39 THE BEARING OF FILM ON PHILOSOPHY r o b e rt b . p i p p i n I The ways in which serious thought about film and philosophical reflection might intersect are various, and those dimensions have been much explored in the twentieth century, especially with the establishment of the academic study of film in the seventies and eighties.1 At that intersection, there are various philosophical questions that can be raised, primarily but not exclusively, about filmed fictional realist narratives, or “movies.” There are related questions about photography and other types of recordings of movement or figuration: documentaries, art videos, and non-representational avant-garde films, for example. But both Hollywood (or commercially produced narrative films) and art cinema, considered as new art forms, have drawn the most attention. The most natural philosophical attention to film or movies has been as a subdivision of aesthetics, or philosophy of art. There is the obvious question of what kind of art object a filmed narrative is and so how it compares with plays, paintings, and so forth, a question that now must include not just celluloid recording but digital recording and projection, and narratives made for television. (So “film” is now often used to refer to any and all such technologies, not just celluloid recording.) This is sometimes called the problem of film “ontology.” There is also the question of the specific character of the cinematic experience, whether the ways in which we understand what is happening are connected to our cognitive processing of events in general, and if so, how? In what ways is our relation to what we see and understand connected to what we see and understand in the real world? If there is that connection, how is the 1 There are several good surveys of these developments, up to and including the current divisions. See especially Wartenberg 2015; the first chapter of Wartenberg 2007, “Can philosophy be screened?” (1–14); and the introductory remarks in Sinnerbrink 2011: 1–11. There are also a number of readers and anthologies (see Sinnerbrik’s list, 2011: 208). More than anything else, changes in the technology of film viewing have made possible a studied attention to film never before possible without great expense and investment of time. 529 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 530 Robert B. Pippin connection made and maintained? This is also relevant to our emotional involvement. Why do we care about fictional characters as much as we do, recoiling in fright or weeping in sympathy with what befalls them, but in no way that prompts us to do anything about their fates, fictional as they are. I will discuss in a moment the question of our understanding these narratives as shown to us, displayed, made for an audience. This raises the question of the “narrator” of the film. (Who is showing us what?) Is there an “implied narrator” in the film world? (And what is a film world?) Is the narrator primarily the director, the so-called “auteur,” or is the whole apparatus for the production and distribution of the film, and the performers, the collective “agent” responsible for the product? Can that agent be said to have “intentions”? But thanks largely to the work of the Harvard philosopher Stanley Cavell, and, from a different tradition, the French philosopher Giles Deleuze, a distinct intersection has evolved, one that in some circles is now designated “filmphilosophy.” (There is an online journal with that name.) This “style” of philosophizing,” one could call it, sometimes occurs within film studies (as in the work of D. N. Rodowick) or in philosophy departments, a fact which raises another issue too large for an economical discussion: the relation between “film theory” and “film philosophy,” as practiced in the two departments. The idea I want to explore briefly here is one that has gained currency in recent years, and about which more and more is being published: that films can be considered a form of philosophical reflection itself, given a capacious enough understanding of philosophy, one not limited to the marshaling of arguments in support of explicit theses. Moreover, the strongest claim is not that film might inspire a viewer to pose philosophical questions or that film can serve as examples of philosophical problems (like moral dilemmas, for example), or that they pose “thought experiments” that prompt philosophy (although films can certainly do all of these things very effectively and we might want to know what is distinctive about cinematic means for doing so) but that film, some films anyway, can have philosophical work to do. It is not easy to give a formulaic account of just what in the work “demands” such closer and, for want of a better word, “aesthetic” attending, the kind we would direct at so-called “high art,” and then what a “philosophical” version of that attending consists in. At least it is hard to point to anything beyond this abstract appeal to “questions raised by the work” that are not questions about plot details, but are like: “Why are we so often looking from below at figures in shadows in some noir?” Or “What does it mean that Gary Cooper’s character throws his marshal’s badge to the ground in obvious disgust at the end of High Noon?” Or “Why does the director ‘twin’ Grace Kelly’s wedding ring with that badge”? Or “Why is Hitchcock so apparently Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 The Bearing of Film on Philosophy 531 indifferent to the obvious artificiality, the blatant, even comic phoniness of the back projection techniques he uses frequently in Marnie?” It is even more difficult to present a general account of when those questions are “distinctly philosophical” in character. And it is certainly a controversial claim. Many academics who think and write about film, and a great many philosophers of all kinds, would vigorously dispute this view. It is also a far more complex issue than it might at first seem. One of philosophy’s chief topics is itself and the endlessly contested question of what philosophy is. Asking this sort of question about film puts us at the center of such centuries-old disputes. It is a more familiar idea among philosophers who occupy themselves with historical figures in the tradition who had something close to this “complementary” view about philosophy and the arts, primarily but not exclusively philosophy and literature. These would include Hegel’s treatment of Sophocles or Diderot in his Phenomenology of Spirit, Kierkegaard’s use of Don Giovanni, Schopenhauer’s theory of the philosophical significance of music, Nietzsche’s reflections on Greek tragedy and an “aesthetic justification of existence,” or Heidegger’s appeal to Hölderlin. In the case of Hegel, for example, art in general, together with religion and philosophy, is treated as part of a collective attempt at self-knowledge over time, and is viewed not as a competitor with religion or philosophy but as a different and indispensable way (a sensible and affective way according to Hegel) of pursuing such a goal. The notion is also not foreign to philosophers influenced by Wittgenstein, concerned with, as it is put, how we came to be in the grip of a picture of, say, the mind’s relation to the world, or our relation to each other, and how we might be “shown” how to escape that picture. (This is especially so with Cavell’s work, concerned as he is with various dimensions of skepticism and given his view that film is “the moving image of skepticism” [Cavell 1981: 188–9]).2 The central question in Heidegger’s work, the meaning of being, since a question about meaning in the existential not linguistic sense, is understandably a question that might be informed by how such a meaning might be “disclosed,” as Heidegger sometimes puts it, in a work of art. But, as noted, that notion of “philosophic work” in film remains controversial. If it is to have some currency, we need a clearer idea of what might distinguish a “philosophical reading” of a film, and how such a reading might contribute something to philosophy itself. To begin, consider the simplest issues that arise when we watch a film. Issues like the following. 2 See also the chapters by Cerbone and Mulhall, this volume. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 532 Robert B. Pippin II The basic question is: what must we do in order to understand what we are shown?3 The question raised above might be formulated: even if the “cognitivists” in film theory are onto something about our simply “following” a movie (see Bordwell and Carroll 1996; Currie 1995), is there a way of working to understand a film that goes beyond working to understand the details of its plot? When, at what point, have we “understood a movie,” and might we be said to have learned something from having thus understood it? That is, is it possible that, in working to understand a movie better, we could just thereby understand better something of philosophical significance? Cavell has said that what serious thought about great film requires is “humane criticism dealing with whole films” (Cavell 1979b: 12) and he later calls such criticism “readings.” What are readings of films, and, our question, are there “philosophical” readings?4 One way, among many ways, of beginning to think about the issue can be suggested by the following two points. First, there is the issue of our mode of attending. We can consider the conditions that must obtain for a cinematic experience to be an aesthetic experience, an experience directed at a work of art. I mean only that when we are attending to a work as a work of art, we could not be doing so unless we knew that this is what we were doing. Not all filmed narratives are works of art. There are home movies, orientation videos, documentary records. But knowing what we are doing “in” doing it (not doing it and observing ourselves doing it) is difficult to account for philosophically. The situation is roughly similar to cases attended to by philosophers where, in general, we could not be doing what we were doing unless we were aware, in doing it, that we were doing it – marrying, promising, etc. So if we wander into a large building, and stand up and sit down when other people do, and even if we are indistinguishable in our conduct from everyone else, if we do not consider ourselves to be attending mass, we would not be. This involves no conscious application of the concept “mass” to what we are doing. It is in doing it, succeeding in doing it, or doing it competently, that we know we are attending mass. We are not monitoring ourselves constantly, but if we did not know that saying or doing this or that counts as participating in a mass, what we were doing would not count as participating.5 3 4 5 I rely here on material I have also discussed in these terms (Pippin 2016; 2017). As Cavell writes: “I do not deny that there is a problem about the idea of ‘reading a movie.’ Is it greater, or other, than the problem about the idea of ‘reading a poem,’ when, of course, that is not the same as reciting the poem?” (Cavell 1979b: 9). This is actually not an uncommon predicament in movies, like the “marriage” between the Native American, Look, and Martin in John Ford’s The Searchers. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 The Bearing of Film on Philosophy 533 Aesthetic experience is, again roughly, like this. It does not simply happen to one. It requires a particular mode of attending. It is conceptually articulable in more extensive exfoliations, but in that rough sense, when we go to a movie, we take ourselves to be doing just that, and we have an equally rough sense that a movie is an art work, a product of the human imagination, not a secret recording of various people dressed in the garb of the 1940s, if we are watching a film noir. Perhaps we even have that concept, noir, but it is not necessary to the point. It is important to stress constantly that this knowingwe-are-so-attending is nothing like a self-observation, an attending to ourselves as an object. It is a constituting aspect of aesthetic attending itself, not a separate noting of that fact. It is in attending this way that we are, in George Wilson’s terms, “imaginatively seeing” what we are seeing (Wilson 2011). Or, at least, this is how I understand his claim. We are not seeing actors on a big screen and imagining who they are. We see Ethan in The Searchers and we wonder what Ethan is doing and why. We do not see John Wayne and imagine, in a separate act, Ethan. And, since The Searchers is a work of art, we wonder what it means to be shown that he acts as he does. We can of course wonder why characters do what they do in the movie, what it means that they act as they do in the sense of asking what could have motivated that fictional character – why they would do something so self-destructive – and so forth, and not get very far. The work may have a narrow or limited ambition. By the ambition to be a work of great or “fine” art, I mean that the point of being shown such actions is defined by the way a question of some generality – typological, historical, moral, etc. – is broached, and sometimes that generality is of a philosophical sort. It is also not the case that attending aesthetically – knowing what we are doing when we are experiencing, attending to, the work – is something that need interfere with or compete with our direct emotional absorption in the plot, our anxious concern for some character. And we can begin seeing a movie on the assumption that its ambition is merely to entertain us or frighten us pleasurably (however that actually works). We attend to it in such a way, take ourselves to be on about such an experience, but someone can point out for us that there are elements in the movie that might be entertaining, but, our friend shows us, they also raise questions beyond cinematic pleasure itself, questions that cannot be explained by that function alone, and we can begin to attend to the movie in a different way, a way I want to follow Wilson in calling imaginative seeing, or, in the term used above, aesthetically attending. (The same sort of “parallel track attending” is possible in admiring the performance of Wayne, even as we follow and try to understand what Ethan is doing. The main point is the same. There are not two steps: seeing Wayne Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 534 Robert B. Pippin and imaging Ethan.)6 Then we can say that the imagination or attending in question is not limited to an emotional involvement in the events we see (imaginatively attending to the lives of characters and what might happen) but ranges over many elements. We try also to imagine why we are shown things just this way. When that happens, we begin to attend aesthetically, to see imaginatively. A philosophical answer might be the appropriate answer; that “the film” (however we designate the agency responsible for its making) presents this view of love as illusory (and can show us the “inevitable” illusion), and this other view as close to what romantic love actually amounts to (the presentation compels conviction, although how it does so is something that would require extensive discussion). Second, consider that films can be treated as very much like speech-acts addressed to an audience, which narrate some tale (the analogy is far from perfect, but serviceable in this context; it brings out the relation between seeing, and being shown what one sees), and we can sometimes (as suggested above) ask what the director – or the collective intelligence we can postulate behind the making of the film – meant by so narrating a tale.7 We want to know the point of showing us such a story at all, and showing it to us in just this way, with just this selection of shots, from which point of view at what point in the film, with just this selection of detail. In the same way that we could say that we understood perfectly some sentence said to us by someone, but that we cannot understand the point of his saying it now, here, in this context, given what we had been discussing, we can also say that we can understand some complex feature of a movie plot, but wonder what the point might have been in showing us this feature in such a way in that context. This allows us to put the point in an even broader way. Visualized fictional narratives, movies, can be said to have many functions, can be said to “do” or 6 7 This is no more mysterious than our concentrating on the promises being made in the marriage exchange, while aware that it is by saying them, in this context, with the right authority present, that we are thereby marrying. That is, it is not mysterious. I am adopting the so-called “fictional” or “as if” narrator position, an implication of which is that the attribution of intentions to such a narrator has nothing to do with what some historical individual, e.g. the director, actually had in mind. I am in agreement here with what Cavell says about an “artist’s intention” in his discussion of whether Fellini can be said “to have intended” a reference to the Philomel myth in La Strada (see Cavell 1976: 230–1). It also is important to understand something that Wilson, in the book just cited, stresses: this narrator should be conceived in cinematically minimalist terms. The agency of such a narrator “is merely minimal; e.g. generally invisible and inaudible to the spectator, uniformly effaced, and characteristically inexpressive” (Wilson 2011: 129). “Characteristically” is the key word here. Our attention can be explicitly directed to the fact of narration by the director, something quite prominent, say, at the beginning of Psycho, with its expansive, searching pan (from no point of view that could be occupied by anyone in the film), and an intrusive, “spying” descent through an open window. For a longer discussion of Wilson’s thesis, see Pippin 2013. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 The Bearing of Film on Philosophy 535 accomplish various things. They please, for example, or they are painful to watch, but painful that is in some odd way pleasant as well. We can also say, in a straightforward, commonsense way, that some films can be a means of rendering ourselves intelligible to each other, rendering some feature of human life more intelligible than it otherwise would have been; all, if we are attending aesthetically, appropriately. This can be as simple as a clearer recognition that, say, some aspect of the implications of a violation of trust is as it is shown, and other than we might have thought. And this might be so in relation to that general issue, not limited to that representation of that violation at that time. This might require, in some cinematic presentation of this drama, a rich narrative about a decision to trust in a situation of great uncertainty8 and this narrative might be able to show us what is “generally” involved in such a decision, and what “follows” from the violation, what “backshadowing” effects it has, what it portends for the future, all in a way that a philosophical example in a discursive account could not do very well. Now, if the question is what the director (or, again, the collective intelligence we can postulate behind the making of the film) meant by so narrating a tale, sometimes the answer will certainly be: he, or she, or they, meant only to be narrating the tale, because the tale is in itself entertaining, thrilling, hilarious. But some films can be said to attempt to illuminate something about human conduct that would otherwise remain poorly understood. The point or purpose of such narrating seems to be such an illumination – a vague word, but it gets us started. There is some point of view taken and not another; and so there is an implicit saying that some matter of significance, perhaps some philosophical or moral or political issue, is “like this,” thereby saying that it is “not like that.” And one other way of rendering intelligible or illuminating is to show that what we might have thought unproblematic or straightforward is not that at all, and is much harder to understand than we often take for granted. Coming to see that something is not as intelligible as we had thought can also be illuminating. (Bernard Williams once wrote that there can be a great difference between what we actually think about something and “what we merely think that we think” [Williams 1993: 7], and great literature or great film can make clear to us in a flash, sometimes to our discomfort, what we really think. In the same way, a film noir’s credibility and illuminating power might throw into doubt that we ever really know our own minds, and so can function as the agents that 8 Think of Robert Bresson’s A Man Escaped (1956), where the main character, Fontaine, must decide whether to trust a boy he does not know well at all if his escape plan is to work. He must trust not only the boy, but his own judgment, one based on a sense of a brief, epiphanic insight. We come to realize that in all this the question of faith, the meaning and implications of faith, are being raised. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 536 Robert B. Pippin philosophical theory requires [see Pippin 2012b]; we might begin to entertain the idea that such theories require an idealization that comes close to being completely counterfactual.) Now this linkage of topics only gets us to the brink of an unmanageably large question. If at least part of what happens to us when we watch a film is that events and dialogues are not just present to us but are shown to us, and if the question that that fact raises – what is the point of showing us this narrative in this way? – does not in some cases seem fully answered by purposes like pleasure or entertainment, because something of a far more general, philosophical significance is intimated, some means of understanding something better, and all this occurs in an aesthetic register, in our attending aesthetically to what is shown, then that much larger question is obvious. This issue of its philosophical significance, with philosophy understood in some sort of traditional way, is, admittedly, quite a specific one, and those same issues can be considered in some other way. For one thing, movies, after they are made and when they are distributed, enter a complex social world, charged with issues of hierarchy, power, gender roles, social class, and many other fields of significance, and they can come to mean a variety of things (across historical times) never anticipated by the makers of the film. But one perspective, a sociohistorical one, need not exclude others, like a philosophical one, and the test for any perspective is the quality of the readings that result from looking at a film one way rather than another, or in addition to another. (This is one of the most difficult aspects of this issue. The question of a philosophical reading demands a kind of reading, and so a kind of writing, that is both true to the experience of watching the film and to the larger issues “screened.” Writing that does justice to the specificity of the film experience and to its philosophical stakes is not one that has any rules or even, as of yet, many paradigmatic examples. And that writing is the test of whether there is such a thing as film philosophy.) But such an approach faces the obvious problem just noted and it must be addressed at least briefly. How could such a visualized fictional narrative, concerning such particular fictional persons and particular fictional events, even or especially when marked out by an aspiration that is aesthetic, bear any general significance? Generality, we know, is a matter of form, and it is possible at least to imagine that the events we see are instances, perhaps highly typical and especially illuminating instances, of some general form of human relatedness. Shakespeare, for example, would not be able to portray so well, so credibly and powerfully, Othello’s jealousy, unless the origins and conditions and implications of jealousy itself were also somehow at issue, illuminated in however particular a case. (If that were not so, wherein would lie our interest in the display of a singular pathology?) But how might such a level of Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 The Bearing of Film on Philosophy 537 generality be intimated by a narrative with a very concrete, particular plot, and what would explain the illumination’s relation to some truth, not to mere psychological effectiveness? (A film after all can at the same time be powerfully compelling, can suggest an ambition to reach this level of generality, and, if the director is technically talented, can carry us along with this point of view, only for us on reflection to realize that the point of view we had been initially accepting is in fact infantile, cartoonish, pandering to the adolescent fantasies of its mostly male fans.) This example suggests a set of further examples that are recognizable philosophical questions, but do not seem to admit of anything like Socratic definitions, or necessary and sufficient conditions for their having the determinate meaning they do. Many involve so-called “thick” concepts that require a great deal of interpretative finesse to understand whether the concept is even applicable, and how we might know, in some complicated context or other, whether it is relevant at all. I mean moral issues like: Does this count as a violation of trust? Should that consequence have been foreseen? In this particular situation of wrong-doing, who (if anyone) is morally blameworthy and why? When rightly blaming someone, when is it wrong to keep blaming him or her? Who might seem to be, but finally not be, blamable? How does such seeming and distinguishing work? What does forgiveness require before it is reasonably granted? (Is it ever reasonably granted, or is it beyond reasons?) Who, under what conditions, is worthy of trust, and who is not? How would one decide that? What is an acceptable risk in exposing oneself to betrayal or manipulation? Can the same action be said to be at the same time both good and evil, noble and ignoble, loving and self-interested? Is the relation between such value contraries one not of opposition, but of gradations, as Nietzsche claimed (Nietzsche 2002 [1886]: §§24, 25)? What would that look like? In what ways might all such issues look different in different communities at different times? All of these cases must touch on what it is to trust, to blame, to forgive, and again the successful evocation of that generality is a matter of writing that is difficult to formalize. And there are issues raised by some films, questions we seem to confront in trying to understand the films, in what has come to be called moral psychology. How do people come to understand what they are doing, what act description, in some contestable context, is rightly self-ascribed, and what accounts for them getting it right, when very often we get it wrong? Why do they often wrongly, and sometimes culpably wrongly, understand what they are doing? Or, in other words, how is self-deceit possible? And again, a question that could be asked as a corollary to each of these: What does that phenomenon look like? What do we detect when we think we detect the presence of self-deceit, deliberate Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 538 Robert B. Pippin fraudulence, a lack of self-knowledge? How do we make ourselves intelligible to each other, especially when desire and self-interest make that very hard to do? How do we figure each other out, and why, in the most important situations of love, danger, and trust, do we often seem to be so bad at it? (Is there some general point being made by the fact that in so many of Hitchcock’s films, the wrong person is blamed or suspected of something?) What is romantic love; that is, does it exist, or it a dangerous fantasy? And do we know it when we see it? How important is it in a human life? What is the best, the most admirable, way to live with, to bear the burden of, the knowledge that we face eternal nonexistence, death? What distinguishes how we live, now, from how we used to live? Is how we live now a good way to live? What is objectionable about it? If a movie can, speaking very informally, “shed light” on such issues, then is there a limited but potentially important kind of illumination: primarily by means of filmed photographs moving in time? Such a “coming to understand” is not something formulatable in Socratic definitions and is closer to what Aristotle meant in his account of practical wisdom: knowledge but not something that can be taught and transmitted, the kind of knowledge that requires a wide range of experience. And as noted, its being a kind of knowledge that is Socratic amounts to a deeper knowledge of ignorance, a more nuanced state of confusion. The basic idea of the pertinence of drama to philosophy is as old as Aristotle’s claim in his Poetics that drama is “more philosophical” than history because of the generalities and probabilities suggested, and as relatively recent as Hegel’s notion of the “concrete universal,” an instance that best expresses its kind, revealing the kind’s essence much better than an abstract definition. (Wittgenstein on “perspicuous representation” is also relevant.) The question is how such generality can be intimated. One way such a level of generality can be suggested is by the relation of the films to other films, to films by other directors, referenced in a manner that suggests the general thematic purposiveness of that director’s overall project, and especially by reference to the filmmaker’s other films, directly suggesting again such a commonality and so generality of purpose. At some point such repetitions and similarities can suggest a sort of mythic universality.9 That is certainly true of Hitchcock’s films. There is something like a “Hitchcock world,” a set of problems repeatedly faced by his characters, many having to do with the painfulness and the dangers of our general failure to understand ourselves or each other very well, or to make effective use of what little we do understand to 9 For a fuller discussion, see Pippin 2012a. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 The Bearing of Film on Philosophy 539 direct our actions accordingly, all as recognizable as the formal cinematic markers of what is called, what he himself called, his “style.” With the issues set out like this, we can ask about that world, the claim to truth that its representation makes on us. For example, Hitchcock’s masterpiece, his 1958 film Vertigo, is about quite a distinct individual, a neurotic with vertigo caused by acrophobia, obsessed with a woman who is impersonating another woman. What could be more idiosyncratically unique than such a tale? Could anything of any general significance follow from answering the question: “What is the point of Vertigo?” – the point of showing us just this narration in just this way? I want to say that it has a great deal to do with, let us call it, a general, common struggle for mutual interpretability in a social world where that becomes increasingly difficult. The film, in a kind of hyper-exaggerated way, can be said to explore why it is a struggle; what kind of society makes such failure more likely, and why; how and especially why we so often manage to get in our own way in such attempts; what, mostly by implication, would count as success in such a struggle and how it might be achieved. Such a non-discursive treatment of aspects of human irrationality can be said to be attempting to show us the “nature” of these phenomena, what we need to understand in order to to understand systematic and deep mutual misunderstanding, self-opacity, selfdeceit, and other forms of limitation we are subject to when we try to learn what we need to know (but cannot) in cases of trust, love, and commitment.10 All of this, the perspective suggested above, certainly does not amount to a theory of film, or an intervention in academic film theory. Such academic “research” requires, understandably, for its inclusion in an institution dedicated to the creation of new knowledge, a structure that resembles the modern paradigm for such claims to know – modern natural science for the most part. One advances a theory about how movies – let us say, realist narrative fiction cinema – are understood, what effects they have on an audience, why some community at such a time would make and consume such things, what it means that they do, what effect on society at large their doing so produces. And then one finds instances to exemplify and support the theory, to show that the theory works in making sense of what would otherwise not be as explicable. Such a 10 So I disagree with Noël Carroll’s understanding of the philosophical importance of Vertigo. He argues that because the philosophy at issue is “not for the graduate seminar room of a research university,” it is philosophically revelatory, if it is, for its “target audience,” “the general public” (Carroll 2007b: 113). A good deal of the film’s philosophical revelation is certainly accessible to “the general public,” but a very great deal more depends on multiple viewings, extremely close attention, and some awareness of the philosophical tradition. A very great deal is also simply very difficult to understand, apart from sustained and careful attention, of the sort we would not associate with “the general public,” and much of it would indeed be a fit subject for a graduate research seminar, if the seminar were about the nature of the human struggle for mutual intelligibility. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 540 Robert B. Pippin theory can be a Freudian or Lacanian one, or a feminist one, or a Marxist one, or a structuralist one, or, more and more frequently, one informed by cognitive science, and, given the point made previously, that not all films are “movies,” and given that many such theories actively resist any canonization of greater versus lesser films, the range of the objects studied can be quite wide. In fact, if it is to be a successful theory, it aspires to as wide a range of explicables as possible, from Hollywood gangster films, to Chinese silent films, to European art cinema, to Bollywood films, to experimental films. This accounts for the understandable recent move to “media studies” as the genre for which digital films are a species, analog films another species, movies a subspecies of that, and Hollywood movies a subspecies of that. (It has become especially popular recently, across a wide range of different theories – affect theory, cognitive science approaches, neuro-aesthetics, feminist criticism, psychoanalytic approaches, postmodernist art, post-Danto philosophical aesthetics – to consider the art work, film in this case, as in the first instance an occasion for an experience, suggesting that our attention should be devoted to understanding that experience. Deconstructive theory has also played a role in this by attempting to undermine the notion that the work has a meaning that is the proper subject for more or less adequate interpretation.) A concentration on a cinematic treatment of a complicated philosophical problem (or, said inversely, a philosophical reading of film) need not be considered a competitor to all this, but something simply different. Of course, there will inevitably be some disagreement. Some such approaches presuppose a relatively unproblematic access to something like “the movie,” and then proceed to ask what such an object would mean for some audience, or for women, or for men, or in what way it operates ideologically, or psychoanalytically, or what “code” it invokes. This is also possible and can be valuable. But there are movies that present us with a number of elements that are very hard to take in and process on a first viewing. Such a taking in and responding to a movie can be initially confusing and incomplete, with only a dim initial sense of how the elements might fit together. This is not restricted to following details of an intricate plot. We might be quite puzzled about the point of being shown this or that episode, character, or even by means of this or that camera position or camera movement. “The movie” is not something “given” for subsequent subjection to a categorical or a theoretical framework, any more than, in trying to understand an action, “what she did” or “what she was trying to do” are simply “given” empirically. Or a film like Psycho might seem to fit a conventional genre, a horror film, in a way that allows it to be taken as nothing but a work of craft meant to entertain by scaring, even though there are elements of the film, from Marion Crane’s visualizations of the results of her theft, to the Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043 The Bearing of Film on Philosophy 541 kind of paintings Norman Bates has on his office walls, to the stuffed birds hovering about, to the treatment of marriage and its relation to other Hitchcock films that raise the same issue, to an unusually broad and philosophical conversation between Marion and Norman about “traps,” and being either caught in one, or stepping into one, that disrupt any putatively seamless horror movie experience. This is because, so my suggestion goes, such movies (by no means all movies or films) embody some conception of themselves, a distinct form, such that the parts are parts of one organic, purposive whole. Just in the way that a bodily movement in space can count as an action only by virtue of the selfunderstanding embodied in and expressed in it, an art work, including any ambitious movie, embodies a formal unity, a self-understanding that it is always working to realize. Such a formal unity (what I earlier called the “point” of making and showing the film) requires investigative work focused on the details of the film, both stylistic and substantive, covering as many details as possible. In fact, the movie, one has to say in an ontological mode, is the movie it is only by means of this emerging, internal self-conception, a dimension we can miss if we too quickly apply some apparent formal unity, like a genre designation, or a sociohistorical concept. In ambitious films – and such a category is by no means limited to “art cinema” – such a self-conception is unmistakably philosophical, and so what it asks of us is a kind of thought and writing that we are just beginning to explore. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 09 Nov 2019 at 16:17:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.043