Linguistic Society of America Definiteness and Existentials Author(s): Barbara Abbott Source: Language, Vol. 73, No. 1 (Mar., 1997), pp. 103-108 Published by: Linguistic Society of America Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/416595 Accessed: 17-10-2015 20:01 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Linguistic Society of America is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Language. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DISCUSSION NOTE Definiteness and Existentials BARBARAABBOTT Michigan State University Prince 1992reanalyzedthe informationstatus of NPs into two cross-cutting distinctions,one between NPs denotingentities that are new or old with respect to the discourse and another between NPs denoting entities that, in the speaker'sestimation,are new or old with respect to the addressee.The category of HEARER-NEW NPs, equivalent to the category 'brand-new' of Prince 1981, contains NPs denotingentities that the speaker assumes to be unknownto the addressee. The hearer-oldcategory contrasts with discourse-old in including discourse-newNPs that denote entities the speakerassumes to be in the addressee's long termmemorystore; 'in the permanentregistry'(Kuno 1972), 'culturally copresent' (Clark and Marshall 1981), 'unused' (Prince 1981), are other descriptionsof similar ideas cited by Prince (1992: 301-2). Hence discourseold NPs are assumed to be a subset of hearer-oldNPs ('since hearers are expected to rememberwhat they have been told' (Prince 1992:303)), but a proper subset.* Princefoundthat (morphologicallydefined)definitenessin NPs largelycorrelates with their being hearer-old.This reflects the familiarityaspect of definiteness. Princenotedin passing, however, thatnot all definitesare hearer-old.1She hadalreadyacknowledgedthe abilityof definitesto occur in there-sentences,as in l. (1) a. There were the same people at both conferences. [= Prince 1992, ex. Sa] b. There was the usual crowd at the beach. [= Prince 1992, ex. Sb] c. There was the stupidestarticleon the readinglist. f= Prince 1992, ex. 5c] In discussing these examples she remarked, 'There-sentencesdo not require indefinite NPs at all: rather, they require Hearer-new NPs' (302). In la, for example, it is presumablyuniqueness (instead of familiarity)that licenses the definite article in the same people, while hearer-newnessis held to license the NP's occurrencein a there-sentence.In 'Definiteness and the English existential', Ward& Birner(WB)attemptto establishthis idea more thoroughly,using a large corpus of naturallyoccurringdata. Serious problemsremain, however. There are three categories of apparentcounterexamplesto the hearer-new principle. Two of these are discussed by WB, who attempt to describe the examples in a way that will make them actually consistent with the principle. * I am grateful to Larry Horn, Ellen Prince, and two anonymous referees for their comments on earlier drafts of this note. 1 This is a reflection, in part, of the uniqueness aspect of definiteness. See Birner & Ward 1994 for an excellent discussion of the problems of finding a satisfactory unified characterization of definiteness in English. 103 This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LANGUAGE, VOLUME 73, NUMBER 1 (1997) 104 I will argue that the resulting notion of hearer-newnesshas diverged significantly from the originalidea. At best this would be misleading.However I will also argue that no notion of hearer-newnessis adequateto account for all the data. The third type of problematic there-sentence, an example of which is cited by WB but not discussed in connection with their analysis, reinforcesthis conclusion. Finally, I'll suggest what I see as the root of the problem. The first problematiccategoryI want to consideris illustratedby the example given in 2. (2) Like voters everywhere, Montanansare in a resentfulmood, andMarlenee is adept at exploitingthat resentment.... To add to his troubles, Williamsused to be chairmanof the subcommitteeoverseeing grants to the National Endowmentfor the Arts, and he firmly defended the agency against charges that it funded 'obscene' art works. That's what won him the supportof Keillor, who said, 'It's a measure of the man when he's courageous when it's not absolutely requiredof him.' But it has inspiredthe oppositionof nationalconservatives, including Pat Robertson, who referredto Williamsas 'PornographyPat.' Then there is that resentment. [Chicago Tribune, 9/4/92; = Ward & Birner 1995, exx. 8c, 14b] Note that the relevant post-verbal NP is not only hearer-old,it is discourseold. Such examples are described by WB as ones in which hearer-oldentities are neverthelessTREATEDAS hearer-new.In supportof this claim WB say 'there are sufficient grounds for the speaker to believe that the entity has been (at least momentarily)forgotten' (730). Let us assume for the moment that this is the case. There would still be a problemwith this analysis in that we are no longer dealingwith Prince's notion of hearer-newness.Thatnotionwas supposedto distinguishentities the speaker assumes are completely unknownto the addressee from those the speaker assumes the addressee to be acquaintedwith. In that view the obvious way to treat an entity as hearer-newwould be to refer to it using an indefinite NP. Indeed, one can treat a hearer-oldentity as hearer-newin this straightforward sense, as when someone coyly says to their roommate, (3) A certain person came by to see you this afternoon. usingan indefiniteNP to referto an entity knownto be knownto the addressee.2 However that is not the case in these examples. On the contrary, we have not only a definite NP, but a demonstrative(that resentment). As WB note, this kind of demonstrativesignals that the entity 'is assumed to be part of the interlocutors' private shared knowledge store, based on prior co-presence (Clark& Marshall1981)'(731). That is, we have an explicit markingof hearerold status in the sense of Prince 1992.The concept of hearer-newnessemployed here in the phrase 'treated as hearer-new' seems instead to concern what is uppermostin the addressee's consciousness, which is clearly quite a different idea from what is in the addressee's permanentmemory store. 2 This type of case is the inverseof whathas been called 'accommodation'(Heim 1983,following Lewis 1979),where a speakertreats a hearer-newentity as hearer-old. This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DISCUSSION NOTE 105 I also want to challenge WB's claim that the NP referents in this type of example must be assumed to have been forgotten even momentarily.In other words, I doubt that the NP referents in this kind of example must be hearernew even in this remindersense of hearer-new.Althoughthis mightbe plausible in the case of 2, there is a problem even in this case: there seems to be no independentmeans of verification.The only concrete evidence we have is the use of the existential sentence itself. The use of the definitein conjunctionwith the there-constructionreflects the treatmentof the referentas simultaneouslyhearer-newand uniquelyidentifiable.Indeed, it is precisely this mixed markingthat leads the hearerto infer that the utteranceis a reminder-that is, that despite the entity's apparentnewness to the hearer,it nonethelessconstitutes sharedknowledge. (Ward & Birner 1995:730-1) But this type of evidence cannot be used prior to the establishment of the correctnessof the hearer-newanalysis, and there are other examples for which the claim of momentaryforgetting is less plausible than it is for 2. Two are given in 4. (4) a. I think there was one flight where we had one problem. It wasn't ours, but there was that one flight. [Challenger commission tran- scripts, 4/2/86; = Ward & Birner 1995, ex. 10] b. The worst one that existed was 10 thousandthson the single 0ring on the Titan, and there are 20 of the five-segment. That was the earliest version. There were four of the seven-segment, which never went into production,but was just a development;and then two five-and-a-halfsegments, which was a way of getting a little additionalperformance.And I believe every one of them flying now is the five-and-a-halfsegment device. And there is not any evidence, but there was this 10 thousandths. [Challenger commission transcripts,2/10/86; = Ward& Birner 1995, ex. 6] Note thatin 4b we have the proximaldemonstrativethis. Accordingto Gundel et al. 1993(278-9), this use of this requiresnot only an assumptionof familiarity to the addressee (which is both necessary and sufficient for that) but also an assumptionof activationfor the referent,i.e. representationin short-termmemory. The only higherrankingcognitive status in the 'givenness hierarchy'proposed by Gundel et al. is the status of being 'in focus', that is, 'at the current center of attention' (279). This suggests that, rather than saying these theresentences are being used to remind addressees of the existence of entities, a better description of their function may be that they are intended to put an entity into focus, in this sense of currentcenter of attention. The other category of there-sentences with hearer-oldNPs cited by WB is the type that have been called LIST EXISTENTIALS in the literature, following Milsark 1974. (5) A: What's on the office desk? B: There's the telephone, but nothingelse. [= Ward& Birner 1995, ex. 31b] At least part of the WB analysis of this kind of sentence seems right on target-specifically, the idea that it requires a salient open proposition as background information.The problem lies in seeing the postverbal NP as hearer- This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LANGUAGE, VOLUME 73. NUMBER 1 (1997) 106 new. WB describe these as instances of 'hearer-oldentities newly instantiating a variable', the variablein this example being the X of the open propositionX is on the office desk. In other words, althoughthe entity in question is not new, its 'membershipin the set being enumeratedis new to the hearer' (Ward & Birner 1995:734). At this point Prince's notion of hearer-newseems to have gotten lost altogether. Thatnotion had to do with acquaintancewith the existence of referents. This notion has to do with given entities possessing properties.It is very hard to makethis kindof example consistent with the claim that 'the there-construction is licensed by the hearer-newstatus of the referent' (Ward& Birner 1995: 729), or with the statementin the conclusion of their paperthat 'the postverbal NP in a there-sentencemust represent an entity which is hearer-new(Prince 1992)'(740). There is no new entity referredto in 5. One might argue that this is just a question of terminology, and that what WB are getting at is a claim that the there-constructionsimply marks hearernewness, sometimes of a discourse entity and sometimes of the instantiation of a variable.On the one handthis is problematicin the weakness of the notion of hearer-newnessinvolved. This certainly could not be what is distinctive about there-sentences,given the commonalityof new informationof this type that sentences in general can express. On the other hand (and more crucially) there are there-sentenceswhich appearnot to convey hearer-newnessof either type, such as the examples above in 4 and the following list-type example. (6) OK, lets finish up this guest list. There's you and me. Who else is coming? The third category of problematicexamples reinforces this conclusion. The constructedexample in 7a, cited by WB, was intendedto call to mindnaturally occurringexamples such as KC's utterancein 7b, and Cathy's utterancein the last panel of 7c. (7) a. A: Don't forget that Kim will be bringinga salad. B: Oh right-there is that [= Abbott 1992, ex. 15; Ward & Birner 1995, ex. 3a] b. CT: It's just not somethingthe MidlandSymphonyis going to be able to pull off. KC: That's true-there is that. LOverheard conversationexplaining the lack of recordingsof a concerto because of the difficulty of the orchestralparts (5/1/96)] c. CATHYBy Cathy Guisewite SNA CRUt1Y ' HE HAS A ROOft1ATEI)rTHA tLE. ULIVES $75 WORTH AhOHAWK... A CO RACKFULOf PAPTRWmTWUTH Of FURN(TUREAND A GROUPSI NEVERHEARDO... SOUND AND HE HIANGS ... AROUNDWUnH IS,O000 SVSTEM A eUCH Of DATLESS 80DY1 / // | BUILDERS (OITH ERRT-TimE OBS e THE V(0?C 7Gs __ STRE ! Jai^| y-- This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DISCUSSION NOTE 107 These examples are similarto the ones in 5 and 6 in the apparentnecessity of a salient open proposition, although the variables here seem to range over situations or factors rather than concrete objects such as people and office machines. But crucially in these cases it is the ADDRESSEEof the there-sentence who has put forwardthe instantiationof the variable.It thus seems impossible either to argue that the referent of that in any of these sentences (i.e. the situationor factor) is new to the addressee, or to argue that the fact that this referent satisfies the salient open proposition is new information.3Note that while the that in each case is in focus position it nevertheless undergoes anaphoricdestressing(forcingmain sentence stress to occur on is so that it cannot be contracted).4A constituentcan be focussed in a sentence withoutbeing new information. There is a more fundamentalissue here, and that is the explanationfor any constraintof the type proposed on postverbalNPs in there-sentences. Neither Prince nor WB go into details about this issue. If one assumed that theresentences had a single function, and that that function was introducingnew entities into the discourse, then such a constraintwould follow naturally.WB do seem to makethis assumptionaboutthe functionof theresentences, although they are not completely explicit. In their concludingremarksthey state that WHILE MANY HAVE ATTEMPTED TO CAPTURE THE INTUITION THAT THERE-SENTENCES SERVE TO INTRODUCE A NEW REFERENT INTO THE DISCOURSE, all have failed to adequatelycharacterizethe discrepancy between the felicity conditions on there-sentences and those on definiteness. (Ward & Birner 1995; 740, emphasis added.) However the examples above show that there-sentences do not all have this function. It may be a mistaketo thinkthat there-sentenceshave only one function of this type. Makingthe addressee aware of the existence (or absence) of entities, introducingthem into the discourse, drawingthe addressee's attention to their presence (or absence), or even simply acknowledgingthe existence of certain entities, are all possible functions served by there-sentences. Thus it may not be the case that any single discourse-basedprinciplecan account for the distributionof NPs in this construction, but in any case certainly not a principlerequiringthe postverbalNP to representan entity that is hearer-new. REFERENCES ABBOTT, BARBARA. 1992. Definiteness, existentials, and the 'list' interpretation.Proceedings of SALT II, ed. by ChrisBarkerand David Dowty, 1-16. Columbus,OH: Ohio State University. 3 A referee has suggested that these examples are echoic. While clearly the speaker is agreeing with the addressee in these examples, some kind of independent evidence would be needed to argue the echoicity in view of the fact that the utterance is of a different form from, and contains which it is supposed to be an echo of. an4anaphoric reference to, the utterance Is can be destressed and contracted if there is another constituent to bear main sentence stress, as in ia below, or if the that receives contrastive stress, as in ib. (i) a. EH: We could not have very much, and then order dessert. JA: Hmmm... there's always that. [Overheard conversation, 6/1/96] b. FS: A lot of times interpreting what people are saying is a problem. SS: There's that, but there's also the fact that the field is basically bullshit. [Overheard conversation, 5/31/96] This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 108 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 73, NUMBER 1 (1997) --. 1993. A pragmatic account of the definiteness effect in existential sentences. Journal of Pragmatics 19.39-55. BIRNER, BETTY, and GREGORYWARD. 1994. Uniqueness, familiarity, and the definite article in English. Berkeley Linguistics Society 20.93-102. CLARK,HERBERT H., and CATHERINER. MARSHALL. 1981. Definite reference and mutual knowledge. Elements of discourse understanding, ed. by Aravind K. Joshi, Bonnie L. Webber, and Ivan A. Sag, 10-63. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1993. Cognitive status K.; NANCYHEDBERG;and RONZACHARSKI. GUNDEL,JEANETTE and the form of referring expressions in discourse. Language 69.274-307. HEIM,IRENE.1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics 2.114-25. KUNO, SUSUMU. 1972. Functional sentence perspective: A case study from Japanese and English. Linguistic Inquiry 3.269-320. LEWIS,DAVID. 1979. Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8.339-59. MILSARK, GARY. 1974. Existential sentences in English. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation. PRINCE,ELLENF. 1981. Towards a taxonomy of given-new information. Radical pragmatics, ed. by Peter Cole, 223-56. New York: Academic Press. . 1992. The ZPG letter: Subjects, definiteness, and information-status. Discourse description: Diverse analyses of a fundraising text, ed. by William C. Mann and Sandra A. Thompson, 295-325. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. WARD, GREGORY,and BETTYBIRNER.1995. Definiteness and the English existential. Language 71.722-42. Departmentof Linguisticsand Germanic,Slavic, Asian, and AfricanLanguages MichiganState University East Lansing,MI 48824-1027 [abbottb@pilot.msu.edu] [Received 20 May 1996; revision received 2 October 1996; accepted4 October 1996.] This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Sat, 17 Oct 2015 20:01:36 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions