Uploaded by dandangwapo2018

book epsilon (metaphysics)

advertisement
Metaphysica of Aristotle
With Commentaries of St. Thomas Aquinas
(Book Epsilon)
A Research Paper Presented to Rev. Fr. John Carl Robles, PhL - MA
Sancta Maria Mater et Regina Seminarium
Cagay, Roxas City
In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements
For Subject course of Metaphysics
BY
Sem. Dale Andrew S. Aguihap
January 2022
Outline of Study:
I.
II.
Short Introduction
The Method of Investigating Being as Being. how This Science Differs from the Other
Sciences
-
Distinction of ‘theology’, the science of being as such, from the other theoretical
sciences, mathematics and physics.
III.
The Being Which This Science Investigates
-
IV.
Refutation of Those Who Wished to Abolish the Accidental
-
V.
Four senses of ‘being’. Of these, accidental being is the object of no science.
The nature and origin of accident.
The True and the False as Being and Non-Being. Accidental Being and Being in the Sense
of the True Are Excluded from This Science
-
VI.
VII.
Being as truth is not primary being.
Conclusion
Bibliography and Sources
Short Introduction
Aristotle himself described his subject matter in a variety of ways: as ‘first philosophy’, or ‘the
study of being qua being’, or ‘wisdom’, or ‘theology’. A comment on these descriptions will help
to clarify Aristotle’s topic.
These causes and principles are clearly the subject matter of what he calls ‘first philosophy’. But
this does not mean the branch of philosophy that should be studied first. Rather, it concerns issues
that are in some sense the most fundamental or at the highest level of generality. Aristotle
distinguished between things that are “better known to us” and things that are “better known in
themselves,”
In Book Epsilon (6), Aristotle adds description to the study of the causes and principles of beings
“qua” beings. Whereas natural science studies objects that are material and subject to change, and
mathematics studies objects that although not subject to change are nevertheless not separate from
matter, there is still room for a science that studies things that are eternal, not subject to change,
and independent of matter. Such a science, he says, is theology, and this is the “first” and “highest”
science.
Aristotle’s identification of theology, so conceived, with the study of being “qua” being has proved
challenging to his interpreters. With the help of St. Thomas Aquinas, he was able to come up with
his own commentaries and knowledge regarding with Aristotle’s Metaphysics which was letr on
used by many philosophers.
Chapter 1
In Chapter 1 of this brief book, Aristotle compares the science of nature, mathematics, and
theology. The science of nature, or natural science, is that which studies natural organisms and
processes. All rational activity, or all activity using the intellect, "can be divided into the practical,
the productive and the theoretical"
We are seeking the principles and the causes of the things that are, and obviously of them
qua being. For, while there is a cause of health and of good condition, and the objects of
mathematics have first principles and elements and causes1 (1025b)
The principles and causes of beings are the object of our search, and it is evident that [we
must investigate the principles and causes of beings] as beings. For there is a cause of
health and of its recovery; and there are also principles and elements and causes of the
objects of mathematics; and in general every intellectual science, to whatever degree it
participates in intellect, deals with principles and causes: either with those which are more
certain or with those which are simpler.2
The science of nature investigates those things that have within themselves a principle of change—
that is, something within them that determines their growth, locomotion, and reproduction. The
science of nature is a theoretical science, as it is not directly aimed at practice or production but
rather aims for theoretical understanding. Mathematics is also a theoretical science, though its
1
Aristotle) Ross, W. D (Sir William David) (editor). (2022). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A Revised Text with
Introduction and Commentary by W. D. Ross [Complete in 2 volumes] (1st ed.). Oxford University Press.
2
Aquinas, S. T., & Rowan, J. P. (1961). Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle Volume II. Chicago: Henry
Regnery Company.
objects, unlike those of the science of nature, are unchanging. That is, mathematical objects such
as numbers and theorems are not subject to change.
But all these sciences single out some one thing, or some particular class, and confine their
investigations to this, but they do not deal with being in an unqualified sense, or as being.
Nor do they make any mention of the “whatness” itself of things. But proceeding from this,
some making it evident by means of the senses, and others taking it by assuming it [from
some other science], they demonstrate with greater necessity or more weakly the essential
attributes of the class of things with which they deal.3
Since natural science, like other sciences, is in fact about one class of being, i.e. to that sort
of substance which has the principle of its movement and rest present in itself, evidently it
is neither practical nor productive. For in the case of things made the principle is in the
maker – it is either reason or art or some faculty, while in the case of things done it is in
the doer – viz. will, for that which is done and that which is willed are the same.4 (1025b)
Now at the end of this chapter, we are introduced to the idea that First Philosophy, metaphysics,
is ultimately the same as theology.
There must, then, be three theoretical philosophies, mathematics, physics, and what we
may call theology, since it is obvious that if the divine is present anywhere, it is present in
things of this sort. And the highest science must deal with the highest genus. Thus, while
3
Ibid, Page 365
Aristotle) Ross, W. D (Sir William David) (editor). (2022). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A Revised Text with Introduction
and Commentary by W. D. Ross [Complete in 2 volumes] (1st ed.). Oxford University Press.
4
the theoretical sciences are more to be desired than the other sciences, this is more to be
desired than the other theoretical sciences.5 (1026a)
He gives the second reason why this science is called theology; and the reason is this: the
most honorable science deals with the most honorable class of beings, and this is the one
in which divine beings are contained.6
Chapter 2
Chapter 2 examines accidental being. Accidental being is that which exists not of necessity and
not for the most part—that is, neither that which exists always nor that which exists most
frequently. The whiteness of a man, Aristotle says, is accidental being because "men are not always
or for the most part white." However, he adds, "it is not an accident that he is an animal." That a
man is an animal is a necessary part of his being; that a man is white is an accidental part of his
being.
since the unqualified term ‘being’ has several meanings, of which one was seen’ to be the
accidental, and another the true (‘non-being’ being the false), while besides these there are
the figures of predication (e.g. the ‘what’, quality, quantity, place, time, and any similar
meanings which ‘being’ may have), and again besides all these there is that which ‘is’
potentially or actually: being’ has many meanings, we must say regarding the accidental,
that there can be no scientific treatment of it. (1026a-1026b)7
5
Ibid, Page 58
Aquinas, S. T., & Rowan, J. P. (1961). Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle Volume II. Chicago: Henry
Regnery Company.
7
Aristotle) Ross, W. D (Sir William David) (editor). (2022). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A Revised Text with Introduction
and Commentary by W. D. Ross [Complete in 2 volumes] (1st ed.). Oxford University Press.
6
Hence, there is no science of accidental being. If someone studies humankind, for instance, the
object of study encompasses humankind's essential rather than accidental essence.
Therefore, since there are some beings which always are in the same way and of necessity
(not necessity in the sense of compulsion, but in the sense of that which cannot be
otherwise), and others which are neither of necessity nor always, but for the most part, this
is the principle and this the cause of the accidental.8
Chapter 3
Chapter 3 discusses that you cannot refute the accidentals and that they are a certain chain reactions
which leads to a certain point of time.
That there are principles and causes which are generable and destructible without ever
being in course of being generated or destroyed, is obvious. For otherwise all things will
be of necessity, since that which is being generated or destroyed must have a cause which
is not accidentally its cause. (1027a)9
Clearly then the process goes back to a certain starting-point, but this no longer points to
something further. This then will be the starting-point for the fortuitous, and will have
nothing else as cause of its coming to be. But to what sort of starting-point and what sort
of cause we thus refer the fortuitous – whether to matter or to the purpose or to the motive
power, must be carefully considered. (1027b)10
8
Aquinas, S. T., & Rowan, J. P. (1961). Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle Volume II. Chicago: Henry
Regnery Company.
9
Aristotle) Ross, W. D (Sir William David) (editor). (2022). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A Revised Text with Introduction
and Commentary by W. D. Ross [Complete in 2 volumes] (1st ed.). Oxford University Press.
10
Ibid, Page 60
Chapter 4
In Chapter 4 we could find that for Aristotle, truth is the expression of what is. In other words,
truth is the expression of being.
For we have sufficiently determined its nature. But since that which is in the sense of being
true, or is not in the sense of being false, depends on combination and separation, and truth
and falsity together depend on the allocation of a pair of contradictory judgements.
(1027b)11
Having drawn his conclusions about accidental being, the Philosopher now settles the issue
about the being which signifies the truth of a proposition; and in regard to this he does two
things. First, he determines the meaning of this kind of being. Second, he excludes it from
the principal study of this science12
Therefore both being in the sense of the accidental and being in the sense of the true must
be excluded from this science. For the cause of the former—being in the sense of the
accidental—is the indeterminate, and therefore it does not come within the scope of art, as
has been shown13
Conclusion
Aristotle’s description ‘the study of being qua being’ is frequently and easily misunderstood, for
it seems to suggest that there is a single subject matter “being qua being” that is under investigation.
But Aristotle’s description does not involve two things; first, a study and second, a subject matter
11
Ibid, Page 61
Aquinas, S. T., & Rowan, J. P. (1961). Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle Volume II. Chicago: Henry
Regnery Company.
13
Ibid, Page 390
12
(being qua being) for he did not think that there is any such subject matter as ‘being qua being’.
Rather, his description involves three things: (1) a study, (2) a subject matter or being, and (3) a
manner in which the subject matter is studied (qua being).
Of course, first philosophy is not the only field of inquiry to study beings. Natural science and
mathematics also study beings, but in different ways, under different aspects. The natural scientist
studies them as things that are subject to the laws of nature, as things that move and undergo
change. That is, the natural scientist studies things qua movable (they are subject to change). The
mathematician studies things qua countable and measurable. The metaphysician, on the other hand,
studies them in a more general and abstract way “qua” beings. So first philosophy studies the
causes and principles of beings qua beings.
Bibliography and Sources
Aristotle) Ross, W. D (Sir William David) (editor). (2022). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A Revised
Text with Introduction and Commentary by W. D. Ross [Complete in 2 volumes] (1st ed.). Oxford
University Press.
Aquinas, S. T., & Rowan, J. P. (1961). Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle Volume II.
Chicago: Henry Regnery Company.
Download