Uploaded by Bernie D'Angelo Asher

justice

advertisement
463
British Journal of Social Psychology (2014), 53, 463–483
© 2013 The British Psychological Society
www.wileyonlinelibrary.com
On the relationship between justice and
forgiveness: Are all forms of justice made equal?
Michael Wenzel1* and Tyler G. Okimoto2
1
2
Flinders University, Adelaide, Australia
The University of Queensland, Brisbane, Australia
This research investigates whether, following a wrongdoing, the restoration of justice
promotes forgiveness. Three studies – one correlational recall study and two
experimental scenario studies – provide evidence that while a restored sense of justice
is overall positively related to forgiveness, forgiveness is highly dependent on the means of
justice restoration being retributive (punitive) versus restorative (consensus-seeking) in
nature. The findings showed that, overall, restorative but not retributive responses led to
greater forgiveness. Although both retributive and restorative responses appeared to
increase forgiveness indirectly through increased feelings of justice, for retributive
responses these effects were counteracted by direct effects on forgiveness. Moreover,
the experimental evidence showed that, while feelings of justice derived from restorative
responses were positively related to forgiveness, feelings of justice derived from
retributive responses were not.
Justice and forgiveness share a complex relationship. At the surface it would seem justice
and forgiveness are antithetical to one another, where justice demands imposed offender
suffering that seems counter to the undeserved benevolence implied by forgiving
sentiments. Alternatively, justice and forgiveness can be thought of as independent from
one another; victims may (or may not) forgive offenders irrespective of their
punishment, or they may seek offender punishment regardless of their willingness to
forgive. In fact, however, it is also possible that justice and forgiveness are not only
compatible but rather functionally related. Forgiveness can help restore a sense of justice
(Wenzel & Okimoto, 2010, 2012), and conversely, the restoration of justice can facilitate
forgiveness (Tripp, Bies, & Aquino, 2007). Despite being a dominant assumption, this
latter possibility, that the repair of a sense of justice facilitates forgiveness, has received
surprisingly little attention in psychological research and is the focus of this article: Are
victims more willing to forgive when measures have been taken to restore their sense
of justice?
Justice and forgiveness
Justice is defined as a subjective sense of restored moral order and moral rightness of
response following a transgression or wrongdoing. What justice means is subjective, but
to the extent that people feel an offender deserves to be punished – a deeply ingrained
*Correspondence should be addressed to Michael Wenzel, School of Psychology, Flinders University, GPO Box 2100, Adelaide, SA
5001, Australia (e-mail: michael.wenzel@flinders.edu.au).
DOI:10.1111/bjso.12040
464
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
notion of justice in Western societies (Hogan & Emler, 1981) – justice would seem
antithetical to forgiveness. Forgiveness has been defined as the transformation of a
victim’s motives and attitudes towards the offender from negative to positive, indicated
by reduced revenge or retributive tendencies, reduced avoidance and increased
benevolence towards the offender (McCullough, Root, & Cohen, 2006; McCullough
et al., 1998). It has been likened to altruistic behaviour that is most proximally driven by
empathy for the offender (McCullough, Worthington, & Rachal, 1997; McCullough
et al., 1998): A benevolent act despite the forgiver’s ‘moral right, and perhaps even …
moral obligation, to seek retribution by punishing or harming the offender’ (Aquino,
Grover, Goldman, & Folger, 2003, p. 212). As an act of mercy, forgiveness would seem to
sacrifice justice, abandon justice standards and, therefore, be in opposition to justice
(Exline & Baumeister, 2000). However, research suggests that justice and forgiveness are
actually quite compatible. For example, Karremans and Van Lange (2005) found that
participants primed with the concept of justice showed greater, not less, propensity to
forgive.
While there is little empirical research on this question, there are dominant theoretical
views that argue that justice restoration may in fact benefit forgiveness. Tying in with the
idea that forgiveness implies some sacrificing of justice, it has been argued that such a
sacrifice would be easier if it is small rather than large. If the initial injustice the offender
caused is more benign, and/or actions have been taken to reduce the injustice and restore
justice, then victims should find it easier and be more willing to forgive. This idea has been
articulated in the concept of the injustice gap (Exline, Worthington, Hill, & McCullough,
2003; Worthington, 2006). After a transgression, the injustice gap is the discrepancy
between the victims’ entitlements or desired just treatment and their actual treatment,
hurt and victimization. However, the discrepancy may be subsequently reduced by the
offenders being punished or offering an apology, and/or the victims being compensated,
given the opportunity to express their hurt in a victim statement, and so on. Failing these
responses, the discrepancy between the victims’ actual outcome and what they desire as a
just outcome may remain undiminished (or may even increase), causing victim
dissatisfaction and an unwillingness to forgive (Worthington, 2006). In this sense,
forgiveness is positively dependent on the restoration of justice. Even if the discrepancy is
often not completely reversible (not least because the offender’s actions cannot be
erased) and forgiveness is needed to bridge the remaining gap, this ‘sacrifice’ is easier if the
gap has been narrowed.
Importantly, the injustice gap concept implies that ‘any factor that influences
perceived injustice should thus influence a person’s ability or willingness to forgive’
(Exline et al., 2003, p. 344). So, any intervention (e.g., third-party punishment), action
(e.g., offender apology), or cognitive rationalization (e.g., external attribution) that
increases feelings of justice in the victim should therefore increase the probability that the
victim will forgive the offender. A similar proposition is made in Tripp, Bies, and Aquino’s
(2007) vigilante model of justice, which also predicts that any given justice response will
increase the likelihood of forgiveness by restoring a sense of justice and reducing negative
emotions. Specifically, they argue that both apologies and third-party punishment can
increase forgiveness through the restoration of justice, and even proportionate revenge by
the victim may lead to forgiving tendencies.
As far as we know neither the injustice gap notion nor the vigilante model have been
put to a proper empirical test. Certainly, existing research has shown that perceptions of
severity and attributions of blame to the offender are negatively related to forgiveness
(Boon & Sulsky, 1997; Fehr, Gelfand, & Nag, 2010), ostensibly because they represent a
Justice and forgiveness
465
larger injustice gap. Likewise, conciliatory behaviour such as apologies have been found
to promote forgiveness (e.g., Fehr et al., 2010; McCullough et al., 1998), ostensibly
because they narrow the injustice gap. However, we are not aware of any research
showing that retribution (by third parties or the victims) facilitates forgiveness. In this
research we critically test this idea.
However, we question the validity of the proposition that justice restoration by any
means promotes forgiveness. We argue that the concept of the ‘injustice gap’
presupposes a unitary understanding of justice, but that when it comes to forgiveness,
not all forms of justice are made equal. Although some injustice responses do indeed
increase feelings of justice and lead to forgiveness, other responses can increase feelings of
justice without impacting a victim’s willingness to forgive.
Retributive versus restorative justice
Recent theoretical advances in the psychology of injustice and victimization have
suggested a more nuanced understanding of what it means to restore justice. Justice
restoration theory (Wenzel, Okimoto, Feather, & Platow, 2008) proposes that there are
two distinct understandings of what justice means to victims and what its restoration
entails: a retributive versus restorative understanding of justice. A retributive notion
conceptualizes justice as unilateral assertion against the offender. On the other hand, a
restorative notion conceptualizes justice as achieving a renewed consensus between the
affected parties. These two understandings of justice are conceptually distinct, yet not
necessarily mutually exclusive (Okimoto, Wenzel, & Feather, 2012).
While initially conceptualized as a way to identify preferences for punitive sentencing
versus restorative conferencing in legal domains, this theory serves as a comprehensive
model for understanding all types of injustice responses (Okimoto & Wenzel, 2008) as
they can entail essentially retributive (e.g., punishment, revenge) or essentially restorative
(e.g., apologies, dialogue) justice meanings. This analysis is based on evidence that
retributive and restorative responses primarily address different underlying justice goals
(e.g., Okimoto et al., 2012; Wenzel, Okimoto, Feather, & Platow, 2010). Retributive
responses achieve justice through unilateral assertion against the offender, thus
addressing concerns over the victims’ status and power usurped by the offender. In
contrast, restorative responses achieve justice through a renewed understanding
between victim and offender, thus addressing concerns over the violation of shared
norms and values that define the victim-offender relationship or common group identity.
By analysing various responses according to the fundamental psychological needs they
address, justice restoration theory (Wenzel et al., 2008) helps to specify when different
responses are deemed appropriate and why – predictions that extend to interpersonal,
intragroup, and intergroup phenomena, and to social, legal, and organizational contexts
(Okimoto, Wenzel, & Platow, 2010).
This theoretical approach has implications for our understanding of forgiveness as it
relates to justice. It suggests specific circumstances in which the injustice gap prediction
that justice restoration will increase forgiveness may not hold true. Specifically, this
approach suggests that the positive link between justice and forgiveness might only hold
for restorative, not retributive, means of justice restoration.
First, we contend retributive responses, while restoring justice, are otherwise
incompatible with forgiveness. That is, in addition to their justice-restoring effect (and its
presumed benefit for forgiveness), retributive responses have psychological implications
that tend to make people less willing to forgive. Retributive responses operate by
466
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
reassertion against offenders, lowering their status and power and symbolically excluding
them; they label offenders as deviants who do not share the moral values constitutive of
one’s identity (Okimoto & Wenzel, 2009). Retributive responses create social distance,
reducing the basis for empathy and shared identity that have been shown to facilitate
forgiveness (McCullough et al., 1997; Wohl & Branscombe, 2005). Thus, while
retributive responses might increase forgiveness indirectly through the restoration of
justice, their direct effect runs counter to this and may neutralize the indirect benefits. In
contrast, restorative responses operate by seeking consensus and reaffirming values that
define a shared identity (Wenzel et al., 2008). Thus, restorative responses not only
increase forgiveness indirectly through perceptions of justice but their psychological
implications of inclusion of the offender, and the trust and hope that the offender shares
the same moral values, may also be directly related to forgiveness – indirect and direct
processes that add to another:
Hypothesis 1:
Restorative responses will have both a positive direct and indirect effect (via
justice) on forgiveness, both adding to a positive total effect on forgiveness.
Retributive responses will have a positive indirect effect on forgiveness (via
justice), but a negative direct effect; the combined total effect may not be
significant (depending on the relative strength of the two effects).
Second, we contend that while retributive responses lead to feelings of justice, the quality
of this justice may be different from the justice achieved through restorative means. Even
though both retributive and restorative responses may lead participants to report greater
feelings of justice, the essence of this justice differs. Retributive responses achieve
retribution-oriented justice through the imposition of punishment against the offender,
implying a re-balancing of the scales (in status or power) for one party relative to the other
(Wenzel et al., 2008). The very understanding of retributive justice suggests oppositional
identities and a negative interdependence over status/power that is not conducive to
forgiveness. In contrast, justice derived from restorative means has a different quality; it is
restorative justice achieved through social reaffirmation of the values violated by the
offence (Wenzel et al., 2008). It implies a positive interdependence regarding the social
validation of values and a shared identity that are conducive to forgiveness. In other words,
the relationship between feelings on justice and forgiveness will depend on the means
from which those justice feelings are derived because the different means establish a
different quality of justice; the means will therefore moderate the relationship between
justice and forgiveness.
Hypothesis 2:
Feelings of justice will generally be positively related to forgiveness, but this
will be qualified by the nature of the response from which those feelings
derive: feelings of justice achieved through a restorative response (compared
to an unspecified control) will be more strongly related to forgiveness;
feelings of justice achieved through a retributive response (compared to an
unspecified control) will be less strongly related to forgiveness.
The predictions are in line with findings that forgiveness is consistent with a restorative
understanding of justice but in fact inconsistent with a retributive understanding
(Okimoto et al., 2012; Strelan, Feather, & McKee, 2008, 2011). However, previous
research established these relationships in self-reported preferences for justice type and
forgiveness, and thus it is not surprising that retributive justice orientations (Okimoto
et al., 2012) or retributive goals (Strelan et al., 2011) are related to a tendency to seek
Justice and forgiveness
467
revenge, which is a definitional counter-indication of forgiveness (McCullough et al.,
1997). However, this prior work does not speak to the consequences for forgiveness
when retributive or restorative responses are used to restore justice, or whether the
restoration of justice is indeed beneficial for the willingness to forgive.
Taken together, both theoretical predictions suggest that the link between justice and
forgiveness should be qualified by the nature of the justice-restoring response, with
retributive responses being less conducive to forgiveness than restorative responses.
However, the two predictions differ in the process through which that provision occurs.
The difference is in whether the qualification comes from the retributive intervention
itself having negative effects on forgiveness independent of its beneficial indirect effect
through justice (i.e., suppression), or from the essence of the achieved justice being
different depending on the nature of the intervention (moderated mediation). Both
processes may also operate in tandem.
STUDY 1
Study 1 used a recall paradigm. Participants were asked to recall a situation where they felt
they were the victim of a transgression. To explore whether results would be the same
irrespective of seriousness, they were asked to recall either a serious or a less serious
transgression. They then indicated retrospectively on a number of self-report scales what
was done in response, the degree to which they felt justice was restored, and their level of
forgiveness to the offender.
Method
Participants and design
A total of 105 Australian university students participated in the study (69% female
students, age M = 24.5, SD = 7.65). They were randomly allocated to one of two
conditions, asking them to recall a transgression of low versus high seriousness.
Materials and procedure
Participants were asked to ‘Think about a time when you were the victim of what you
consider to be a (minor, serious) transgression – some type of crime, offence, or unfair
treatment that happened to you that you felt was (not very) serious.’ They rated the
seriousness of the recalled transgression on three items (e.g., ‘How serious was this
incident?’; a = .87). Next, participants were asked to ‘really try and reflect back about the
situation’ and were prompted to write down their recollections in an open text-field. They
then completed the main dependent variables. Responses from multi-item measures were
averaged to obtain scale scores.
Retributive response
Retributive justice refers to justice through imposition of punishment (Wenzel et al.,
2010). Seven items assessed whether participants believed there was a retributive
response to the transgression, whether the offender was punished and received their just
desert (e.g., ‘How severely was the offender punished, compared to similar incidents of
this type?’, 1 = much less than usual, 7 = much more than usual; ‘Did the offender get
468
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
what was deserved – his/her just deserts?’, ‘Were you able to pay the offender back?’,
1 = not at all, 7 = very much; a = .91). Note that some of the items assumed that the
participant knew what happened to the offender; when missing values resulted from
these items, scores were the average of the available responses.1
Restorative response
Restorative justice refers to justice through seeking consensus between the parties,
about wrongdoing, the values violated, and what can be done to repair the harm (Wenzel
et al., 2010). Seven items assessed whether participants believed there was a restorative
response, whether the participants and the offender worked towards a shared
understanding of the wrongdoing and what needed to be done (e.g., ‘Did you try to
communicate to the offender that what he/she did was wrong?’, ‘Did the offender seem
to acknowledge that the values he/she violated were indeed important?’, ‘Did you and
the offender agree about how the situation should be resolved?’, 1 = not at all, 7 = very
much; a = .91). Retributive and restorative response scales were strongly correlated,
r = .70. Given the high correlation between the measures of retributive and restorative
response, we investigated further whether the empirical evidence supported their
conceptual distinction. First, a principal component analysis with varimax rotation
extracting two factors explained 64% of variance in total (34% and 30% by the two
factors, respectively); all items loaded on their designated factor with loadings >.61
(there were some cross-loadings, but these were consistently smaller or insubstantial).
Second, we conducted confirmatory factor analyses and compared a 1-factor model with
the theoretically assumed 2-factor model. A chi-square difference test showed a
significantly better fit of the 2-factor compared to 1-factor model, Dv2(1) = 57.31,
p < .001.
Justice
Eight items assessed feelings of justice (e.g., ‘Do you feel the situation, as it unfolded, is
very unjust? [reverse-coded]’, ‘Given everything that has happened, is your sense of
fairness satisfied?’, 1 = not at all, 7 = very much; a = .89).
Forgiveness
Eight items assessed participants’ sentiments of forgiveness and willingness to forgive
(e.g., ‘Do you hold a grudge against the offender? [reverse-coded], ‘Do you wish that
something bad would happen to the offender’ [reverse-coded], ‘Do you want to see the
offender hurt and miserable?’ [reverse-coded], ‘Do you feel goodwill for the offender?’,
‘Do you trust the offender?’, ‘Do you (or would you) find it difficult to act warmly towards
the offender?’, ‘Do you harbour negative feelings towards the offender?’ [reverse-coded],
‘If you had the opportunity now, would you be willing to express your forgiveness to the
offender?’; 1 = not at all, 7 = very much; a = .86).
1
It was natural that, due to circumstances, some participants did not know what other actions had been taken against the
offender; however, this did not diminish the validity of their responses about their own involvement in punishment. In order not to
lose valuable information, introduce bias in the selection of cases, and diminish statistical power, we retained all participants with
the information they could provide. Note that the pattern of results was the same when respondents with missing values on any of
the items were excluded from the analyses.
Justice and forgiveness
469
Results
Participants recalled a great variety of situations in private, workplace and community
contexts, including disrespect, procedural unfairness, sabotage of one’s work, theft and
major fraud. As intended, the events recalled were less serious in the low (M = 4.45,
SD = 1.45) compared to the high seriousness condition (M = 5.07, SD = 1.55),
t(103) = 2.14, p = .034; however, in both conditions the perceived seriousness was
rated above the midpoint of the scale, t(49) = 2.18, p = .034 and t(54) = 5.26, p < .001
respectively. Analysis also indicated that seriousness did not moderate any of the findings
reported below; interactions involving seriousness were therefore omitted from the
reported analyses. Zero-order correlations showed that forgiveness was positively
correlated with justice (r = .54), retributive response (r = .27), and restorative response
(r = .46); justice was positively correlated with retributive response (r = .43) and
restorative response (r = .42); and retributive and restorative responses were positively
correlated (r = .70).
We used multiple regression techniques to test our predictions (see Table 1). First, we
tested for the effects of retributive and restorative responses on feelings of justice.
Controlling for manipulated seriousness, which had a negative effect on feelings of justice,
both retributive and restorative responses were positively related to justice perceptions.
Second, we conducted a hierarchical regression for forgiveness, including seriousness as
well as retributive and restorative responses in the first step, adding perceptions of justice
as a predictor and suspected mediator in a second step, and the two-way interactions
between perceived justice and retributive and restorative responses (all centred) in the
third step. Diagnostics indicated no problems of multicollinearity at any of these steps
(Tolerance >.46, Condition Index = 3.20). In Step 1, seriousness had a negative effect on
forgiveness; retributive response had no significant effect, while restorative response was
positively related to forgiveness. In Step 2, justice perceptions were positively related to
forgiveness; when including justice, the effect of the restorative response was reduced,
but still significant and positive, while the retributive response now had a significantly
negative effect on forgiveness. These results were not further qualified by any interaction
effects in Step 3.
Bootstrapping techniques for testing specific indirect effects with small samples
(Preacher & Hayes, 2008) showed that restorative response had a significant positive
indirect effect on forgiveness through feelings of justice, B = .09, SE = .05 (95%
CI = 0.01–0.21). The indirect effect of retributive response was also significant, B = .11,
SE = .06 (95% CI = 0.003–0.25). However, because its direct effect was in the opposite,
negative direction, the total effect of the retributive response in Step 1 was not significant.
Discussion
Study 1 showed that restorative, but not retributive, responses appeared to increase
forgiveness, supporting Hypothesis 1. While both seemed to increase feelings of justice,
and justice was positively related to forgiveness, this only translated into a total effect on
forgiveness for restorative responses; for retributive responses, the positive indirect effect
on forgiveness was counteracted by a negative direct effect. In line with the concept of an
injustice gap, reduction in injustice feelings appears to increase forgiveness. However,
only restorative responses helped to restore justice and foster forgiveness.
Notably, Study 1 did not show support for Hypothesis 2; the type of justice
intervention did not appear to moderate the link between justice and forgiveness. This
Seriousness
Retributive response
Restorative response
Seriousness
Retributive response
Restorative response
Justice
Retributive 9 Justice
Restorative 9 Justice
Justice
.26
.26
.20
.31
.13
.45
B
.11
.13
.10
.12
.13
.10
–
–
–
SE B
B
SE B
.20
.25
.26
.23
.12
.55
–
–
–
2.33*
2.06*
2.11*
2.67*
.99
4.57***
.19
.24
.37
.44
N/A
.11
.12
.09
.09
.14
.22
.45
.42
–
–
b
t-value
b
1.76†
2.00*
3.95***
4.63***
–
–
t-value
.21
.22
.37
.43
.05
.00
N/A
B
.11
.12
.09
.10
.08
.07
SE B
.16
.20
.45
.41
.07
.00
b
STEP 3
1.88†
1.77†
3.97***
4.48***
.65
.04
t-value
Note. For Justice as dependent variable (D.V.), R2 = .26, F(3, 101) = 11.51; for Forgiveness, in Step 1: R2 = .26, F(3, 101) = 11.94; in Step 2: R2 = .39, F(4,
100) = 16.12; in Step 3: R2 = .40, F(6, 98) = 10.72.
†
p < .10; *p < .05; **p < .01; ***p < .001.
Forgiveness
Predictor
D.V.
STEP 2
STEP 1
Table 1. Hierarchical regression results for dependent measures (Study 1)
470
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
Justice and forgiveness
471
finding may reflect actual relationships, however, it could also be an artefact of the
correlational design of the study. The presumed measured moderators – retributive and
restorative response – were not designed to be mutually exclusive and were indeed
strongly correlated, limiting their distinctive variance and capacity to differentially
moderate the effects of justice. Generally, it has been argued that moderation effects are
more difficult to detect in correlational studies (McClelland & Judd, 1993), which is why
we employed experimental designs next.
STUDY 2
By drawing on participants’ real-life experiences, Study 1 benefits from high ecological
validity, but it is limited in internal validity. The correlational data do not permit causal
inferences. Therefore, in Study 2 we offer a complimentary experimental test of the same
predictions, this time using a scenario methodology that allows for causal interpretations.
Method
Participants and design
Participants were 140 Australian university students (66% female students, age M = 24.2,
SD = 7.62). They were randomly allocated to a 3-cell experimental design: retributive
response, restorative response, or inaction (control).
Materials
Participants completed a paper/pencil questionnaire. They were asked to imagine that
another student, Sarah, had stolen their study notes days before the examination, and that
University Student Services handled their formal complaint. The scenarios varied in
whether the complaint was resolved through retributive or restorative processes (based
on theoretical conceptualizations and experimental manipulations used by Wenzel et al.,
2010), versus inaction. The student services administrator called in both students for a
meeting. In the retributive response condition the administrator unilaterally imposed a
punishment on the offender:
[He] tells the two of you that, after carefully weighing the implications of the offence and how
it has affected you, he has made an objective decision about what he believes to be
appropriate punishment. He also explains to Sarah that she had no choice in the matter but to
accept her punishment.
In the restorative response condition, offender and victim engaged in a dialogue to come
to a shared understanding and bilateral solution:
[He] encourages both you and Sarah to engage in a discussion about the incident. Both of you
express your feelings and views about the situation. Eventually, you both come to an
agreement about appropriate student conduct. You seem to reach a shared understanding
about the implications of the offence and how it has affected you, and you also reach an
agreement about Sarah’s punishment.
The punishment was the same in both conditions (an unpaid service to the university). In
contrast, in the control condition participants were told they received an email from student
services saying that ‘because there is no proof, nothing can be done about the situation.’
472
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
Seriousness
Prior to the experimental manipulation, participants rated the seriousness of the incident
on two items: ‘What happened in this situation was really no big deal’ (reverse-coded), and
‘What happened in this situation was very serious’ (1 = strongly disagree, 7 = strongly
agree). The two items were highly correlated (r = .72) and responses were averaged.
Justice
We used seven items to measure feelings of justice similar to Study 1 (a = .91).
Forgiveness
We measured forgiveness with the 18-item Transgression-Related Interpersonal Motivations Scale (TRIM-18; McCullough et al., 2006). It taps into three aspects of forgiveness:
lack of revenge (e.g., ‘Somehow, I’ll make Sarah pay’, reverse-coded), lack of avoidance
(e.g., ‘I will try to keep as much distance between us as possible’, reverse-coded) and
benevolence (e.g., ‘Even though Sarah’s actions hurt me, I have goodwill for her’;
1 = strongly disagree, 7 = strongly agree). Analyses indicated no notable differences
among the three aspects of forgiveness, so for parsimony all 18 items were averaged into a
single forgiveness score (a = .88).
Results
The level of seriousness attributed to the offence did not differ among the three
experimental conditions, F(2, 137) = .21, p = .814. Overall, the participants rated the
transgression as very serious (M = 6.05, SD = 1.12) and clearly different from the scale
mid-point, t(139) = 21.67, p < .001. Forgiveness and justice were positively correlated at
r = .38.
We again used multiple regression techniques to test our predictions (see Table 2 and
Figure 1). We created two dummy-coded variables to represent the retributive and
restorative response conditions, treating the control condition as the reference group.
Diagnostics indicated no problems of multicollinearity at any of the following steps
(Tolerance >.11, Condition Index = 8.11). First, we tested for the effects of retributive
and restorative responses on feelings of justice. Both retributive and restorative responses
had a significant positive effect on justice perceptions. Second, we conducted a
hierarchical regression for forgiveness, including retributive and restorative responses in
the first step, and adding perceptions of justice as a predictor in a second step. In Step 1, a
retributive response had no significant effect, while a restorative response had a
significant positive effect on forgiveness. In Step 2, justice perceptions were significantly
positively related to forgiveness; when controlling for the mediating effect of justice, the
positive effect of the restorative response was no longer significant, and a marginally
significant negative effect of retributive response was revealed. Bootstrapping techniques
for testing specific indirect effects with small samples (Preacher & Hayes, 2008) showed
that the restorative response had a significant indirect effect on forgiveness through
feelings of justice, B = .57, SE = .18 (95% CI = 0.25–0.97). There was likewise a
significant indirect effect for the retributive response, B = .43, SE = .12 (95% CI = 0.22–
0.71). Importantly, similar to Study 1, the indirect effect for the restorative response
translated into (or partially accounted for) a significant total effect, whereas the significant
indirect effect of retributive justice was counteracted by a (marginal) negative direct effect
Retributive response
Restorative response
Retributive response
Restorative response
Justice
Retributive 9 Justice
Restorative 9 Justice
Justice
1.71
2.23
.01
.83
B
.25
.25
.21
.21
B
SE B
.52
.69
.01
.36
–
–
–
6.87***
9.00***
.07
3.94***
–
–
–
.42
.26
.26
N/A
.23
.25
.07
.18
.11
.36
–
–
b
t-value
b
SE B
1.80†
1.03
3.67***
–
–
t-value
.64
.06
.48
.40
.19
N/A
B
.29
.30
.16
.20
.19
SE B
.28
.03
.68
.27
.17
b
STEP 3
2.22*
.20
3.05**
2.02*
1.03
t-value
Note. For Justice as dependent variable (D.V.), R2 = .39, F(2, 137) = 44.50; for Forgiveness, in Step 1: R2 = .13, F(2, 137) = 10.06; in Step 2: R2 = .21, F(3,
136) = 11.82; in Step 3: R2 = .23, F(5, 134) = 8.07.
†
p < .10; *p < .05; **p < .01; ***p < .001.
Forgiveness
Predictor
D.V.
STEP 2
STEP 1
Table 2. Hierarchical regression results for dependent measures (Study 2)
Justice and forgiveness
473
474
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
Retributive
Response
–.28* (.01)
Forgiveness
**
–.03 (.36 )
Restorative
Response
***
.69
Control = .68**
Retributive response = .12
Restorative response = .41**
.52***
Feelings of
Justice
Figure 1. Study 2. Direct and indirect effects of justice response on forgiveness (total effects in
parentheses).
of the retributive response that resulted in a non-significant total effect of retributive
justice.
In a final, third step of the hierarchical regression we added the two-way interactions
between perceived justice and the two experimental conditions. The Justice 9 Retributive
response interaction was significant, whereas the Justice 9 Restorative response interaction was not (see Table 2, right-hand column). Probing the significant interaction effect
showed that the simple effect of justice was significant and positive in the control condition,
b = .68, p = .003, and the restorative response condition, b = .41, p = .005, but not
significant in the retributive response condition, b = .12, p = .489. Thus, while perceptions of justice were overall positively related to forgiveness, this was in fact only true in the
control and restorative response conditions, but not when the response was retributive.
Given the significant moderation of the justice-forgiveness link, we next investigated
its implications for the mediation effects, using an integrated analytical approach that
combines tests for moderation and mediation effects. We used the PROCESS macro by
Hayes (2012; Model 74) to test the model where an independent variable moderates the
relationship between mediator and outcome variable and, thus, moderates its own
indirect effect (see Model 1 in Preacher, Rucker, & Hayes, 2007). The results for the
complete model were identical with those reported in Step 3 above (see Table 2).
Furthermore, the analysis provided bootstrap tests of the conditional indirect effects that
illustrate the moderated mediation: The indirect effect of retributive response (under the
condition of a retributive response being administered) was in fact not significant,
B = .14, SE = .25 (95% CI = 0.37–0.58).2 In contrast, the conditional indirect effect of
restorative response via perceived justice on forgiveness was significant, B = .64,
SE = .22 (95% CI = 0.28–1.15).
Discussion
Study 2 replicated the basic findings of Study 1, allowing for a causal interpretation of the
relationships. A restorative response led to greater forgiveness, mediated by perceptions
of justice. A retributive response also led to greater justice and thus indirectly to greater
forgiveness, but this appeared to be counteracted by a negative direct effect on
forgiveness. However, the experimental design of Study 2 also permitted a test of the
2
The effect of retributive response was only significant under the moderating condition that no such response was administered,
which is of course paradoxical and not meaningful, B = .82, SE = .27 (95% CI = 0.33–0.39). The interpretational difficulty of
the moderated indirect effects is a peculiarity of the case where dichotomous variables act as independent variable and moderator
at the same time. In this situation, only one of the conditional indirect effects is meaningful (A. F. Hayes, personal communication, 7
February 2013).
Justice and forgiveness
475
possibility that subjective feelings of justice do not necessarily mean the same thing when
participants arrive at these through different responses. Specifically, justice perceptions
derived from restorative responses (as well as, here, inaction) appear to facilitate
forgiveness, while justice perceptions deriving from retributive responses do not. As a
consequence, only restorative, but not retributive, responses indirectly facilitated
forgiveness via the restoration of a sense of justice.
STUDY 3
In Studies 1 and 2, we operationalized restorative justice as the seeking and achieving of a
shared consensus about the wrongdoing and its consequences. While true to its
theoretical conceptualization (Wenzel et al., 2008), such consensus-building may involve
complex processes that make it quite different from a single act such as punishment. In
Study 3, we therefore focused instead on a single restorative act that has the potential to
contribute to consensus: an apology. While a full apology may contain a greater number of
elements, such as an expression of concern for the victim, or the offer of repair (e.g.,
Goffman, 1967; Scher & Darley, 1997; Schlenker & Darby, 1981), at the core of an apology
is an acknowledgement of wrongdoing and expression of remorse (Lazare, 2004), which
is also how it was operationalized in this study. An apology signals an endorsement of the
victim’s moral position, promoting a consensus constitutive of restorative justice
(Okimoto et al., 2008); indeed, research has shown that a victim’s desire for an apology is
correlated with a restorative understanding of justice (Okimoto et al., 2012). As we
argued earlier, restorative responses facilitate forgiveness through feelings of justice,
partly explaining why apologies tend to elicit forgiveness in victims (e.g., Darby &
Schlenker, 1989; McCullough et al., 1997).
The focus on apology also allows us to further distinguish between two possible forms
of restoration. On the one hand, an apology may contribute to a consensus between victim
and offender, which presumably communicates that the offender reaffirms and is
committed to the violated values, repairing the identity between these two parties and
motivating victims to forgive. On the other hand, an apology that is issued by a third party,
such as representatives of the group to which offender and victim belong, may also
socially validate the violated values; by siding with the victim, the group might be seen to
reaffirm the values and thus alleviate the victim’s concerns (see also Eaton, Struthers, &
Santelli, 2006). However, a third-party apology does not imply a consensus with the
offender; in fact, it might indicate a distancing of the group from the offender. Stated
simply, consensus can be achieved while being either inclusive or exclusive of the
offender (Okimoto & Wenzel, 2009), and it is an empirical question whether or not it is a
specific type of consensus that motivates forgiveness. Hence, in Study 3 we included a
third-party apology and an offender apology to distinguish the social validation of values
with and without offender consensus.
Method
Participants and design
Participants were 314 U.S. residents who took part in an online study (64% female
participants, age M = 35.6, SD = 11.81). They were randomly allocated to a four-cell
experimental design: retributive response, third-party apology, offender apology, or
inaction (control).
476
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
Materials
Participants were asked to imagine they were an employee in a large advertising agency
and that another employee, Jason, falsely claimed credit for a successful marketing
campaign that, participants were told, was actually theirs. The supervisor quickly
understood that Jason blatantly lied. The company did not want to fire him, but put an
incident report in his employee record. In the control condition, there was no further
action beyond this report.
In addition, in the retributive response condition, Jason ‘was assigned to the least
popular project at the company’ and ‘was also put on ‘probation’ in the company’ having
to undergo a disciplinary review in 6 months’ time to get off probation.
Alternatively, in the third-party apology condition, ‘your supervisor made a point to
call you into his office and personally apologize for what happened in the situation’,
saying, ‘I’m actually really embarrassed about the fact that Jason almost got away with his
lie. I am sincerely sorry about what happened – the whole management team is’.
Finally, in the offender-apology condition, ‘Jason (the offender) made a point to call
you into his office and personally apologize for what happened in the situation’, saying,
‘I’m actually really embarrassed about the fact that I tried to get away with lying. I am
sincerely sorry about what happened’.
Seriousness
Prior to the experimental conditions (i.e., the different resolutions of the situation),
participants rated the seriousness of the incident on a single item: ‘How serious was this
incident?’ (1 = not at all serious, 7 = extremely serious).
Justice
Six items measured feelings of justice and satisfaction with the resolution (e.g., ‘I am very
satisfied with the situation as it now stands’, ‘My sense of fairness has been satisfied’;
1 = strongly disagree, 7 = strongly agree). The item responses were averaged to obtain
scale scores (a = .92).
Forgiveness
We measured forgiveness with nine items that tapped into lack of revenge (five items
based on TRIM-18; McCullough et al., 2006; e.g., ‘I’m going to get even’, reverse-coded)
and express forgiveness (four items based on Okimoto et al., 2012; ‘I forgive the offender
for what he did to me’, ‘I would offer my willingness to forgive the offender’, ‘I want to
explain to the offender that I wish to settle the incident and move on’, and ‘I would want
the offender to know that if the harm can be repaired, it can be forgiven’); items were
averaged into a single score (a = .84).
Results
The level of seriousness attributed to the offence did not differ among the three
experimental conditions, F(3, 311) = .30, p = .828. Overall, the participants rated the
transgression as very serious (M = 6.18, SD = 0.96) and clearly different from the scale
mid-point, t(314) = 40.51, p < .001. Forgiveness and justice were positively correlated at
r = .34.
Justice and forgiveness
477
We used multiple regression techniques to test our predictions (see Table 3 and
Figure 2). We dummy-coded the experimental conditions and treated the control
condition as reference group. Diagnostics indicated no problems of multicollinearity at
any of the following steps (Tolerance >.34, Condition Index = 4.12). First, we tested for
the effects of retributive response, third-party apology and offender apology on feelings of
justice. All three led to greater feelings of justice compared to the control condition.
Second, we conducted a hierarchical regression for forgiveness, including retributive
response, third-party apology and offender apology in the first step, and adding
perceptions of justice as a predictor in a second step. In Step 1, a retributive response
and third-party apology showed no significant effect, while an offender apology had a
significant positive effect on forgiveness. In Step 2, justice perceptions were significantly
positively related to forgiveness; and when including justice the positive effect of
restorative justice was diminished (although still significant), while the effects for
retributive response and third-party apology were still non-significant, although now with
a negative sign. Bootstrapping techniques for testing specific indirect effects (Preacher &
Hayes, 2008) showed that the restorative response had a significant positive indirect effect
on forgiveness through feelings of justice, B = .16, SE = .07 (95% CI = 0.04–0.30). There
was likewise a significant positive indirect effect for the retributive response, B = .18,
SE = .07 (95% CI = 0.06–0.37) and for third-party apology, B = .23, SE = .07 (95%
CI = 0.12–0.39). Similar to Studies 1 and 2, however, the indirect effect for the restorative
response translated into (or partially accounted for) a significant total effect, whereas this
was not the case for retributive justice or third-party apology.
Finally, in Step 3 of the hierarchical regression, we added the two-way interactions
between perceived justice and the three experimental conditions (see Table 2, right-hand
column). The Justice 9 Retributive response interaction was not significant, although
the apparent negative trend was consistent with Study 2. In contrast, the Justice 9 Thirdparty apology interaction was marginally significant and positive, and the Justice 9 Offender apology interaction was significant and positive. Probing these interaction effects (see Figure 2) showed that the simple effect of justice was positive and the
strongest in the offender apology condition, b = .70, p < .001, and similarly strongly
positive in the third-party apology condition, b = .49, p < .001; both were, as implied by
the interaction effects, stronger than in the control condition, b = .26, p = .003, while the
relationship between justice and forgiveness was not significant in the retributive
response condition, b = .06, p = .574.
We used again Hayes’s (2012) PROCESS macro (Model 74) for a combined analysis of
moderation and mediation. The results for the complete model were identical with those
reported in Step 3 above (see Table 3). Bootstrap tests of the conditional indirect effects
showed that, taking the moderated nature of the link between justice and forgiveness into
account, the indirect effect of offender apology was indeed significant, B = .32, SE = .14
(95% CI = 0.08–0.63). Similarly, the indirect effect of group apology was significant,
B = .33, SE = .11 (95% CI = 0.15–0.58). In contrast, the indirect effect of retributive
response via perceived justice on forgiveness was not significant, B = .03, SE = .10 (95%
CI = 0.13–0.26).
Discussion
Replicating Studies 1 and 2, a restorative response (here in the form of an offender
apology) led to greater forgiveness, partially mediated by perceptions of justice.
Retributive response
Third-party apology
Offender apology
Retributive response
Third-party apology
Offender apology
Justice
Retributive 9 Justice
Third-party A. 9 Justice
Offender A. 9 Justice
Justice
.58
.76
.51
.11
.18
.54
B
.20
.19
.21
.18
.17
.19
–
–
–
–
B
SE B
.19
.26
.16
.04
.07
.19
–
–
–
–
2.90**
3.94***
2.43*
.60
1.05
2.85**
.07
.05
.39
.31
N/A
.17
.17
.18
.05
.03
.02
.13
.35
–
–
–
b
t-value
b
SE B
.41
.31
2.13*
6.39***
–
–
–
t-value
.01
.06
.41
.23
.18
.21
.39
N/A
B
.17
.17
.18
.08
.13
.12
.14
SE B
.00
.02
.14
.26
.09
.12
.17
b
STEP 3
.03
.33
2.26*
2.96**
1.37
1.70†
2.76**
t-value
Note. For Justice as dependent variable (D.V.), R2 = .05, F(3, 311) = 5.62; for Forgiveness, in Step 1: R2 = .03, F(3, 311) = 2.91; in Step 2: R2 = .14, F(4, 310) = 12.66;
in Step 3: R2 = .18, F(7, 307) = 9.86.
†
p < .10; *p < .05; **p < .01; ***p < .001.
Forgiveness
Predictor
D.V.
STEP 2
STEP 1
Table 3. Hierarchical regression results for dependent measures (Study 3)
478
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
Justice and forgiveness
Retributive
Response
479
–.00(.04)
–.02(.07)
Third-party
apology
*
Forgiveness
**
.14 (.19 )
Offender
apology
.16*
***
.26
**
.19
Control = .26**
Retributive response = .06
Third-party apology = .49***
Offender apology = .70***
Feelings of
Justice
Figure 2. Study 3. Direct and indirect effects of justice response on forgiveness (total effects in
parentheses).
Third-party apology and retribution – responses that were not inclusive of the offender –
did not lead to greater forgiveness even though they both also increased perceptions of
justice. Consistent with Study 2, the relationship between justice and forgiveness also
depended on the response from which those feelings of justice derived. The relationship
was stronger when an apology was the response, irrespective of whether the apology was
offered by the offender or a third party. This suggests that social validation of the violated
values, which is an element of both offender and third-party apology, is key to a kind of
justice experience that is conducive to forgiveness. However, inclusion of the offender in
the value consensus, which characterizes an offender apology, seems to be critical for a
positive direct effect that adds to the indirect effect via justice, producing a significant
total effect of offender apology on forgiveness. In contrast, although not significant, the
direct effects tended to be negative (and thus neutralizing any indirect effects) for a thirdparty apology and retributive response, both of which imply an absence of a consensus
with the offender and may even imply a distancing from, or social exclusion of, the
offender.
GENERAL DISCUSSION
This research challenges the theoretical views that forgiveness requires victims to
sacrifice justice (Aquino et al., 2003; Exline et al., 2000), or that achieving justice
promotes forgiveness (Exline et al., 2003; Tripp et al., 2007; Worthington, 2006). In
contrast, the current results suggest that both may be true, but that the relationship
between justice and forgiveness depends on the way that justice was achieved. Although a
restored sense of justice is overall positively related to forgiveness, not all means of justice
restoration increased forgiveness.
Consistent with the injustice gap and the vigilante model of justice, restorative
responses (consensus-seeking or more unilateral offender apologies) increased forgiveness indirectly by restoring justice, as well as directly (in Studies 1 and 3). This direct effect
suggests that inclusive and consensus-building restorative responses imply a common
identity that facilitates forgiveness (Wenzel et al., 2010; Wohl & Branscombe, 2005).
However, we did not measure identity in this research and this therefore remains
speculation; this direct effect might merely represent a residual effect due to incomplete
mediation caused by methodological limitations and should therefore be interpreted with
caution.
480
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
In contrast, inconsistent with the notion of injustice gap and the vigilante model of
justice, retributive responses did not lead to greater forgiveness. Although they did help to
restore a sense of justice and, thus, apparently indirectly increased forgiveness, this
indirect effect seemed to be counteracted by negative direct effects. Although the direct
effect of the retributive response was not significant in Study 3, additional processes
prevented the indirect effect from translating into a significant total effect. Again, we can
only speculate what these processes might be in the absence of evidence showing
alternate mediating mechanisms. However, on the basis of justice restoration theory
(Okimoto et al., 2008; Wenzel et al., 2008) we would argue that retributive responses
imply a competitive relationship, a negative interdependence over status/power
restoration, and/or a symbolic distancing of the offender, which undermine feelings of
forgiveness.
However, a further key to why retributive responses did not seem to promote
forgiveness lies in the finding that the relationship between justice and forgiveness was
not the same for all means of justice restoration. While we did not find a moderation of
the justice-forgiveness link in Study 1, this may be due to the correlational design of the
study where the presumed measured moderators – retributive and restorative response –
were strongly correlated. In Studies 2 and 3, where the presumed moderators were
manipulated and thus independent from another, we found that forgiveness was
positively related to justice feelings that derived from a restorative response, but
unrelated to justice feelings that derived from retributive responses. These results
support the theoretical distinction between retributive and restorative justice (Wenzel
et al., 2008), where only the latter, being based on the renewal of consensus about
relevant values, is conducive to forgiveness. Once we take into account that the meaning
of justice depends on the means of its restoration, the evidence shows that only
restorative responses, but not retributive responses, facilitate forgiveness indirectly
through feelings of justice.
While from our theoretical perspective restorative justice has forgiveness-promoting
effects because it implies a value consensus between victim and offender, a shared recommitment to the violated values, there may be alternative theoretical explanations. For
example, according to the needs-based model of reconciliation (Shnabel & Nadler, 2008),
victims experience an impairment of their sense of power, and restoration of their power
would foster their willingness to reconcile. It is conceivable, albeit speculative at this
point, that restorative justice affords a greater sense of victim empowerment, whereas
retributive justice merely implies offender disempowerment. While both might help to rebalance the scales of power and increase perceptions of justice in victims, it might be that
only justice through victim empowerment leads to more forgiveness (Wenzel & Okimoto,
2010).
It may be noted that the moderation pattern appeared to differ between Studies 2
and 3, with the retributive response being the significant moderator of the justiceforgiveness relationship in Study 2, but the restorative response being the moderator in
Study 3. However, the reason for this difference was actually the control condition,
which provided a different baseline in the two studies (see Figures 1 and 2): in Study 2
there was a stronger significant relationship between justice and forgiveness than in
Study 3. It is possible that in Study 2 the default relationship was cooperative (the
offender was a fellow student), while in Study 3 the default relationship was
competitive (co-worker vying for organizational status). In other words, the difference
between retributive and restorative was very similar between the studies, but the
control condition moved.
Justice and forgiveness
481
Study 3 also included a third-party apology as a response, which is a kind of hybrid
response as it involves the social validation of values (like an offender apology) but not
with, and by implication perhaps against, the offender (like a third-party punishment).
Interestingly, the results showed a similar moderation of the justice-forgiveness
relationship as for offender apology, but the absence of a total effect on forgiveness as
for the retributive response. The latter again might be due to the symbolic exclusion (or
non-inclusion) of the offender, which diminishes a shared identity that would facilitate
forgiveness. The significant moderation effect suggests that the social validation of values
(with or without the offender) is crucial for the justice experience to be conducive for
forgiveness. This is consistent with findings that third-party communications that
acknowledge the wrong-doing can facilitate forgiveness through providing validation and
indicating social consensus (Eaton et al., 2006; Wenzel & Coughlin, 2012). It is possible
that victims who see the violated values socially validated feel less need to demonstrate
unforgiveness towards the offender, less need to demonstrate indignation as a symbolic
reassertion of those values.
A limitation of this research is that it did not include an equivalent differentiation
between retributive responses inflicted by the victim (i.e., revenge) versus retributive
responses inflicted by a third party. The measure in Study 1 included items of both kinds
of retributive response, whereas the experimental manipulations in Studies 2 and 3
focused on third-party punishment only. It is possible that victim-inflicted revenge and
third-party punishment have quite different implications. For example, a victim might
experience an act of revenge as cognitively inconsistent with the idea of a subsequent
opposite act of forgiveness. In contrast, when a punishment is imposed by a third party,
victims might not see any contradiction in their own behaviour; they might even start to
feel sympathy for the suffering offender and therefore feel more forgiveness towards the
offender. However, from this perspective Studies 2 and 3, focusing on third-party
punishment, offered a conservative test of our predictions; and there was no evidence
for a sympathy effect, or any beneficial effect of punishment for that matter, on
forgiveness.
While the hypothetical nature of Studies 2 and 3 represents a limitation, the recall of
real-life events in Study 1 provides complementary evidence. On the other hand, Study 1 is
limited by its correlational design, which does not allow causal inferences and, with the
presumed moderators being strongly correlated, is sub-optimal for the detection of
distinct moderation effects. However, the experimental designs of Studies 2 and 3 make
up for these weaknesses. The consistency across different methods, scenarios, measures
of forgiveness and restorative versus retributive responses should also add confidence in
the generalizability of the findings. Moreover, the complex pattern of results speaks
against the possible criticism that the scenario studies constituted a transparent
methodology, in which the participants merely responded on the basis of their lay
theories.
In sum, regarding the relationship between justice and forgiveness, not all forms of
justice are made equal. A sense of justice restored through restorative responses promotes
forgiveness, but justice restored through retributive responses does not.
Acknowledgement
This research was supported by a grant from the Australian Research Council,
DP0877309.
482
Michael Wenzel and Tyler G. Okimoto
References
Aquino, K., Grover, S. L., Goldman, B., & Folger, R. (2003). When push doesn’t come to shove:
Interpersonal forgiveness in workplace relationships. Journal of Management Inquiry, 12,
209–216. doi:10.1177/1056492603256337
Boon, S. D., & Sulsky, L. M. (1997). Attributions of blame and forgiveness in romantic relationships: A
policy-capturing study. Journal of Social Behavior & Personality, 12, 19–44.
Darby, B. W., & Schlenker, B. R. (1989). Children’s reactions to transgressions: Effects of the actor’s
apology, reputation and remorse. British Journal of Social Psychology, 28, 353–364. doi:10.
1111/j.2044-8309.1989.tb00879.x
Eaton, J., Struthers, C., & Santelli, A. G. (2006). The mediating role of perceptual validation in the
repentance-forgiveness process. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32, 1389–1401.
doi:10.1177/0146167206291005
Exline, J. J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2000). Expressing forgiveness and repentance: Benefits and
barriers. In M. E. McCullough, K. I. Pargament, & C. E. Thoresen (Eds.), Forgiveness: Theory,
research, and practice (pp. 133–155). New York, UK: Guilford.
Exline, J. J., Worthington, E. L., Jr, Hill, P., & McCullough, M. E. (2003). Forgiveness and justice: A
research agenda for social and personality psychology. Personality and Social Psychology
Review, 7, 337–348. doi:10.1207/S15327957PSPR0704_06
Fehr, R., Gelfand, M. J., & Nag, M. (2010). The road to forgiveness: A meta-analytic synthesis of its
situational and dispositional correlates. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 894–914. doi:10.1037/
a0019993
Goffman, E. (1967). Interaction ritual: Essays on face-to-face interaction. Oxford, UK: Aldine.
Hayes, A. F. (2012). PROCESS: A versatile computational tool for observed variable mediation,
moderation, and conditional process modeling [White paper]. Retrieved from http://www.
afhayes.com/public/process2012.pdf
Hogan, R., & Emler, N. P.. (1981). Retributive justice. In M. J. Lerner & S. C. Lerner (Eds.), The justice
motive in social behavior (pp. 125–144). New York, UK: Academic Press.
Karremans, J. C., & Van Lange, P. A. (2005). Does activating justice help or hurt in promoting
forgiveness? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 41, 290–297. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.
2004.06.005
Lazare, A. (2004). On apology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
McClelland, G. H., & Judd, C. M. (1993). Statistical difficulties of detecting interactions and
moderator effects. Psychological Bulletin, 114, 376–390. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.114.2.376
McCullough, M. E., Rachal, K. C., Sandage, S. J., Worthington, E. L., Jr, Brown, S. W., & Hight, T. L.
(1998). Interpersonal forgiving in close relationships: II. Theoretical elaboration and
measurement. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 1586–1603. doi:10.1037/
0022-3514/75.6.1586
McCullough, M. E., Root, L. M., & Cohen, A. D. (2006). Writing about the benefits of an interpersonal
transgression facilitates forgiveness. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 74, 887–
897. doi:10.1037/0022-006X.74.5.887
McCullough, M. E., Worthington, E. L., Jr, & Rachal, K. C. (1997). Interpersonal forgiving in close
relationships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 321–336. doi:10.1037/00223514.73.2.321
Okimoto, T. G., & Wenzel, M. (2008). The symbolic meaning of transgressions: Towards a unifying
framework of justice restoration. In K. Hegtvedt & J. Clay-Warner (Eds.), Advances in group
processes (pp. 291–326). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Okimoto, T. G., & Wenzel, M. (2009). Punishment as restoration of group and offender values
following a transgression: Value consensus through symbolic labelling and offender reform.
European Journal of Social Psychology, 39, 346–367. doi:10.1002/ejsp.537
Okimoto, T. G., Wenzel, M., & Feather, N. T. (2012). Retribution and restoration as general
orientations toward justice. European Journal of Personality, 26, 255–275. doi:10.1002/per.
831
Justice and forgiveness
483
Okimoto, T. G., Wenzel, M., & Platow, M. J. (2010). Restorative justice: Seeking a shared identity in
dynamic intra-group contexts. In E. Mannix, M. Neale, & E. Mullen (Eds.), Research on
managing groups and teams: Fairness and groups (Vol. 13, pp. 205–242). Bingley, UK:
Emerald.
Preacher, K. J., & Hayes, A. F. (2008). Asymptotic and resampling strategies for assessing and
comparing indirect effects in multiple mediator models. Behavior Research Methods, 40, 879–
891. doi:10.3758/BRM.40.3.879
Preacher, K. J., Rucker, D. D., & Hayes, A. F. (2007). Addressing moderated mediation hypotheses:
Theory, methods, and prescriptions. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 42, 185–227. doi:10.
1080/00273170701341316
Scher, S. J., & Darley, J. M. (1997). How effective are the things people say to apologize? Effects of the
realization of the apology speech act Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 26, 127–140. doi:10.
1023/A:1025068306386
Schlenker, B. R., & Darby, B. W. (1981). The use of apologies in social predicaments. Social
Psychology Quarterly, 44, 271–278.
Shnabel, N., & Nadler, A. (2008). A needs-based model of reconciliation: Satisfying the differential
emotional needs of victim and perpetrator as a key to promoting reconciliation. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 116–132. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.94.1.116
Strelan, P., Feather, N., & McKee, I. (2008). Justice and forgiveness: Experimental evidence for
compatibility. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 1538–1544. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.
2008.07.014
Strelan, P., Feather, N., & McKee, I. (2011). Retributive and inclusive justice goals and forgiveness:
The influence of motivational values. Social Justice Research, 24, 126–142. doi:10.1007/s11211011-0132-9
Tripp, T. M., Bies, R. J., & Aquino, K. (2007). A vigilante model of justice: Revenge, reconciliation,
forgiveness, and avoidance. Social Justice Research, 20, 10–34. doi:10.1007/s11211-007-0030-3
Wenzel, M., & Coughlin, A.-M. (2012, April). Third-party communications and forgiveness. Paper
presented at the 41st annual conference of the Society of Australasian Social Psychologists
(SASP), Adelaide, Australia.
Wenzel, M., & Okimoto, T. G. (2010). How acts of forgiveness restore a sense of justice: Addressing
status/power and value concerns raised by transgressions. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 40, 401–417. doi:10.1002/ejsp.629
Wenzel, M., & Okimoto, T. G. (2012). The varying meaning of forgiveness: Relationship closeness as
a moderator of forgiveness effects on feelings of justice. European Journal of Social Psychology,
42, 420–431. doi:10.1002/ejsp.1850
Wenzel, M., Okimoto, T. G., Feather, N. T., & Platow, M. J. (2008). Retributive and restorative justice.
Law and Human Behavior, 32, 375–389. doi:10.1007/s10979-007-9116-6
Wenzel, M., Okimoto, T. G., Feather, N. T., & Platow, M. J. (2010). Justice through consensus: Shared
identity and the preference for a restorative notion of justice. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 40, 909–930. doi:10.1002/ejsp.657
Wohl, M. J. A., & Branscombe, N. R. (2005). Forgiveness and collective guilt assignment to historical
perpetrator groups depend on level of social category inclusiveness. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 88, 288–303. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.88.2.288
Worthington, E. L. (2006). Forgiveness and reconciliation: Theory and application. New York,
UK: Routledge.
Received 12 June 2012; revised version received 2 May 2013
Download