See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/215570266 Reconciling the Debate on Universal Human Rights: Reframing the Notion of Identity Article · January 2008 CITATIONS READS 0 3,955 1 author: Lida Bteddini 3 PUBLICATIONS 7 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Research View project All content following this page was uploaded by Lida Bteddini on 27 May 2014. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL Volume 7, Summer 2008 Reconciling the Debate on Universal Human Rights Reframing the Notion of Identity Lida Bteddini It is often argued that securing universal human rights is a means to achieving human security. However, universal human rights have long been contested by cultural relativists who argue that such universality undermines cultural differences. This article aims to reconcile universalists’ and cultural relativists’ arguments by demonstrating that universal human rights can exist within a culturally-sensitive universal framework. T Preamble of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights advocates the fundamental importance of the establishment of universal human rights," to reaffirm faith…in the dignity and worth of the human person, in the equal rights of men and women and of nations large and small."1 The underlying foundation of human rights lies in the implicit acknowledgement the importance such rights have for human security. After all, human rights abuses represent a breach of such security and an infringement on the dignity and worth of the individual self. For this reason, the notion of universal human rights must be understood as an extension of the human security paradigm. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights was established over a half a century ago, and yet the notion of universal human rights is still highly contested. Cultural relativists argue that rights and moral values cannot be universally established he because no universal culture exists, and therefore, universal human rights are implausible, while proponents of universal human rights argue that universality does not presuppose uniformity. In other words, the principle of universal human rights implies that such rights would be based on universally recognized and accepted principles which transcend cultural or religious diversity. Perceptions of individual identity play a crucial role in shaping a person’s perception of human commonality. This article aims to illustrate the reconcilability of cultural relativist and universalistic arguments regarding universal human rights by proposing an alternative conception of identity as presented through George Herbert Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self." Mead’s theoretical framework will provide a new lens by which the debate surrounding universal human rights may be analyzed and resolved. The first segment of this article will provide a Lida Bteddini has a dual-Bachelor’s degree in International Relations and Philosophy as well as a Master’s degree in Ethics, Peace, and Global Affairs, from the American University of Washington D.C. She also studied political science at the American University of Beirut in Lebanon for one year. She is currently working in international development. Global Images ▪ 104 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE brief summary of the theoretical arguments made by cultural relativists and universalists regarding the notions of identity and universal human rights. Understanding the foundation of these theories allows for a better recognition of how notions of identity contribute to a conflict over the universality of human rights, and helps to better define the way in which universal human rights are conceptualized. Next follows an extensive theoretical analysis of George Herbert Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self."Mead’s analysis of identity provides an innovative framework by which relativist and universalistic notions of human rights may be understood, as will be discussed in detail within this section. Finally, a comprehensive assessment of the philosophical claims of Mead will be applied to the debate surrounding universal human rights. This section of the article will help to illustrate the possibility of reconciliation between the two theories of the human rights debate through analyzing Mead’s theory regarding identity and its role in shaping moral action. Cultural Relativism the Debate and Universalism: Cultural Relativism In rejection of the notion of objective truth, the ancient Greek sophist Protagoras is quoted as having described truth as "the way things appear to me, in that way they exist for me and the way things appear to you, in that way they exist for you."2 While not explicitly linked to culture, Protagoras’ theories on relativism have played a crucial role in establishing the theoretical argument against objective truth and in support of relativistic concepts of morality. The crux of the argument posed by cultural relativists regarding universal human rights is whether it is possible to successfully conceive of culturally sensitive universals. Since according to this theoretical perspective, culture is the underlying foundation of an individual’s identity, universal human rights seems problematic due to the absence of a universal culture. The absence of a "universal culture" would imply that moral values could only be derived specific to particular communities. In other words, though all cultures may subscribe to human rights, the definition of such rights would differ from one culture to the next, and would not be universally applied. In "Universalism and Relativism in Human Rights," David Duquette argues that the core of a person’s identity is comprised mainly by the social network within which one is assimilated, relying heavily on "the hypothesis of enculturation" and the role that culture plays in forming an individual’s "ethical self-perception and perception of others."3 In other words, the values and judgments of an individual are ultimately the product of that person’s cultural affiliation and social patterns of life.4 Melville Herskovitz, one of history’s leading exponents of ethical relativism, states that cultural relativism is a philosophy that stresses the dignity inherent in every body of custom, and "the need for tolerance of conventions though they may differ from one’s own."5 The implication of this worldview is that moral evaluations are ultimately relative to an individual’s cultural identity, and therefore, no universal moral claims exist. It is through this theoretical framework that cultural relativists regard the notion of universal human rights. The implication of this theory is that morality is essentially culture-specific and even more so, that each culture differs in terms of its moral values and judgments. Ann Mayer’s cross-cultural analysis of Islamic notions of human rights adequately illustrates this point. According to Mayer, if human rights are not derived locally from a specific culture, the validity and applicability of such rights becomes questioned.6 According to such theorists, a universal notion of human rights is problematic in that it is an attempt to impose an absolute moral valuation among a world divided culturally and socially, thus comprised of various identities, each holding a different conception of human rights. The cultural relativist framework emphasizes the role of social patterns in establishing an individual’s conception of morality. In response to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, ▪ 105 ▪ Lida Bteddini HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL Herskovitz declared that the underlying concern of cultural relativism is the potential imposition of a single culture over the moral values and rights of others.7 The inability of universal human rights to incorporate the particularities of specific cultures and communities is the most problematic aspect of its application, thus making such rights seem impossible. Universalism Universalism is effectively represented through John Locke’s "natural rights theory," which views human rights as universal insofar as the rights or entitlements proposed are those applicable to all persons simply by virtue of their existence as human beings.8 The underlying claim of universalism is that human rights are universal because they address the absolute needs for securing the life of any individual regardless of cultural affiliation.9 According to universalism, human nature is the level of identity emphasized through the establishment of human rights and therefore, such rights are "ascribable to people simply as human beings."10 This theoretical lens frames the issue of human rights as universally applicable since such rights aim to secure common physiological necessities attributable to all human beings regardless of cultural and societal particularities. The implication of such a theory is that individuals are entitled to be treated in certain ways solely by virtue of their common existence as human beings, and therefore, human rights work towards protecting the basic essentials of human life. The notion of human commonality was the basis for the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which declares human rights as inherent to all human beings and therefore, not a social production. Article 1 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights states that "all human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights," while Article 2 further stresses the entitlement of all human beings to "all the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaration, without distinction of any kind, such as race, color, sex, language, religion, political, or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth, or other Global Images Volume 7, Summer 2008 status."11 Because the universalistic framework views human rights as dealing with the rights of all human beings on the basis of physiological needs and commonalities, the notion of universal human rights seems natural and cultural relativist claims against the universality of such rights are deemed unfounded. The preceding sections offer a brief overview of the debate surrounding universal human rights. While cultural relativism emphasizes the constitutive role that culture and societal practices have on the defining of an individual’s view of morality, universalism considers the common physiological essence of all human beings as the basis for human rights. The way in which a problem is framed determines its resolution. In other words, the irreconcilability of the arguments presented by universalism and cultural relativism is due to the way in which the problem of universal human rights is framed. Cultural relativists consider identity as shaped entirely by a person’s cultural tradition and therefore, since no universal culture exists, universal human rights cannot exist either. The universalistic approach to human rights considers human nature as the building block of identity. All human beings are physiologically equal through their common human nature, regardless of their cultural or societal differences. Therefore human rights can be universally applied because such rights secure the basic necessities for the preservation of human life. The two theories seem to be irreconcilable and preclude agreement about human rights. However, George Herbert Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self" offers an alternative framing of the notion of identity that can resolve this seeming impasse. His pragmatist approach to the notion of the social self provides a new lens by which the universal human rights problematic may be understood. Though Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self" may not provide a complete resolution to the debate on universal human rights, Mead’s ideas prove useful in reframing the notion of identity on which the debate currently founders. The following section will provide an extensive overview of Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self" to show that Mead’s model is an effective strategy ▪ 106 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE to resolve the theoretical divide between cultural development of the social group in which human relativism and universalism. beings exist.17 Becoming an object to oneself refers to the ability of an individual to distinguish Mead's Theory of the Social Self: the between an experience that immediately takes Origin of the Mind place and "our own organization of it into the experience of the self."18 As Mead stresses, the The first step to gaining an understanding of self and the organism are not one and the same, Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self" is illustrating since the self is "entirely distinguishable from an "the structures upon which the self is constructed," organism that is surrounded by things and acts and the framework by which Mead defines with reference to things, including parts of its own personal identity.12 The overarching principle of body."19 The ability of an individual to experience Mead’s theory is the emphasis on the role that itself indirectly through the particular standpoints society plays in defining the notion of the "self." of other members of a social group allows an According to Mead, the mind and the self are individual to become a subject to oneself.20 This essentially social products, and therefore, the is an important aspect of Mead’s theory because it individual self is constructed entirely out of the provides the basis by which human existence can social process.13 The self, according to Mead, has be understood in relation to its social community. a "character different from that of a physiological As Mead explains, because the social network 14 organism proper." It is not an inherently of selves is intertwined with the creation of the existing entity, but is instead developed over self, the unity and structure of the complete time and through a process of social experiential self reflects the unity and structure of the social activity.15 This theory is often challenged by such process as a whole.21 Therefore, the organization essentialists as S. A Gelman, who view certain and unification of a larger social group will in turn aspects of personal identity as being inherent and define the structure of the complete and unified unalterable.16 self.22 The implication of this statement is that It is necessary to illustrate Mead’s conception of a "unified self" is determined on the basis of an the self in order to examine the implications such individual’s capacity to internalize the attitudes and a theory has for the debate surrounding universal roles of others within a particular social network human rights. The next few sections will examine of selves.23 The "generalized other" is, therefore, a Mead’s notion on the distinction between the term that refers to the ability of one to perceive an "self and the organism," "the generalized other," experience on the basis of the attitudes and roles "consciousness vs. self-consciousness," and the of others apart from itself. This notion marks "'I' vs. 'me' distinction," all of which are pertinent the basis for an individual’s capacity to make concepts for a successful reframing of the debate decisions and develop moral and value-based on universal human rights. judgments. This next section will further clarify Mead’s theory of the "generalized other," and The Self and the Organism provide a more comprehensive illustration of the relationship of the self to the social community. Mead begins with an analysis of the distinction between the self and the organism. "Reflexiveness," The "Generalized Other" and the Self-Conscious according to Mead, is the "essential condition…for Self the development of the mind," and which allows an individual to distinguish definitively between Though Mead’s model forcefully stresses that the self and the body. The main differentiation the self is not inherent at one’s birth but, rather, between an individual person and a "lower is completely defined within a social network, animal" is that individual’s ability to become an it is important to note that Mead’s account of ‘object to itself’, possible through the evolutionary identity does not preclude the existence of moral ▪ 107 ▪ Lida Bteddini HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL The Universal Declaration of Human Rights was established over half a century ago, and yet the notion of universal human rights is still highly contested. autonomy—something that is important when considering a person’s capacity to think.24 Mead states that "the organized community or social group which gives to the individual his unity of self may be called ‘the generalized other,'" which represents the attitude of the whole community.25 Nonetheless, the internalization of the "generalized other" provides a means by which an individual can develop a thought process and "think." A personality is created through an individual’s membership within a community, because that individual incorporates the "institutions" of that community into one’s own conduct.26 This implication of this argument is that a person’s selfrealization is dependent on his or her participation within a social community. The self, apart from this participation, is unidentifiable.27 The community, according to Mead, is comprised of a "structure of attitudes" instead of a "group of habits."This is important, since as Mead stresses, a social community is not based on traditional habits formed as a result of one’s membership in a group. Such habits are, instead, insignificant in the defining of the selfconsciousness, but merely comprise that which Mead terms the "unconscious self."28 He furthers this point by asserting that while consciousness merely refers to a "field of experience," selfconsciousness is a term which signifies the "ability to call out in ourselves a set of definite responses which belong to the others of the group."29 Therefore, these two terms must be understood separately, since the self-conscious self is of a different level of awareness not characteristic of a merely conscious being. The most significant aspect of this analysis is Mead’s assertion that "each one of the selves is different from everyone else; but there has Global Images Volume 7, Summer 2008 to be a common structure (…) in order that we may be members of a community at all."30 The "common structure" is the backbone of particular social groups and subsequently, individual selves, which comprises the notion of ‘overarching unity’ characteristic of the social community.31 In other words, social structures and societal norms play a crucial role in defining self-identity because they provide the foundation upon which the individual and unique self may develop. The full development of the self is described in two stages. In the first stage, the individual self is conceived of as constituted "simply by an organization of the particular attitudes of other individuals toward [themselves] and toward one another in the specific social acts in which he participates with them."32 During the second stage, "the organization of the social attitudes of the generalized other or the social group as a whole to which [one] belongs" completes the development of the self so that it is an individual reflection of a general systematic pattern of socialization in which the self and other selves are involved.33 More clearly, the first stage of development signifies one’s ability to generalize the "other." This generalization leads into the second stage of development which is the thought process and the notion of the "I." Mead’s account of the social self is important since it provides reconciliation between the notion of the socially determined self (me) and the self, which is autonomous and unique (I). The differentiation between these two self-concepts is illustrated more clearly in the next section, which discusses their distinctions in detail. This divide will help to conceptualize the aspect of identity, which plays a role in decision making, especially in regards to moral action within Mead’s theoretical framework. The "I" Vs. "Me" Distinction Mead’s model divides the self into two specific entities: the socially determined and concrete "me" and the unique and unfixed "I."34 Therefore, a person’s identity is a mixture of both social determinacy and autonomous individuality. This ▪ 108 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE intertwining of self-concepts is important since it provides a forceful resolve to the paradox of determinacy vs. free will. Though an aspect of personal identity may be socially determined on the basis of one’s membership within a particular community, the self is nonetheless capable of individuality and self-deliberation. Membership within a social community is dependent on the existence of a common social structure, and the existence of a community of attitudes that controls the attitudes of all.35 The implication of Mead’s theory is that personal identity is a mixture of both socially determined characteristics in addition to the unique and autonomously defined entity which is the "I." Without the foundation of the "me," the "I" cannot exist. At the same time, the give-and-take nature of the relationship between these two phases implies that the "I" is also a necessary response to the existence of the "me." 36 In other words, while the "me" is representative of the socially defined and limited aspect of identity, the "I" is a representation of autonomy and spontaneity which allows for individual thought and expression. This point is important in illustrating the potentiality for the existence of social distinction even within a homogenous social group. The metaphysical question of the "I" vs. "me" distinction is not the main concern for Mead. Instead, he illustrates these self-concepts in terms of their functionality as well as the nature of conduct between them. The conduct of the "me" compared to the "I" is quite different. While the "I" provides the self with a component of individuality, the "me" refers to the aspect of the self which represents "a definite organization of the community."37 Mead adds that for the "me," "there is no certainty in regard to it. There is a moral necessity but no mechanical regard to it."38 The importance of this statement is that individual identity cannot be fully understood unless it is recognized as a collaboration of "I" vs. "me" distinction. Contrary to essentialist perspectives which view components of identity as inherent and static, the defining of an individual, for Mead, is a continuous process of adjustment and reaction, something which allows for personality and distinctiveness. The relationship between the "me" and the "I" is further discussed in relation to the social community within which one exists. Though an individual cannot control the environment he or she is born in, the country of his or her origin, or the culture and traditions of his or her ancestry, Mead emphasizes that these aspects of a particular identity comprise the "me," which does not constitute the complete self. The continuous process of the defining of the social self necessitates change. Therefore, the self is never static and unchanging. The self is "an eddy in the social current and so still a part of the current."39 Unfortunately, Mead does not provide a extensive analysis on the limits of the individual’s control over his or her development and autonomy and, in turn, the extent of the influence of the community or social group on the shaping of self identity. Therefore, it is questionable whether Mead considers the self capable of willingly choosing or rejecting certain personal affiliations, or being bound by the components of the socially determined "me." Furthermore, it is not clear what Mead specifies as constituting a "shared environment" or a "common context," thus leaving these terms ambiguous. Nonetheless, what Mead provides is a pervasive account on the individualistic and autonomous nature of the social self, a notion which is crucial to understanding the extent of diversity and distinction that can exist within a social group or community. Mead's Theory of Universals The "I" vs. "me" distinction is similar to Mead’s theory of "universals," which proves significant to the application of Mead’s Theory of the Social Self and the debate on universal human rights. A "universal" is described as belonging to "the experience of all of us," the "us" referring to all human beings.40 An effective illustration of the notion of universals is in the scenario Mead provides to express the difference between the individual and the community. He explains that during a concert, for example, what each individual gets out of the experience is very ▪ 109 ▪ Lida Bteddini HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL different from the next. Nonetheless, the physical objects of that concert are universal and common to the whole audience.41 In other words, a particular experience is derived from a common quality by which all individuals can relate. The concept of the universal and particular is not meant to be understood as the difference between objective and subjective. In other words, the particular experience of an individual should not be understood as something that is based on individual perception, but rather, that everything in the social community takes place as a process. This process begins with the existence of a social organization. Therefore, the community within which the organism or individual exists "acts in such a co-operative fashion that the action of one is the stimulus to the other to respond, and so on…"More importantly, Mead asserts that the "universe of discourse" within which people are able to communicate, allows for the collaboration of various social groups into a higher organizational relationship. Such a relationship is representative of the commonality necessary for social development, and is the foundation of the mind, or the self.42 Establishing the foundation of the self is important since it provides a base by which the development of the individual can be better analyzed. Furthermore, the recognition of the role of the individual within the larger social community, and the interrelatedness of the relationship between society and the self, is a crucial aspect of Mead’s theoretical framework. The peculiarity of Mead’s theory is that it views the social process as existing prior to the existence of individuals or selves. Therefore, unlike an individualistic theoretical framework, which considers the individual as a precondition to the appearance of the social community, the social theory places the social community as the foundation for the genesis and development of the mind, and in turn, the self. Whereas the preceding sections focused on illustrating the development of selves on the basis of "the human organism," the next section of this article will examine the application of Mead’s Theory of the Social Self to the social community. Global Images Volume 7, Summer 2008 This section will prove helpful in illustrating the nature of human societies and the role of individual selves within such communities. Mead's Theory of the Social Self - The Self the "Social Context" in The basis of human society, according to Mead, begins with understanding the difference between man and the most basic of societies, the society of insects. The fundamental difference, stresses Mead, is that while the society of insects is constructed around the physiological differentiation between its group members, human society is founded upon the development of language. Therefore, the "system of organization" of human society is built upon a level of communication distinct from that of physiologically-dependent insect societies. Mead states that human society finds "unity into the varied structures of the human form by means of an additional organ, the brain and the cortex."44 It is insufficient to evaluate human society on the basis of physiological differentiation, according to Mead, since human beings are minimally different on this level. Analyzing human society on such a basis would be similar to analyzing the physiological differentiation existing within a "nest of ants."45 The implication of such a statement is that while insect societies are differentiated physiologically, the level of response possible by its members is limited intellectually. Human society, on the other hand, is dependent on intellectual and languagebased differentiation for the functioning of its "system of organization." Because of this, "there thus arises the almost indefinite multiplicity of the responses of the human organism."46 A human being is socially defined in large part by his or her ability and response within an environment instead of mere physiologically or biologically determined characteristics. In describing the relationship between human society and the vertebrates, Mead states that the process of communication is "nothing but an elaboration of the peculiar intelligence with which the vertebrate form is endowed."47 It is through communication that the individual can define his ▪ 110 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE or herself, and human free will and self-realization can occur. Nonetheless, Mead stresses that a human being’s capacity for self-determination is wholly dependent on their membership within a social community of selves. The implication of this theory is that communication cannot take place without an individual’s social involvement.48 The social process is, therefore, the key to differentiation among human beings. Language provides human beings with the capacity for "an entirely different principle of organization which produces not only a different type of individual but also a different society."49 Thus, this theory maintains that since human beings are minimally diverse physiologically, universal human rights working to secure the common physiological needs of human beings do not threaten cultural or societal particularities. Self-realization is achieved in acknowledging the consciousness of both oneself and other individuals. The process of co-operative activity which can take place within a human society is distinctly higher than that which takes place among insects, or within a herd, for example.50 While it is the physiological characteristic of the central nervous system of human beings which allows them "to take the attitudes of other individuals, and the attitudes of the organized social group, toward [oneself]," the capacity for self-determination is entirely dependent on how an individual utilizes such a capacity for self-consciousness.51 Principles such as "kindliness, helpfulness, and assistance," comprise the essential Culture is depicted as characteristics of individuals a changing process in a human instead of a static c o m m u n i t y, entity. according to Mead.52 The concept of such a society depicted in Mead’s theory is highly abstract, but nonetheless important in helping one realize the possibility by which the limits of various social groups may be transcended.53 Mead furthers his emphasis of the significance of communication by arguing that an individual’s consciousness of both oneself and other individuals is "equally important for…self-development and for the development of the organized society or social group."54 Therefore, communication necessitates participation with another, which in turn "requires the appearance of the other in the self, the identification of the other with the self, the reaching of self-consciousness through the other."55 A society is thus built up out of elements formed through human to human contact, which Mead argues is identifiable through such universal forms as "universal religions and… universal economic processes.56 The fundamental attitudes of human beings toward one another, as Mead argues, can be seen through such attributes as "kindliness, helpfulness, and assistance," which he refers to as a "universal religion."57 In regards to universal economic processes, Mead argues that there exists a "fundamental process of exchange on the part of individuals arising from the goods for which they have no immediate need themselves but which can be utilized for obtaining that which they do need."58 Mead highlights both the attitudes of ‘neighborliness’ and ‘the process of exchange,’ which constitute the "most highly universal" and "most highly abstract society."59 He unfortunately does not write extensively on the topic of religion or economics, leaving this assertion quite vague and underdeveloped. The term "universal religion," for example, is problematic because of its oversimplification of the complexity of existing religious traditions. In leaving this notion vague, Mead seems to disregard fundamental differences that exist among and within certain religions, which sometimes leads to unavoidable conflict. Further development of this concept would help to address such critical points of contention. Nonetheless, the most important point to consider is that while these two processes represent a universal human society, the process of communication is still the vehicle by which "neighborliness" and "a process of exchange" can take place. Communication represents the utmost universal process available to selfconscious human society. It is also a process that is distinctive to human beings, and which ▪ 111 ▪ Lida Bteddini HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL allows for a complex and highly organized social community unattainable in other societies such as that of insects or vertebrates.60 While not entirely similar, Mead’s theory of the significance of communication can be compared the work of modern behaviorists such as B.F Skinner, who recognized the importance language plays in the process of socialization.61 The next section of this article will provide an application of Mead’s theoretical framework to the debate surrounding the establishment of universal human rights. It will aim to highlight the theories of the "mind" and the "self," and further discuss Mead’s alternative understanding of identity presented within the preceding pages. In addition, the next section will aim to illustrate the potential for reconciliation between universalistic and cultural relativistic arguments regarding a universal implementation of human rights. Application of Mead's Universal Human Rights Theory to Mead’s "Theory of the Social Self" is an innovative approach to the debate surrounding universal human rights: it allows for a reframing of the human rights problematic by redefining the meaning behind "identity" and the "self." Furthermore, Mead’s notion of ‘community’proves helpful in comprehending both universalistic and cultural relativistic arguments, regardless of their stance on the debate surrounding universal human rights. Though Mead did not specifically address the issue of universal human rights, his ‘theory of the social self’ will prove helpful in reshaping the lens by which identity and, in turn, the ‘self’, are perceived. The strength of Mead’s theory is his framing of the "self" as dynamic and complex. As previously discussed, Mead’s notion of identity considers the "self" to be neither completely determined, nor completely free and autonomous.62 The result is a "self" which is best defined as an ever-changing process instead of something that is static and unchanging.63 The implication of this statement is that it is neither culture nor human nature that completely defines an individual. One’s identity is Global Images Volume 7, Summer 2008 intricately bound to the social process and consists of the interconnectedness of both a socially determined "me" and a largely autonomous "I." The presence of both the "me" and the ‘I’ help to shape what Mead terms as the "self-conscious self."64 Moral judgment or action on the part of an individual within a social community can be based on the membership of an individual within that particular society. Nevertheless, Mead stresses that an individual’s identification with a specific community, whether it be religious, political, or cultural, does not dictate that person’s moral action. Instead, selves are wholly capable of acting aside from such affiliations. Decisions of individual moral selves will not necessarily be determined on the basis of social communities.65 The implication of this theory is important for understanding the polar dichotomization of universal and cultural relativist arguments regarding universal human rights. Both universalist and cultural relativist understandings of the "self" are insufficient in effectively recognizing the dynamics of identity as well as an individuals’ capacity for moral judgment. Human nature or culture alone cannot fully explain the nature of an individual’s identity and the role of the "self" in the social community. From the perspective of Mead’s theory, both universalist and cultural relativist theories on universal human rights represent incomplete theorizations of what comprises an individual’s identity. While cultural relativist notions of identity consider culture to be the essence of all moral judgment, Mead emphasizes the relational nature of an individual’s existence to that of another. Social interactions are what define a rational actor, and therefore, the existence of the self of one person is wholly dependent on its relation to others in a community of selves. Nonetheless, the theory that an individual is constituted by the social process, and that all selves exist as "individual reflections" of it, does not mean that each individual does not have its own "peculiar identity."66 As Mead argues, while the "I" exists in spontaneity and autonomy, this does not preclude the existence of a socially defined and concrete ▪ 112 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE "me" by which the "I" is molded and shaped. Such a theory poses an innovative perspective on the nature of identity in forming moral agency within society. Though the existence of one self is dependent on the existence of a community of selves, each particular self also has independent agency as well as individual identity. Culture is a particular characteristic of the larger whole of an individual’s identity. It is one aspect of the self and does not completely define a human being. What Mead proposes is not merely an understanding of the individual self but, more importantly, the relationship of the particular self to society, and consequently, the realization of the self as a part of the larger whole.67 He contends that "the organized structure of every individual self within the human social process of experience and behavior reflects, and is constituted by, the organized relational pattern of that process as a whole."68 In other words, what each individual reflects is a different perspective of a relational pattern, existing out of a common social origin, shaped and molded according to individual particularities.69 In this sense, rationality and morality can be understood as neither wholly universal nor wholly subjective, but as existing in a social interchange among a community of selves.70 In turn, human rights should not be perceived as a force of identity change but, rather, as a result of the particularistic yet universal framework which is characteristic of human society. Cultural relativists hold that the establishment of universal human rights would disregard cultural differences, and therefore, prove to be problematic and insensitive to such concerns. If one applies Mead’s theory to the debate on universal human rights, however, it follows that cultural groups represent a particular community which derives from a larger and all-encompassing common social origin. The implication is that universal human rights are plausible insofar as they are constituted by the generalized and common origin of the rights of all human beings. Thus, they transcend the particularities of culture and specific social communities and work towards securing the individual interests of all human beings, which live in partial independence from their cultural contexts and social limitations. A crucial component of Mead’s Theory of the Social Self is the notion of a "common structure."Universalism argues that human nature comprises an all-encompassing level of identification among human beings that should be the core of universal human rights. While it is true that different social communities are comprised of different social habits and values, Mead’s theory asserts that there exists a "common structure" which is necessary in order for any community to exist at all. This "common structure" acts as a backbone to social communities, and provides a sense of "overarching unity" necessary for the sustenance of social groups. Therefore, the existence of social groups validates the notion of a ‘common structure.’ The process of communication which exists within such social communities is a characteristic of all human social networks, whether it is through language, social habits, or even physical gestures. As long as there is a level of communication among human beings within or among different social groups, there must exist an ‘overarching unity’ which allows for successful communication to take place. In other words, culture exists as a particular experience of a larger all-encompassing human social origin. Mead’s depiction of an audience at a concert, mentioned earlier, is an effective illustration of this point. Though the physical environment and set-up of the concert will be the same for all individuals who attend the performance, it is nonetheless true that different people will leave the concert with a different overall experience, with particular incidents acting as the differentiating factor. In this way, culture can be understood as a particular reflection or derivative of a universal common social origin. In other words, specific local communities or groups are similar to mirror reflections of a different aspect of that same social origin of which all human beings are a part. Mead’s theory offers an alternative way of understanding the relationship of the individual to culture, which circumvents the irreconcilability of the debate between cultural relativist and universalists and reframes the debate on the ▪ 113 ▪ Lida Bteddini HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL establishment of universal human rights. As Mead effectively portrays, the self is dynamic. It is a complex entity which cannot be adequately expressed or understood through static, unchanging, and concrete definitions. In viewing identity as multifaceted, it becomes evident that the approaches of both universalism and cultural relativism regarding identity are both crucial yet incomplete understandings on the nature of identity. In other words, while identity is shaped forcefully by culture, the "common social origin" of human beings also plays a large role in the shaping of an individual’s propensity for moral action. At the same time, this common origin alone is not the deciding factor of a person’s moral judgment. It only helps to define the "me," and provides minimal influence on the individual’s autonomy or individuality. According to this theory, the self is both culture-specific as well as universally derived. In turn, an individual can be both a member of a certain local community or social group, but also has the capacity to associate oneself as a member of a civilization, or even an entire race. Universal human rights are derived from and should work to secure the "common social origin" of all human beings, regardless of, but not insensitive to, cultural affiliation. The application of Mead’s Theory of the Social Self presents an alternative approach to the universal human rights paradigm. Culture is depicted as a changing process instead of a static entity. Over time, humans evolve and so does culture. At the same time, an individual born into a specific culture has the propensity to travel, and thus integrate into other cultures across the world. That individual is able to communicate and relate to other human beings across-cultures, not merely because of culture similarities, but rather, because of a common social origin which is derived from human nature. Without the existence of an "overarching unity," particular derivations would not exist. In other words, culture is originated through the process of human social development of which all human beings are a part. Through the Meadian lens, universal human rights are rights based on that which is applicable to all human beings. Such rights work to secure Global Images Volume 7, Summer 2008 the universal so that the particular may exist. More clearly, while cultural relativists consider values and judgments of an individual to be ultimately a product of that person’s cultural affiliation and social pattern of life, Mead’s theory identifies a person’s cultural affiliation and social pattern of life as being derived from a larger and all-encompassing human social origin. Just as individuals are members or reflections of their cultural group, so are cultural groups members or reflections of the "universal society of selves." Conclusion As has been discussed, Mead’s Theory of the Social Self provides a new approach to universal human rights. It provides a theoretical framework by which the notion of the universality of such rights may exist in accordance with cultural sensitivities and peculiarities. A universal application of human rights does not necessarily negate the values and judgments of particular cultures, as is often argued by cultural relativists. At the same time, culture comprises a significant and influential aspect of an individual’s identity. What Mead’s account suggests is that a successful reframing of universal human rights would provide due recognition to the cultural sources of individual identity while recognizing the universality of the applicability of human rights. Universal human rights would thus work towards securing the basis for the sustenance of cultures and traditions, all of which are dependent and derived from a larger collective society of selves. Universal concepts such as that of universal human rights arise out of collective social awareness of the interdependence of human beings on one another.71 Mead’s understanding of the social self helps one recognize the inadequacies of cultural relativism and universalism in conceptualizing identity and, in turn, human rights. The preceding assertions made within this article suggest that cultural relativist and universalist arguments on universal human rights are reconcilable and, more importantly, that human rights can exist within a culturally-sensitive universal framework. The actualization of this reconciliation would ▪ 114 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE require a reframing of the current human rights dialogue. In other words, the notion of identity presented within any universal human rights framework must represent that of a complete self, thus incorporating both cultural relativist and universalist notions of what constitutes identity and recognizing the dynamic and ever-changing nature of the social self. In this way, both the peculiarities and commonalities that can be observed among individuals within a social community can be understood as constitutive of individual selves within a larger human society of which all human beings are members. Just as autonomy and diversity can exist within a homogenous and close-knit social community, so can commonality and universality exist among a world of diversity and distinction. Mead’s Theory of the Social Self is a valuable account of the relationship of the individual to a larger community of selves. With the proper acknowledgment, Mead’s theory will provide the human rights debate with a useful outlook on the nature of individual identity and its role in shaping the debate on universal human rights. ▪ 115 ▪ Lida Bteddini HUMAN SECURITY JOURNAL Volume 7, Summer 2008 Notes Universal Declaration of Human Rights. (United Nations: Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, 10 Dec. 1948). http://www.unhchr.ch/ udhr/lang/eng.htm (accessed August 8, 2007). 2 Edward Schiappa. Protagoras and Logos. (Columbia SC: University. of South Carolina Press, 1991). 3 David Duquette. "Universalism and Relativism in Human Rights." Universal Human Rights: Moral Order in a Divided World (New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2005), 63. 4 Melville Herskovitz. Man and His Works, (New York: Knopf, 1950). 5 Ibid. 6 Ann Elizabeth Mayer, “Current Islamic Thinking on Human Rights,” in Human Rights in Africa: Cross-Cultural Perspectives (Abdullahi Ahmed AnNa’im & Francis M. Deng eds., 1990), 137. 7 “Statement on Human Rights,” American Anthropologist, (American Anthropological Association, 1947). 539-543. 8 John Locke. The Second Treaties on Civil Government, (1690). http://www.constitution.org/jl/2ndtr00.txt (accessed 14 July 2007). 9 Ibid. 10 Alistair MacLeod, “The Structure of Arguments for Human Rights,” Universal Human Rights: Moral Order in a Divided World (2005), 24. 11 Universal Declaration of Human Rights. (United Nations: Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, 10 Dec. 1948). http://www.unhchr.ch/ udhr/lang/eng.htm (accessed August 8, 2007). 12 George Herbert Mead, Mind, Self, & Society. (Chicago: The University of Chicago P, 1934). 116. 13 Ibid, 163. 14 Ibid.,135. 15 Ibid. 16 S. A. Gelman and L. A. Hirschfeld, “How Biological is Essentialism?” in Folkbiology, ed. D.L Medin & S. Atran (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1999). 17 Ibid.,136-137. 18 Ibid., 135. 19 Ibid., 137. 20 Ibid., 138. 21 Ibid.,144. 22 Ibid. 23 Ibid. 24 Ibid., 147. 25 Ibid.,154. 26 Ibid. 27 Ibid., 162. 28 Ibid., 163. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid., 163 (emphasis added) 31 Ibid., 146. 32 Ibid., 158. 33 Ibid. 34 Ibid., 173-174. 35 Ibid., 164. 36 Ibid., 182. 37 Ibid., 176. 38 Ibid., 178. 39 Ibid., 182. 40 Ibid., 185. 41 Ibid. 42 Ibid., 284. 43 Ibid., 235. 44 Ibid., 236. 45 Ibid. 46 Ibid. 47 Ibid., 243. 48 Ibid. 49 Ibid., 244. 50 Ibid., 255. 51 Ibid. 52 Ibid., 258. 53 Ibid., 259. 54 Ibid., 253. 55 Ibid. 56 Ibid., 258. 57 Ibid. 58 Ibid. 59 Ibid., 259. 1 Global Images ▪ 116 ▪ REVUE DE LA SÉCURITÉ HUMAINE Ibid. Skinner, B.F. About Behaviorism (New York: Knopf, 1974), 104. 62 Ibid., 174. 63 Ibid. 64 Ibid. 65 Ibid. 66 Ibid., 209. 67 Ibid., 200-201. 68 Ibid., 201. 69 Ibid. 70 Ibid. 71 Ibid., 320. 60 61 ▪ 117 ▪ View publication stats Lida Bteddini