) this uniqueness lays with the Peace of Westphalia in creating the modern international law. The scope and substance of the consequences that Wheaton (69-71) attributes to the Peace of Westphalia is remarkable. According to him, the treaty established secularism and religious tolerance, and thus ended the religious revolutions. It freed states from the religious authorities of the Church and from the secular authorities of the Holy Roman Empire. It also established a right of resistance against oppressive rulers. Wheaton furthermore claims that the peace secured Germany as a safe haven from religious and political persecution and as a place for refugees to "appeal to the public opinion of Europe" in case of oppression. The peace replaced European customary law with the new law of Europe. The treaties also marked the inauguration of modern diplomacy through which the European peace was maintained. With all these distinctive qualities, Westphalia thus established a European order based on public law. Wheaton's "Westphalian" international law disqualified non-Western societies. In the Elements, he stats: "The Public law, with slight exceptions, has always been, and still is, limited to civilized and Christian people or to those of European origin" (Wheaton 1936 [1866]: 15). Reducing international law to European history and culture in the form of "Westphalian" international law became widespread as the nineteenth century progressed. In the second part of the century, W.E. Hall, a prominent international jurist with a strong positivist orientation, justified the existence of international law based on the strength of European culture: "it is scarcely necessary to point out that as international law is a product of the special civilization of modern Europe, and forms a highly artificial system of which the principle could not be supposed to be understood or recognized by countries differently civilized, such states only can be presumed to be subject to it as are inheritors of that civilization." States "outside European civilization," Hall continued, "must formally enter into the circle of law-governed countries. They must do something with the acquiescence of the latter, or of some of them, which amounts in its entirety beyond all possibility of misconstruction" (Cited in Wight 1977:115). Sir Travers Twiss, a counsel to the British Crown and to King Leopold of Belgium (Koskenniemi 2001:33, 108; Hocshchild 1999:71), offered a more con- tractual understanding of Westphalia. Twiss (1884:xvii) argued that Westphalia had "laid the foundation of a new European State-System, by grouping for the first time together the States of Central Europe after the fashion of a family, the members of which were acknowledged to independent, and, although of unequal power were recognized as an equality of Right." While his jurisprudence This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms n devel In 202 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory combined positivist and naturalist elements, he emphasized that the consent of states was necessary for international law (xli) and that Westphalia marked a turning point for international law because it unambiguously showed that state rulers consented to the creation of a positive international law, replacing natural law (155). The above arguments are but a sampling (and one can find plenty of other international jurists making similar arguments Anghie (2005:32-114) and Keal (2003:84-112), however they represented the jurisprudential consensus of the late nineteenth century asserting European exceptionalism in establishing a distinctive legal and political order promoting mutual independence and tolerance. According to the international jurists of the age of Empire, such as Wheaton, Hall, Westlake, Twiss, Lawrance, Oppenheim, Europe had formed a superior order composed of sovereign and secular states, an order significantly shaped by the Peace of Westphalia and the increasing number of treaties and conventions followed Westphalia, making international law, in essence "Westphalian." With respect to the non-Western world, this argument meant that non-Western societies did not have any place in "Westphalian" international law, because these societies were not signatories to the treaties and conventions that made international law. But the narrative included a vision in which non-Western socie- ties could be part of the political and legal order marked by European progress Once in place, the order was self-perpetuating: deepening within Europe and dif fusing out of Europe. Deepening has occurred as the international laws, norms, and institutions of Europe that Westphalia had inaugurated spilled over int other issue areas. This led to further cooperation in Europe and to further dif ferentiation between Europe and the rest of the international system. Diffusio has occurred as "Westphalian" international law, norms, and institutions spread to non-European areas. They spread first to the civilized American states, then t the semi-civilized Asian states, and last to the then uncivilized African states (Bu and Watson 1984). Apart from a few marginalized voices opposing the discriminatory interpret tion and application of international law and the removal of non-Western socie ties from its realm (Pitts 2007), by the end of nineteenth century most international jurists took the existence of a normative hierarchy as the natura division in the international system. Combined with other nineteenth-century hierarchical discriminations, like scientific racism, "scientific" international law allowed jurists to argue that the unique combination of rationality and culture that existed in Europe enabled the European political order to evolve toward more efficient outcomes, fueled by the Peace of Westphalia and bolstered by subsequent treaties and conventions. In contrast, the narrative encapsulated that the other societies were in disorder in terms of their political and legal system (Turner 1978; Hodgson 1993:86). In other words, the construction of European exceptionalism and Orientalism were codependent. While the former elevated the European "order" as just and progressive, the latter denigrated the Oriental system as corrupt and decaying. Jurists constructed "Westphalian" international law and Oriental anarchy and despotism in the same crucible. This view offered a stark image of the world; to paraphrase the seminal title of Eric Wolfs (1982) book, this dichotomy can be understood as Westphalian Europe and people without Westphalia - that is, a non-European political space lacking the crucial dimension of international society, Westphalia, and the political and religious tolerance it generated. To justify their version of what Laura Nader (2005) labels "law and the theory of lack," jurists and scholars contrasted the law-based Westphalian international order of mutual independence and tolerance with a caricaturized image of, for example, a monolithic Islamic despotism under the authority of the caliph with an ideology of constant warfare with non-Muslims. Likewise, the Chinese Middle Kingdom was portrayed as a territory ruled by a This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 203 self-important feudal-isolation quently, constantly, and unfai the qualities that enabled Euro More than simply an intelle had enormous political implica society and the rights of indig "political and legal thought a served to justify the dispass with legal the development positivism, of "Wes internation exclusive to European societies the deterioration of the lega law: while prior to the sevente Grotius, and Pufendorff recog teenth-century jurists like Va like Phillimore and Bluntschil peoples, most of the nineteen Oppenheim denied sovereign tury jurists, whose jurisprude ism and whose political ideolog 2001), were often united in t imperialism. In this sense, nin European domination as it just states against non-Western soc The Westphalian narrative all Westphalian religious and poli and intolerance. Once this nar tional problems like the Easter of Africa expansion became of easy European to ide order t nificant way, the perceived European ability and willing point of the Westphalian narr sion of international society, of political and religious toler For example, John Westlake a agued that even the laws of w with uncivilized societies (Még Compatible with the civilizing ists' vision of global order, fr imperialism. The economic, fi Empire, made ment in courts lyzed China, of European what I call their expansion the legal sovere imper authority through states (1825-1923), and Eur companies legal came non-Western key capitals. compromised expanded Western citizens. Thailand, European for and extr examp China (1 Even though these states were not formal European colonies, these courts lim iting and denying non-Western legal authority over Western foreigners turned these states into, to use Mao's term, semi-colonies. During the mid-1880s, fo example, a total of 44 Western extraterritorial courts operated in Japan's treat This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 204 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory ports. In 1895, 32 British courts operated in the Ottoman Empire. Three dec- ades later (circa 1926), 26 British, 18 American, and 18 French courts existed China's ports and cities. Some of these courts like the British Her Majesty's Supreme Court at Constantinople and the US Court for China had significant legal authority. Legal positivism, by its categorical delegitimation of non-Western law, and international jurists, by their legal tools like extraterritoriality, had a significant effect in motivating and justifying Western courts in non-Western societies. Western states imposed what is known as the standard of "civilization" to end their extraterritorial claims, a standard established and articulated by nineteenth-century jurists (Gong 1984; Kayaoglu 2010). While the scramble for concessions from China and the Ottoman Empire remained limited to "unequal treaties" of consular jurisdiction and tariff limitations, a new wave of imperial expansion from 1870 to 1914 brought all of Africa, with the exception of Ethiopia and Liberia, under formal European imperialism (Hobsbawm 1989; Doyle 1986; Abernethy 2000). As legal scholars Anghie (2005:65-100) and Koskenniemi (2001:110-177) argue despite the rhetoric of "the gentle civilizer of nations," the involvement of European international jurists in the scramble for Africa epitomized by the Berlin Conference of 1884-1885, was anything but benign. Most of the interna- tional jurists acted like ideologists of European colonialism through the doctrines like Westphalian sovereignty that dispossessed non-Western rights or through extraterritoriality policies that limited non-Western legal authority, or acted as apologists for Europe's excessive brutality in the name of its civilizing mission and expansion of international society. In sum, international jurists were often complicit in, and frequently ardent supporters of, European colonialism. In addition, some current scholars of international society have offered insightful analyses linking the nineteenth century discourse of international society with imperialism and colonialism. For example, Real (2003) examines what he calls the "moral backwardness of international society": the role of nineteenth-century legal discourse in dispossessing the rights of individual peoples and facilitating European conquest. Suzuki's (2009) interesting analysis shows how the emergence of Japanese imperialism was rooted in Japan's socialization into what he labels as the "dark side" of international society in the late nineteenth century. The English School's Westphalian International Society No group of international relations scholars has been more active in promoting the Westphalian narrative than the English School. Since the early 1960s, members of the English School have engaged in a sustained and collective effort to articulate a historically informed and normatively progressive theory based on the concept of international society. Working within the notion of the Westphalian international society framework, English School scholars have produced studies exploring the historical foundations, expansion, and contemporary implications of international society. Essentially, these scholars trace the idea of a distinctively European civilization both to Ancient Greece and the Roman Empire. The later is particularly important as under its reign a Christian community was created. Following the secularization of this community with the Peace of Westphalia, Europe institutionalized common principles and institutions; these took the form of international society. Following the admission of Russia and the Americas, European imperialism expanded international society and Europeans started to admit the non-colonized states of Asia (the Ottoman Empire, Japan, Iran, Thailand, and China) into international society upon these states' fulfillment of the "standards of civilization." According to first gen- eration English School scholars (Bull and Watson 1984; Gong 1984; Jackson This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 205 1990), international society bec lowing the Second World War The existence of an interna English School (Manning 196 nami 2000) have even suggeste term for a multi-national gro would be a better descriptor, agenda. Part of methodological: the reason English fo School philosophy in international behavioral-positivist framew relations scholarship. However as scholars of The British Com Rockefeller-funded committee, 1959-1984) established the core ideas and meth- odologies of what would later come to be called the English School (Dunne 1998). Well-known English School scholars such as Herbert Butterfield, Martin Wight, Adam Watson, and Hedley Bull, were consecutive chairs of the British Committee. Over time, the number of scholars identifying themselves with the English School has increased and diversified, however the emergence and evolution of international society has remained the focus of their scholarship, in the words of Barry Buzan, its flagship idea (Buzan 2004:1). The concept of international society is particularly central to Hedley Bull's works. Often referred to as the classical definition of international society, Bull's definition has certainly been the most influential (Bull 1977; Alderson and Hurrell 2000; Bellamy 2005). The distinction between "international system" and "international society" is key for Bull. States constitute an international system when their interactions influence each other's behavior mechanically, without the states sharing principles and institutions to regulate their interactions. States constitute an international society when "conscious of certain common interest and common values... they conceive themselves to be bound by a common set of rules in their relations with one another, and share in the working of common institutions." In Bull's dualist perspective, the international system corresponds to Hobbesian anarchy, and the international society corresponds to a Lockean contractual society that features "order, regularity, predictability and long periods of peace" (Cited in Alderson and Hurrell 2000:3). On these parallel dichotomies of system/society, Hobbesian/Lockean, Bull successfully reinvents the nineteenth-century notion of the Westphalian narrative of European/non-European normative orders using a legal and historical perspec- tive. His legalism is compatible to the English School's Grotian approach to international relations. As elaborated by Wight (1991) the Grotian legal-rational approach offers a state-centric middle way between that of Hobbesian anarchy and Kantian cosmopolitanism. Within this broader Grotian tradition, Bull further refines his view of international society. Bull is particularly reliant upon nineteenth-century international jurists, especially Oppenheim (Bull 1966). Bull substantiates the nineteenth century legalistic notion of international society with a Eurocentric history, following the German historian A.H.L. Hareen (Keene 2002:22-29). As Alderson and Hurrell (2000:4) argue, for Bull, the European origins of international society are "a matter of historical fact." Westphalia is key in this history because "[t]he idea of international society, which Grotius propounded was given concrete expression in the Peace of Westphalia" (Bull 1992:75). The Peace of Westphalia marked "the emergence of an international society as distinct from a mere international system, the acceptance by states of rules and institutions binding on them in their relations with one another, and of a common interest in maintaining them" (Bull 1992:75-76). According to Bull (1992:77-78), Westphalia removed the problem of religious conflict and This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 206 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory affirmed a "general commitment to peaceful coexistence." The treaties advanced "external sovereignty," "internal sovereignty" and curtailed the hegemonic efforts of the Holy Roman Empire and the Catholic Church. Moreover, "the Westphalian treaties demonstrated... that the independence of sovereignty of states was not incompatible with their subjection to law or their recognition of the common bonds of society." In essence, Westphalia created the European order by providing "a kind of constitutional foundation of international society" (Bull 1992:77). The English School's Westphalian international society in general and Bull's approach in particular have been criticized for their Eurocentrism (Keal 2003; Suzuki 2009). Several scholars (Cutler 1991; Kingsbury 1997/1998; Bartelson 1996; and Keene 2002) note the problems with Bull's anachronistic interpreta- tion of Grotius as the first theorist of international society. For example, Keene (2002:35-38) argues that Bull's state-centric and positivist notion of international society imposes a "peculiarly narrow and twisted perspective of order in modern world politics" onto Grotius by squeezing "Grotius' extremely eclectic and wide ranging account of the law of nations into a small box." Moreover, as critics like Suzuki (2009), Keal (2003), and, more elaborately, Keene (2002) argue, the Eurocentric conceptualization of international society allowed the English School scholars to ignore the function of international society outside of Europe. In particular, international society discourse equated European international society with political and religious tolerance and, conversely, equated non-European systems with political disorder and religious intolerance. With this dualism, the Eurocentric notion of international society was invoked to promote the "standard of civilization." thereby legitimizing colonialism (Keene 2002: chapter 4), dispossessing the rights of indigenous people (Keal 2003), and even socializing Japan into an imperialist state (Suzuki 2009). While Suzuki (2009) and Keene (2002) identify problems associated with the normative divergence that the notion of international society presumes between Europe and Europe's relations with those deemed outsiders and while these scholars provide incisive critiques of the English School's notion of international society, they fall short in theorizing the relationship between different aspects of international society. For example, Keene largely treats dualism in the workings of the international society's European and extra-European spheres as unrelated to each other, neglecting to examine how the construction of the European international society of tolerance may have presupposed the view of non- European societies as intolerant. Similarly, Suzuki refers to imperialism as the "dark side" of international society without elaborating how this "dark side" and a presumably "good side" of international society have been related. The analyses of Keal (2003) and Callahan (2004), however, rightly suggest that differ- ent aspects of international society have been complementary. They argue that European self-identification depended on various European other-identifica- tions; the assertion of the complete superiority and exceptionalism of the European political and legal order has necessitated the European willingness to spread it, even if the process of civilizing non-European societies frequently requires some evil. The political impetus that gave rise to the first generation of English School scholars was decolonization, namely the possibility of sustaining the international order that European imperialism had created in the postcolonial world. This was associated with an anxiety that a non-Western "revolt" could further challenge Western dominance and values (Callahan 2004). Once the notion of international society was secured within European history and values, this perspective facilitates a pessimistic scenario: any non-Western disagreement with the West is potentially also a revolt against Western values. A revolt against Western values can destroy the foundations of the international society. Bull believed This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 207 international society and interna non-Western revolt against West The second generation of Engl various aspects of international s 2006). One issue of scholarly deb ety: so-called solidarists and plura sis on state sovereignty allows (Jackson 2000); the solidarists' tions overriding state sovereignty (Clark 2005; Wheeler 2005). In the rest of this section, I dis society School and Jackson's tradition. pluralist Although they r ety, the Westphalian narrative identifies the most important pr (legitimacy to Clark and pluralis back to the Peace of Westphali "Westphalian" global covenant, e tric account of international histo According to Ian Clark, the mos is legitimacy. Legitimacy shapes, ship and conduct in internationa Clark argues that legitimacy is a bution of power as well as mor cesses. While the definition of international of society, Westphalia remains (Clark am 2005:51-70 society has evolved from Westph temporary international society' rules about the use of power in in European/Western evolves solely within state a system Western s macy, European powers were la mentation of this legitimacy p became the engine of legitimacy post-Cold War era, democratic g national society. Yet membersh requires adherence to a new set o with human ciples rights (173-90). norms and th Clark (2005:33, 36) states his con rizing international relations. Yet phalian narrative and the normat essentially produces what can be correspond international legitim matic history, his analysis of the marginalizes non-Western societi European societies develop conc notions may be similar to or diff the only time these societies are non-Western societies violated th membership in international soc object of "Westphalian" legitim international legitimacy is min Western states that are the au This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 208 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory Westphalia, core Western states, possessing an unquestioned claim on legitimacy, have interpreted and applied the legitimacy principle in part in their encounters with non-Western societies; whereas non-Western states, lacking this legitimacy, have been subjected to Western interpretations and applications of the legitimacy principle. Once the dichotomous normative framework was established in Clark's theory of legitimacy, deviations among core European and Western states were framed as instances of reinterpretation and contestation of the legitimacy principle while the deviations of non-Western states from Western-expected behaviors have been framed as non-Western violations of the legitimacy principle. In Robert Jackson's idea of international society, the most important element is pluralism, and he traces this back to the Peace of Westphalia. For his pluralist theory of international society, he takes international legal sovereignty, territorial integrity, and non-intervention as givens and theorizes a thin transnational normative content from these basic principles (Jackson 2000:16-25). In his view, the narrow scope of international society reduces the possibility of value conflicts associated with the difficulty of building international consensus on issues where cultural perspectives may vary. Jackson unequivocally rejects a thick understanding of international society because it fosters paternalism, the tendency of imposing one's preferred values onto others. For example he correctly notes that the civilizing missions of the late nineteenth century and the articulation of "standards of civilization" illustrate this paternalism (412-416). Also figuring prominently in Jackson's arguments is the reciprocal recognition of sovereignty and state-centrism; this emphasizes the centrality of the great powers. This centrality is not incompatible with his anti-paternalism because great power privileges are limited to the organization of international security rather than to the organization of the cultures of the lesser powers, a view that accommodates some degree of global pluralism. While Jackson supports pluralism, his narrative of the emergence, spread, and evolution of pluralism remains grounded in the Westphalian narrative (162-5, 419-26). He argues that the Peace of Westphalia has symbolized the emergence of a pluralist ethos. Initially, this pluralism was a religious one, based on a rejection of Latin Christendom's universalist claims in order to accommodate reli- gious pluralism. Eventually, however, this pluralism symbolized a more expa political transformation: "as a reconstitution of European politics from th universitas, based on the solidarist norms of Latin Christendom, to that of a asy based on the pluralist norms of state sovereignty, on political indepen (164). In other words, Jackson equates the Westphalian narrative with the a modation of global pluralism like a global covenant. Essentially he offers a n tive and theory of "Westphalian" covenant advancing global pluralism. Jackson's commitment to the Westphalian narrative makes even a pluralis sion of international society Eurocentric. Some of this ethnocentric bias sur when he, perhaps unwittingly, stereotypes Islam by pairing "democracy," a of political tolerance, with "jihad," a form of political and religious intole These are the examples in his argument against paternalism, where "d racy" defines and represents Western political value and "jihad" defin represents Islamic political values (182, 368). 4 Like other English School sc ars, he recognizes the Eurocentric roots of his theory of pluralism, but d believe its Eurocentrism invalidates his theory: "[AJlthough global covena historically rooted in particular civilization, that of post-medieval Europe, i longer associated with exclusively with Western civilization as it still 4Of course "Jihad" has many different meanings, and Jackson does not define which one he is using. H the context in which he uses it suggests he defines it as "holy war," and not as spiritual striving, which is ho Muslims would define it. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 209 recently as 1945. It now it serv ilizations of the contemporary Although Jackson's attempt t right direction, it falls short. tional recognition, accommo confining these demands with for cultural and civilizationa invention of "global" covenant cess of the interpreting and diverse moral traditions, an themselves in various UN agen dialogues) are seeking a globa tional society as equals (for m see Falk 2000: chapter 8; D Kymlicka 2008). In sum, the Westphalian nar international society. Most ha School scholars whose scholars By acknowledging the impor states share, and theorizing ho tional relations, the English S tional relations and created a v system. However, the commit narrative prevents them both normative and historical sou these contributions (Bull and W cultural interactions in contem Constructivist Like the English Westphal School, const historical contingencies in e 2000:29-46; Reus-Smit 2002). the European legal and philoso is related to critical internatio Critical theorists were united and state interests as givens. R state identitie and interests ar state and nonstate actors. Thes and shared ideas among thes these interactions possible (Ru domestic authority within sta shared understanding among s fundamental place in constitut Although constructivists diff ing the consolidation of the whereby of the consolidatio system-wide normative chan of norms in Europe and then ties through state socialization secularism, and human rights and then diffuse into the nor use a variety of means (socia non-Western states to comply turn of circular logic, Wester This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 210 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory to re-invent the Westphalian narrative, and then the narrative is used to justify further dualism. For example, this two-step approach - most visible in constructivist studies on human rights (Finnemore and Sikkink 1998 and Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink 1999) - limits the emergence of international norms geographically (Europe) and normatively (the Enlightenment ideals) and results in several problems. First this view leads them to either ignore the non-Western ideas and norms or acknowledge them only to illustrate their incompatibility of the Western Westphalian ones that embodies political and religious tolerance, like that of Chinese suzerainty system or Ottoman Empire's alleged "house of war" versus "house of peace" jihad-oriented Islamic worldview (Spruyt 1994:16-17, Philpott 2001:15-20). Second, the two-step approach allows scholars to ignore the sys- tematic European practices that are incompatible with the Enlightenment ideals such as Western colonization and imperialism. Third, this two-step dualism causes the constructivist scholars to discount the role of power asymmetry in norm-construction by isolating norm-construction from the categories of normexclusion. Only after distancing themselves from the concerns of those who are excluded and disempowered, can constructivists move to emphasize shared ideas which in turn suggests that norm-construction is an empowering process lead- ing to superior outcomes allegedly for all (Kurki-Sinclair 2010). As a result, constructivist arguments for norm-construction may inadvertently - but systematically - marginalize and stigmatize non-European norms, values, and institutions. These problems also appear in the constructivists' interpretation of the Peace of Westphalia as pivotal in the construction of the international system. Among constructivist scholars, Alexander Wendt and Daniel Philpott are most explicit in their Eurocentrism. Unlike the English School scholars, who more or less share common theoretical assumptions, institutional affiliations, and identification as a group, constructivists are a more diverse group whose foundational assumptions are disputed. For example, Reus-Smit (2001) divides constructivists into conventional and critical categories and further sub-divides the critical category into modernist and postmodernist camps. These groups also differ regarding the nature of the international system and the centrality of the Westphalian narrative. Both Wendt and Philpott can be called conventional as they try to construct a grand theory of international relations. In addition, both of them adhere, to varying degrees, to the Westphalian narrative, Wendt both metaphorically and historically, and Philpott historically. Wendt's social identity theory of international relations emphasizes the change and evolution of international structures. According to Wendt, shared knowledge about state identities is more important than the distribution of material capabilities enabling and constraining interstate interactions. Wendt's theory reinvents the Westphalian narrative by creating ideal-type categories based on what he calls "cultures of anarchy," a tripartite typology of international structures - Hobbesian, Lockean, and Kantian. This typology invokes the English School's categories and thus indirectly links Wendt to the nineteenth-century international jurists' categories of European civilized/Asian barbarians/African savages. In Wendt's typology, Hobbesian anarchy is a system in which states take on the role of enemy with respect to each other; this system is identified with unmitigated violence. According to Wendt, Hobbesian anarchy describes significant portions of international history, except for the post-Westphalian European/Western system. Wendt's Hobbesian anarchy is therefore similar to Bull's international system. What distinguishes Wendt's theory is his argument that this state of war is constituted by shared ideas of enmity, not by the logic of anarchy or human nature (Wendt 1999:260). This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 211 Wendt's argument elevates the substantially. In Wendt's analys the hierarchy of cultures of an ing, Westphalia transformed a (enmity) one to a Lockean (rival Westphalia were important in developed a capability of polit started to treat other states lik accepted a set of norms (like th (like that of the "standards of After establishing Lockean anar Europe, Wendt minimizes elem presumably has operated in Eur he argues that despite the dom states occasionally fell back i Wars, the First World War, an tion, he concedes that Europe pursue colonization. But in Wendt's account these are treated as isolated fallbacks that do not disqualify his conclusion of post-Westphalian Europe dominated by a logic of Lockean anarchy and its self-restraint. However, according to Wendt, it is Kantian anarchy, in which states have internalized the role of friend. Hence Kantian anarchy represents the highest stage of the "culture of anarchy;" this is exemplified by the post-World World II behavior of the North Atlantic states (Wendt 1999:297). Three aspects of Wendt's theory are remarkably Eurocentric. First, While Wendt (242-3) accepts the possibility that Kantian international culture is "mul- tiply realizable" through, for example, "Islamic states," "socialist states," and "Asian Way states," he exclusively focuses on Western states and explains the evolution of the European international system from the Hobbesian state of nature into a Kantian peace. According to Wendt (354), values like self-restraint, that "essence of civilization," is an enabling factor in the realization of other important factors (homogeneity, interdependence, common fate). According to Wendt, self-restraint, a form of political tolerance, is most likely to be found in democratic states. Second, in addition to self-restraint, Wendt identifies homogeneity, common fate, and interdependence (most likely, to be found in capitalist societies, he agues) as being necessary for states to develop what he calls "prosocial behavior" required for Kantian anarchy. Thus, it is difficult to see how his theory allows for a diversity of political forms. Since states identities are formed, Wendt (1999:366) claims, through imitation and social learning, and since the "Western way" appears to be the preeminent model of behavior in Kantian anar- chy, non-Western states needed to "socialize" into the Western international order to realize Kantian anarchy. Third, Wendt also, in a Eurocentric blindness, ignores imperialism. His references to the mechanisms of imitation and socialization through which units develop collective identities ignore the coercive nature of the "expansion" of "international society." Somewhat unsurprisingly, his Social Theory of International Relations does not even have an index entry for impe- rialism or colonialism. Compared to Wendt's structural-cultural approach and his metaphorical use of the Westphalian narrative, Daniel Philpott offers a Weberian ideational account that reconstructs the Westphalian narrative as a historical claim. Philpott (2001) examines the role of social justice ideas in the emergence of the modern stat system with a particular focus on two "revolutions" in international society. Th 'Chacko (2008) offers a critique of Wendt's use of "anarchy." Schmidt (1998) offers a similar critique for the concept of anarchy in international relations theory. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 212 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory first revolution began with the Protestant Reformation and culminated with the Peace of Westphalia, ending medieval Christendom and bringing about a system of sovereign states in Europe. The second revolution sprang from the postwar ideas of equality and colonial nationalism, ending the colonial empires and bringing sovereignty to the rest of international system. In both cases, revolutions in ideas about legitimate political authority profoundly altered the "constitution" that established basic authority in the international system. These revolutions stemmed from earlier understandings of justice and political authority. In Philpott's theory of change, new ideas challenge the legitimacy of existing order leading to crises, and thus trigger a revolution that creates a new order. To show the autonomous influence of ideas apart from material factors in his claims of "Westphalia as origin" and "no Reformation, no Westphalia," (8) Philpott relies on scholarship concerning social movements and international norms. In so doing, he delineates the dual role of ideas in politics (48-51). In their first role, ideas create identities when people internalize new ideas and form social movements, including interest groups, lobbies, and parties. In their second role, when a significant number of people accept the new ideas, the ideas turn into a form of social power, persuading rulers to change their policies including forming a new international constitution, supporting new international norms, values, and institutions. In the context of the Westphalian Revolution, Philpott (108) holds that the Protestant ideas "lay the prescription for the new Westphalian order." In an attempt to link Protestant theology and what can be called as "Westphalian" freedom, he points to central Protestant tenets such as justification by faith, salvation through grace, and the complete and unique authority of scripture in creating a new understanding of political authority (104-10). On this alleged Westphalian foundation, Philpott interprets decolonization as the second revolution in the creation of the modern international order. The principle of freedom, which Westphalia symbolizes, establishes an ideation between the Westphalian and decolonization revolutions. While the princip "Westphalian" freedom did not prevent European states from denying this ciple of freedom to non-European societies, according to Philpott, after ab three-century interval, Western elites conceded the colonized peoples' righ freedoms associated with Westphalia and thus Protestant religious prin resulting in decolonization. Philpott's commitment to the Westphalian narrative slants his accou decolonization. For example, the most important elements of this nor challenge to colonialism happen in the Western international system and i domestic politics of imperial métropoles and only secondarily among c populations themselves (chapter 9). In Philpott's view, even colonial de for independence have European roots, such as the education the colonial e received in the métropoles or the fact that the métropoles established the i tions and the principles of equality that the Church had embraced (193). L ideas, norms, and religions do not play any significant role in Philpott's stu decolonization. Even if some (very few) of the actors of the decolonization ment are non-Western, their ideas, inspirations, and models are markedly tern and can be traced back to ideas propagated by theologians and philosophers of the Reformation and Westphalia. In Philpott's international history, every freedom enhancing idea and incident is traced back to the Peace of Westphalia and thus to the Protestant reformation. Conversely, the problems in chronology, the undesirable behaviors of post-Westphalian Western societies, and the contributions of non-Western ideas and events in the creation of interna- tional society are explained away, if not totally neglected. In conventional constructivist studies, the centrality of progress and civilizatio appear in the form of the Westphalian narrative; with this assumed trut This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 213 constructivist phal image of scholars like We the West based contemporary structure ety. Using the Westphalian of foundational narrative assumes that the rest of the world has benefited from the n int spread and imposition of Western values and civilization; this foundational narrative transforms itself into a constitutional argument when it posits that non-We tern societies continue to benefit from the spread and imposition of Western ideas such as modernization, state-building, and human rights. This commitmen to the Westphalian narrative limits the usefulness of constructivist insights abou the importance of "shared" values in international system and prevents the constructivists acknowledging how these norms, like human rights, can b affirmed and supported by non-liberal, non-Western traditions. Conclusion International relations scholarship is shaped both by the political and the id logical affinities of international relations scholars (Oren 2003), but als perhaps more significantly, by arguments about the superiority of Western v and political systems. This presumption of superiority is embedded in the dard historical reference points of the discipline's description of internatio relations, descriptions which are drawn almost exclusively from Europe's int history. This distortion influences theorizing about modern international r tions because it presents European thought and practices as the engine o international system and as the source of enlightenment, modernity, democ sovereignty, and human rights. Contemporary international relations t remains caught in the notion that the West sets the standard for civilized h conduct; Western liberal democracies are constantly treated as the only ent capable of bringing any sort of order to the system. This ethnocentrism is most evident in the international relations scholars' acceptance of the Westphalian narrative to explain the origins and develo of international society. Nineteenth-century jurists and some contemporar national relations scholars follow strikingly similar strategies. They identi element associated with political and religious tolerance, broadly correspo to the ideas of sovereignty and secularism, and they credit the Peace of We as the origin of that particular value. This value is international law for th teenth-century international jurists, legitimacy to Clark, pluralism to Jackson, restraint to Wendt, and freedom to Philpott. Once these scholars have attr these values to Westphalia, they then explicitly reconstruct an internationa in which European societies are assumed to inherit these values from We Progress is then defined in terms of progressive refinement of these value scholars also reconstruct, explicitly or implicitly, a secondary history deali non-Western societies without Westphalia, societies thereby lacking thes Finally, for European societies, behaviors consistent with these values are uted to the European political system and culture while behaviors incons with them are presented as unimportant, caused by external and situatio tors. The opposite is true for non-Western societies: behaviors consistent these values (law, legitimacy, pluralism, self-restraint, freedom) are attrib external and European influences in these societies while their behaviors in tent with these values are attributed to their history, religion, and culture. This skewed understanding of international history and relations is ind of the Eurocentrism of international relations scholarship. This Euroc prevents international relations scholars from envisioning the integr non-Western societies in a way that does not involve coercion, dominatio an assumption of Western superiority. There is a great need to broa This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 214 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory deepen global values. The way forward is to investigate how non-Western traditions of political and religious tolerance, like those of the Ottoman millet system, the Chinese tributary systems, and Mughal Emperor Akhbar's religious pluralism or contemporary calls for the coexistence of civilizations or interfaith dialogue, can be appreciated and incorporated into international society. Such refocus can facilitate the non-Western affirmation of international society, the promotion of its fundamental values of peace, development, tolerance, and human rights. International relations theory without Westphalia may open new research agendas for international relations scholars in three specific ways. First, moving away from the Westphalian narrative allows a critical evaluation of the emergence of sovereignty and norms in the international system. If the revisionist scholarship is correct that many of the so-called Westphalian norms are a product of the nineteenth century, the age of empire (Hobsbawm 1989), then imperialism should be integral, not incidental, to the emergence of norms in the international system. Yet the current norm and sovereignty literature emphasizes cultural and contractual evolution and ignores the role of power dynamics in norm construction. Integrating non-European areas into a reexamination of the emergence of so-called Westphalian norms, such as sovereignty, may open new avenues for examining the nexus of power and ideas. For example, a norm analysis should address not only how norms benefit the group members but also how they weaken the ones excluded, rather than treating such exclusion as given. Thinking beyond the Westphalian narrative will shift the attention from the largely functionalist and evolutionary understanding of international society which emphasizes linear, steady progress to one that better integrates power and interest and which indicates the contested and politicized nature of the concept of international society and its various incarnations. Second, imperialism has been one of the most influential forces shaping world politics. Yet, imperialism remains marginal for many English school scholars and constructivists. This neglect that comes with emphasizing the Westphalian order, misrepresents the current world order as one based on sovereign equality despite the pervasiveness of imperial influences and the legacies present in many postcolonial states. Greater recognition and awareness of international society's imperial origins and its reproduction of the imperial world order can produce better analyses of imperialism in the twenty-first century (Jones 2006). Third, thinking beyond Westphalia offers historical picture of the development of the international system that recognizes the interdependence among different regional systems and acknowledges the need to accommodate global diversity and pluralism. The idea of international society can be indispensable for achieving the universal ideals of peace and the promotion of human rights. The Westphalian narrative inhibits the legitimacy and efficacy of the notion of international society because of its inherent dualism: it designates "the West" as primary creator of the ideas of international society and identifies the other states as those that must be coerced and coaxed into conforming and complying with these ideas. Rather, a truly global international society needs to appeal to and be affirmed by diverse ethical traditions, such as the Chinese, Indian, Jewish, and Islamic (Mapel and Nardin 1998; Sullivan and Kymlicka 2008). Such appeal and affirmation requires a prior understanding about what these traditions contributed to the development of international society and how they can provide their own rationales for the necessity of and value in international society. A serious consideration of these diverse traditions could take the form of what John Rawls (1996) calls an "overlapping consensus" over the substance of interna- tional society. As it now stands, the Westphalian narrative prevents the emergence of a genuine cross-civilizational dialogue on how best to achieve political and religious tolerance in international society. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 215 References Abernethy, David B. (2000) Global Dominance. New Haven: Yale University Press. Ashley, Richard. (1989) Untying the Sovereign State: Double Reading of the Anarchy Problé tique. Millennium 17: 227-262. Alderson, Kai, and Andrew Hurrell, Eds. (2000) Hedley Bull on International Society. New Y St. Martin's Press. Anghie, Antony. (2005) Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Austin, John. (2000 [1832]) The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. Bartelson, Jens. (1996) Short Circuits: Society and Tradition in International Relations Theory. Review of International Studies 22: 339-60. Beaulac, Stéphane. (2003) Emer de Vattel and the Externalization of Sovereignty. Journal of th History of International Law 5(2): 237-292. Beaulac, Stéphane. (2004) The Westphalian Model in Defining International Law: Challenging the Mvth. Australian Journal of Legal History 8(2): 181-213. Biersteker, Thomas J. and Cynthia, Weber., Eds. (1996) State Sovereignty as Social Construct. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bellamy, Alex J., Ed. (2005) International Society and Its Critics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bull, Hedley. (1966) The Grotian Conception of International Society. In Diplomatic Investigations, edited by H. Butterfield and M. Wight. London: George Allen & Unwin. Bull, Hedley. (1977) The Anarchical Society. New York: Columbia University Press. Bull, Hedley. (1984) The Revolt Against the West in The Expansion of International Society, edited by Hedley Bull and Adam Watson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bull, Hedley. (1992) The Importance of Grotius in the Study ot International Relations. In Hugo Grotius and International Relations, edited by H. Bull, B. Kingsbury, and A. Roberts. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Bull, Hedley, and Adam Watson, Eds. (1984) The Expansion of International Society. New Yo Oxford University Press. Buzan, Barry. (2004) From International to World Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Callahan, William A. (2004) Nationalising International Theory: Race, Class and the English School. Global Society 18(4): 305-323. Chacko, Priya. (2008). Modernity, Orientalism, and the Construction of International Relations. Unpublished Manuscript. Clark, Ian. (2005) Legitimacy in International Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cutler, Claire A. (1991) The 'Grotian Tradition' in International Relations. Review of International Studies. 17(1): 41-65. Dallmayr, Fred, and Abbas Manoochehri, Eds. (2007) Civilizational Dialogue and Political Thought. Lanham: Lexington. Doyle, Michael. (1986) Empires. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Dunne, Tim. (1998) Inventine International Society. New York: St. Martin's Press. Elman, Colin, and Miriam F. Elman, Eds. (2001) Bridges and Boundaries. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Falk, Richard A. (2000) Human Rights Horizon. New York: Routledge. Finnemore, Martha, and Kathryn Sikkink. (1998) International Norm Dynamics and Politcial Change. International Organization 52(4): 887-917. Gong, Geritt. (1984) The Standard of "Civilization" in International Society. Oxford: Clarendon University Press. Goody, Jack. (2006) The Theft of History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gross, Leo. (1948) The Peace of Westphalia: 1648-1948. The American Journal of International Law 42(1): 20-41. Hall, William Edward. (1894) Foreign Powers and Jurisdiction of the British Croton. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hobsbawm, Eric. (1989) The Age of Empire 1975-1914. New York: Vintage. Hobsbawm, Eric, and Terence Ranger. (1992) The Invention of Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hochschild, Adam. (1999) King Leopold's Ghost. New York: Mariner Books. Hodgson, Marshall G. S. (1993) Rethinking World History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Holland, Thomas Erskine. (1898) Studies in International Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 216 Westphalian Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory Jackson, Robert. (1990) Quasi-States: Sovereignty International Relations and the Third World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jackson, Robert. (2000) Global Covenant. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jones, Branwen Gruffydd. (2006) Introduction: International Relations, Eurocentrism, and Imperialism. In Decolonizing International Relations, edited by B. G. Jones. Boulder: Rowman & Littlefield. Kaplan, Benjamin J. (2007) Divided by Faith. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kayaoglu, Turan. (2007) The Extension of Westphalian Sovereignty: State-Building and the Abolition of Extraterritoriality. International Studies Quarterly 51(3): 649-676. Kayaoglu, Turan. (2010) Legal Imperialism: Sovereignty and Extraterritoriality in Japan, the Ottoman Empire, and China. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Keal, Paul. (2003) European Conquest and the Rights of Indigenous People. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Keene, Edward. (2002) Beyond the Anarchical Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kingsbury, Benedict. (1997/1998) A Grotian Tradition of Theory and Practice?: Grotius, Law, and Moral Skepticism in the Thought of Hedley Bull. Quinnipiac Law Review 17(Spring): 3-34. Koskenniemi, Martti. (2001) The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870-1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Koskenniemi, Martti. (2005 [1989]) Apology and Utopia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Krasner, Stephen. (1993) Westphalia and All That. In Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, edited by J. Goldstein and R. O. Keohane. Ithaca, NY: Cornel University Press. Krasner, Stephen. (1995/96) Compromising Westphalia. International Security 20(3): 115-151. Krasner, Stephan. (1999) Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Kurki, Milja, and Adriana Sinclair. (2010) Hidden in Plain Sight: Constructivist Treatment of Social Context and Its Limitations. International Politics. 47 (1): 1-25. Linklater, Andrew, and HiDEMi SuGANAMi. (2006) The English School of International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Manning, Charles. (1962) The Nature of International Society. London: London School of Economics Press. Mapel, David R., and Terry Nardin. (1998) International Society: Diverse Ethical Perspectives. Princeton: Princeton University Press. MÉGRET, Frédéric. (2006) In From 'Savages' to 'Unlawful Combatants/ In International Law and Its Others, edited by A. Orford. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mercer, Jonathan. (1996) Reputation and International Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Nader, Laura. (2005) Law and the Theory of Lack. Hastings International and Comparative Law Review 28(2): 191-204. Nussbaum, Arthur. (1954) A Concise History of the Law of Nation. New York: Macmillan. Onuf, Nicholas. (2000) Henry Wheaton and the 'Golden Age of International Law.' International Legal Theory 6(1): 2-9. Oren, Ido. (2003) Our Enemies and US. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Osiander, Andreas. (2001) Sovereignty, International Relations, and the Westphalian Myth. International Organization 55(2): 251-288. Patterson, Thomas C. (1997) Inventing Western Civilization. New York: Monthly Review Press. Philpott, Daniel. (2001) Revolutions in Sovereignty: How Ideas Shaped Modern International Relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Pitts, Jennifer. (2007) Boundaries of Victorian International Law. In Victorian Visions of Global Ord edited bv D. Bell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rawls,John. (1996) Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Reus-Smit, Christian. (2001) Constructivism, in Scott Burchill, Andrew Linklater et al., Theories of International Relations (2nd edn). London: Macmillan. Reus-Smit, Christian. (2002) Imagining Society: Constructivism and the English School. British Journal of Politics and International Relations 4(3): 487-509. Risse, Thoamas, Stephen C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink. (1999) The Power of Human Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ruggie,John G. (1998) Constructing the World Polity. London: Routledge. Schmidt, Brain. (1998) The Political Discourse of Anarchy. Albany: State University of New York Press. Slyvest, Casper. (2007) The Foundations of Victorian International Law. In Victorian Visions of Global Order, edited by D. Bell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Spruyt, Hendrik. (1994) The Sovereign States and Its Competitors. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Turan Kayaoglu 217 SuGANAMi, HiDEMi. (2000) A New tion and Conflict. 35 (2): 217. Sullivan, versity William of M., and Cambridge Will Narra Kymlic Près. Suzuki, Shogo. (2009) Civilization and E Teschke, Benno. (2003) The Myth of 164 Relations. London: Verso. Thomson, Janice. (1994) Mercenaries, Pirates, & Sovereigns. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Pr Turner, Bryan S. (1978) Marx and the End of Orientalism. London: Allen & Unwin. Twiss, Sir Travers. (1884) The Law of Nations, Considered as Independent Political Communities. Oxfor Clarendon Press. Vattel, Emer (de). (1916) The Law of Nations or Principles of Natural Law. Washington, DC: Car Insitution. Walker, R. B. J. (1993) Inside/ Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wendt, Alexander. (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Westlake, John. (1894) Chapters on the Principles of International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wheaton, Henry. (1936 [1866]) Elements of International Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Wheaton, Henry. (1973 [1845]) History of Law of Nations. New York: Gould, Banks & Co. Wheeler, Nicholas J. (2005) Saving Strangers. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wight, Martin. (1977) Systems of States. Leicester: Leicester University Press. Wight, Martin. (1991) International Theory: The Three Traditions. New York: Holmes & Meier. Wolf, Eric R. (1982) Europe and the People Without History. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. This content downloaded from 13.210.62.193 on Tue, 09 Mar 2021 02:45:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms