Conceptual Art 1962-1969: From the Aesthetic of Administration to the Critique of Institutions Author(s): Benjamin H. D. Buchloh Reviewed work(s): Source: October, Vol. 55 (Winter, 1990), pp. 105-143 Published by: The MIT Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/778941 . Accessed: 14/01/2013 05:22 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to October. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Conceptual Art 1962-1969: From the Aestheticof Administration to the Critique of Institutions* BENJAMIN H. D. BUCHLOH called beautyis noteternal.We knowthatour breathhad no This monster and beginning willneverstop,butwecan, aboveall, conceiveoftheworld's creationand its end. - Apollinaire,Les peintrescubistes Allergictoanyrelapseintomagic,art is part and parcel ofthedisenchantmentof theworld,to use Max Weber'sterm.It is inextricably intertwined withrationalization.Whatmeans and productivemethodsart has at its disposalare all derivedfromthisnexus. -Theodor Adorno A twenty-year distanceseparatesus fromthe historicalmomentof Concepis a Art. It distance that both allows and obliges us to contemplate the tual movement'shistoryin a broader perspectivethan that of the convictionsheld during the decade of its emergence and operation (roughlyfrom 1965 to its temporarydisappearance in 1975). For to historicizeConceptual Art requires, firstof all, a clarificationof the wide range of oftenconflictingpositionsand the mutuallyexclusivetypesof investigationthatwere generatedduringthisperiod. But beyond that there are broader problemsof method and of "interest." For at thisjuncture,any historicizationhas to considerwhattypeof questionsan art-historical approach- traditionallybased on the studyof visual objects- can legitimatelypose or hope to answer in the context of artisticpractices that explicitlyinsistedon being addressed outsideof the parametersof the production of formallyordered, perceptual objects, and certainlyoutside of those of art historyand criticism.And, further,such an historicizationmustalso address the An earlier versionof thisessay was published in L'art conceptuel: * une perspective (Paris: Mus&e d'art moderne de la Ville de Paris, 1989). This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions a .Juliete 3 MEFROf'TCJ; 2 amicelemeif Sonatine Bureaueratique SONATINA) (BUREAUCRATIC AlleTro PIA No Erik SATIE ITI's off. Le voilk parti. / He goes 11 va +)"en ell offie bureau e se his to a merrily gaiement soil g'arillat" "givillall" L PtL is not translatable. an !(opyrihtAf?egrr..a.nt." 1917 by S. CArpeaer Parr Editeur, L. PHILIPPO, B Poissononniire, Paris. PRILIPPO, Editeur, 24, 24, BO. Paris. ; r. P. 669 69 Poissononni.re, Erik Statie.BureaucraticSonatina. 1917. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions R1 = E E OU OS DANINAnk Y COeOI,S LASUEDE LA WoRVEt LA SU 0E LA DLABCAR LE WORVEGEET YCtONPRIS T LF ConceptualArt 1962-1969 107 currencyof the historicalobject, i.e., the motivationto rediscoverConceptual Art fromthe vantage point of the late 1980s: the dialecticthatlinksConceptual Art, as the most rigorous eliminationof visualityand traditionaldefinitionsof representation,to thisdecade of a ratherviolentrestorationof traditionalartistic formsand procedures of production. It is withCubism,of course, thatelementsof language surfaceprogrammatically within the visual field for the firsttime in the historyof modernist painting,in what can be seen as a legacy of Mallarm&. It is there too that a analysisof language and parallel is establishedbetweenthe emergingstructuralist the formalistexamination of representation.But Conceptual practices went beyond such mappingof the linguisticmodel onto the perceptualmodel, outdistancing as they did the spatializationof language and the temporalizationof visual structure.Because the proposal inherentin Conceptual Art was to replace the object of spatialand perceptualexperience by linguisticdefinitionalone (the work as analyticproposition),it thus constitutedthe most consequentialassault on the statusof that object: its visuality,its commoditystatus,and its formof distribution.Confrontingthe fullrange of the implicationsof Duchamp's legacy for the firsttime, Conceptual practices,furthermore,reflectedupon the constructionand the role (or the death) of the authorjust as much as theyredefined the conditionsof receivershipand the role of the spectator.Thus theyperformed the postwarperiod's most rigorousinvestigationof the conventionsof pictorial and sculptural representationand a critique of the traditionalparadigms of visuality. From its very beginning,the historicphase in which Conceptual Art was developed comprisessuch a complex range of mutuallyopposed approaches that any attemptat a retrospectivesurveymustbeware of the forcefulvoices (mostly those of the artiststhemselves)demandingrespectforthe purityand orthodoxy of the movement.Preciselybecause of thisrange of implicationsof Conceptual Art,it would seem imperativeto resista constructionof its historyin termsof a stylistic homogenization,whichwould limitthathistoryto a group of individuals and a set of strictlydefined practicesand historicalinterventions(such as, for example, the activitiesinitiatedby Seth Siegelaub in New York in 1968 or the authoritarianquests for orthodoxyby the English Art & Language group). To historicizeConcept Art (to use the termas it was coined by Henry Flynt in 1961)1 at thismoment,then,requires more thana mere reconstructionof the As is usual with stylisticformationsin the historyof art, the origin and the name of the 1. movementare heavilycontestedby its major participants.Barry,Kosuth,and Weiner, forexample, vehementlydenied in recent conversationswith the author any historicalconnection to or even knowledge of the Fluxus movementof the early 1960s. Nevertheless,at least with regard to the inventionof the term,it seems correctwhen Henry Flyntclaimsthathe is "the originatorof concept art, the most influentialcontemporaryart trend. In 1961 I authored (and copyrighted)the phrase 'concept art,' the rationale for it and the firstcompositionslabeled 'concept art.' My document was ed. La Monte Young, New York, 1962." (La Monte Young's An firstprinted in An Anthology, was in factpublished in 1963.) Anthology This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 108 OCTOBER movement'sself-declaredprimaryactors or a scholarlyobedience to theirproclaimed purityof intentionsand operations.2Their convictionswere voiced with that is continuous within the the (by now often hilarious) self-righteousness traditionof hypertrophicclaims made in avant-gardedeclarationsof the twentiethcentury.For example, one of the campaign statementsbyJoseph Kosuth fromthe late 1960s asserts: "Art before the modern period is as much art as Neanderthal man is man. It is for this reason that around the same time I Because a conceptual workof art in replaced the term 'work' forart proposition. the traditionalsense, is a contradictionin terms."' It seems crucial to rememberthat the oppositionswithinthe formationof Conceptual Art arose partlyfromthe differentreadings of Minimal sculpture (and of its pictorialequivalentsin the paintingof Mangold, Ryman,and Stella) and in the consequences the generationof artistsemergingin 1965 drew from those readings-just as the divergencesalso resultedfromthe impactof various artistswithinthe Minimalistmovementas one or anotherwas chosen by the new generationas itscentralfiguresof reference.For example, Dan Graham seems to have been primarilyengaged withthe workof Sol LeWitt. In 1965 he organized LeWitt's firstone-personexhibition(held in his gallery,called Daniels Gallery); in 1967 he wrote the essay "Two Structures:Sol LeWitt"; and in 1969 he concluded the introductionto his self-publishedvolume of writingsentitledEnd Momentsas follows:"It should be obvious the importanceSol LeWitt's workhas had formywork. In the articlehere included (writtenfirstin 1967, rewrittenin 1969) I hope only that the after-the-fact appreciation hasn't too much subwork his seminal into mycategories."4 merged A second contestantforthe termwas Edward Kienholz, withhis seriesof ConceptTableaux in 1963 (in fact,occasionallyhe is stillcreditedwiththe discoveryof the term.See forexample Roberta Smith'sessay"Conceptual Art," in ConceptsofModernArt,ed. Nikos Stangos [New York: Harper and Row, 1981], pp. 256-70). JosephKosuth claimsin his "Sixth Investigation1969 Proposition14" (publishedby Gerd de Vries,Cologne, 1971, n.p.) thathe used the term"conceptual" forthe firsttime "in a seriesof notes Art dated 1966 and publisheda year laterin a catalogue foran exhibitiontitledNon-Anthropomorphic at the now defunctLannis Galleryin New York." And then there are of course (most officially accepted by all participants)Sol LeWitt's two famoustextsfrom1967 and 1969, the "Paragraphs on Conceptual Art," firstpublishedin Artforum, vol. V, no. 10, pp. 56- 57 and "Sentences on Conceptual Art," firstpublishedin Art& Language,vol. 1, no. 1 (May 1969), pp. 11-13. For a typicalexample of an attemptto writethe historyof Conceptual Art by blindlyadopting 2. and repeating the claims and convictionsof one of that history'sfigures,see Gudrun Inboden, "JosephKosuth--Artist and Criticof Modernism,"inJosephKosuth:TheMakingofMeaning(Stuttgart: StaatsgalerieStuttgart,1981), pp. 11-27. 3. Joseph Kosuth, The SixthInvestigation1969 Proposition14 (Cologne: Gerd De Vries/Paul Maenz, 1971), n. p. Dan Graham, End Moments(New York, 1969), n.p. The other Minimalistswithwhose work 4. Graham seems to have been particularlyinvolved were Dan Flavin (Graham wrote the catalogue essay for Flavin's exhibitionat the Museum of ContemporaryArt in Chicago in 1967) and Robert Morris(whose work he discussed later extensivelyin his essay "Income Piece" in 1973). This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions !i~ili!!!!!!!ii!! Zi:?iiii;.:riiiii-iiiiii:-ii-_iii'i :: :::::::: ::: :::::: ..: -I7 ...... MelBochner. WorkingDrawingsand OtherVisible Meantto Be Thingson PaperNot Necessarily Viewedas Art.Installation, SchoolofVisualArts 1966. December, Gallery, Mel Bochner,by contrast,seems to have chosen Dan Flavin as his primary figureof reference.He wroteone of the firstessayson Dan Flavin (it is in facta text-collageof accumulated quotations,all of which relate in one way or the other to Flavin's work).5Shortlythereafter,the text-collageas a presentational mode would, indeed, become formativewithinBochner's activities,for in the same year he organized what was probablythe firsttrulyconceptualexhibition (both in termsof materialsbeing exhibitedand in termsof presentationalstyle). EntitledWorking Meant Drawingsand OtherVisibleThingsonPaper NotNecessarily to Be Viewedas Art(at the School of Visual Arts in 1966), mostof the Minimal artistswere presentalong witha numberof thenstillratherunknownPost-Minimal and Conceptual artists.Having assembled drawings,sketches,documents, tabulations,and other paraphernaliaof the productionprocess,the exhibition limiteditselfto presentingthe "originals" in Xeroxes assembledintofourlooseleafbindersthatwere installedon pedestalsin the centerof the exhibitionspace. While one should not overestimatethe importanceof such features(nor should one underestimatethe pragmaticsof such a presentationalstyle),Bochner's interventionclearlymoved to transformboth the formatand space of exhibitions.As such,it indicatesthatthe kindof transformation of exhibitionspace and of the devices throughwhichart is presentedthat was accomplishedtwo years 5. Mel Bochner, "Less is Less (for Dan Flavin)," Artand Artists(Summer 1966). This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 110 OCTOBER later by Seth Siegelaub's exhibitionsand publications(e.g., The XeroxBook)had already become a common concern of the generationof post-Minimalartists. A thirdexample of the close generationalsequencingwould be the factthat JosephKosuthseemsto have chosen Donald Juddas his keyfigure:at leastone of the early tautologicalneon works fromthe Proto-Investigations is dedicated to Donald Judd; and throughoutthe second part of "Art afterPhilosophy"(published in November, 1969), Judd's name, work,and writingsare invokedwith the same frequencyas thoseof Duchamp and Reinhardt.At the end of thisessay, Kosuth explicitlystates: "I would hastilyadd to that,however,that I was certainlymuch more influencedby Ad Reinhardt,Duchamp via Johnsand Morris, ...................................., WallFloorPiece(ThreeSquares).1966. Sol LeWitt. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 111 and by Donald Judd than I ever was specificallyby LeWitt . .. Pollock and Judd are, I feel, the beginningand end of American dominance in art."6 Sol LeWitt'sStructures It would seem that LeWitt's proto-Conceptualwork of the early 1960s originatedin an understandingof the essentialdilemmathathas hauntedartistic production since 1913, when its basic paradigms of opposition were first formulated-a dilemma that could be described as the conflictbetween structural specificityand random organization. For the need, on the one hand, for both a systematicreductionand an empiricalverificationof the perceptualdata of a visual structurestandsopposed to the desire,on the other hand, to assigna new "idea" or meaning to an object randomly(in the manner of Mallarme's "transposition")as though the object were an empty(linguistic)signifier. This was the dilemma that Roland Barthesdescribed in 1956 as the "difficultyof our times" in the concluding paragraphsof Mythologies: It seems thatthisis a difficulty pertainingto our times:there is as yet and one this choice can bear onlyon two equally only possible choice, extrememethods:eitherto posit a realitywhichis entirelypermeable to history,and ideologize; or, conversely,to posit a realitywhich is ultimately impenetrable,irreducible,and, in this case, poetize. In a I do not yet see a synthesisbetween ideology and poetry(by word, I poetry understand,in a verygeneral way,the search forthe inalienable meaning of things).7 Both critiquesof the traditionalpracticesof representationin the American postwarcontexthad at firstappeared mutuallyexclusive and had oftenfiercely attacked each other. For example, Reinhardt's extreme form of self-critical, perceptual positivismhad gone too far for most of the New York School artists and certainlyforthe apologistsof American modernism,mainlyGreenbergand and selfFried, who had constructeda paradoxical dogma of transcendentalism referentialcritique.On the other hand, Reinhardtwas as vociferousas they- if 6. Joseph Kosuth, "Art after Philosophy" (Part II), in The MakingofMeaning,p. 175. The list would seem complete,ifit were not forthe absence of Mel Bochner's and On Kawara's name,and its explicit negation of the importance of Sol LeWitt. According to Bochner, who had become an instructorat the School of Visual Artsin 1965, Joseph Kosuth workedwithhim as a studentin 1965 and 1966. Dan Graham mentionedthat during that time Kosuth was also a frequentvisitorto the studios of On Kawara and Sol LeWitt. Kosuth's explicitnegationmakes one wonder whetherit was not preciselySol LeWitt's series of the so-called "Structures"(such as Red Square, WhiteLetters,for example, produced in 1962 and exhibitedin 1965) thatwas one of the crucialpointsof departurefor the formulationof Kosuth's Proto-Investigations. Roland Barthes,Mythologies, 7. trans.AnnetteLavers (New York: Hill and Wang, 1972), p. 158. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 112 OCTOBER not more so - in his contemptforthe opposite,whichis to say,the Duchampian tradition.This is evident in Ad Reinhardt'scondescendingremarksabout both Duchamp--"I've never approved or liked anythingabout Marcel Duchamp. You have to chose between Duchamp and Mondrian"-and his legacyas represented throughCage and Rauschenberg--"Then the whole mixture,the number of poets and musiciansand writersmixed up withart. Disreputable. Cage, Cunningham,Johns, Rauschenberg. I'm against the mixture of all the arts, against the mixtureof art and life you know, everydaylife."8 What slid by unnoticedwas the factthatboth these critiquesof representation led to highlycomparable formaland structuralresults(e.g., Rauschenberg's monochromes in 1951-1953 and Reinhardt's monochromes such as Black Quadruptychin 1955). Furthermore,even while made from opposite vantage denied the points,the criticalargumentsaccompanyingsuch workssystematically traditionalprinciplesand functionsof visual representation,constructingastonishinglysimilarlitaniesof negation. This is as evident,for example, in the text prepared byJohnCage forRauschenberg'sWhitePaintingsin 1953 as it is in Ad Reinhardt's 1962 manifesto"Art as Art." FirstCage: To whom,No subject,No image, No taste,No object, No beauty,No talent, No technique (no why), No idea, No intention,No art, No feeling,No black, No white no (and). Aftercareful considerationI have come to the conclusion that there is nothingin these paintings thatcould not be changed, that theycan be seen in any lightand are not destroyedby the action of shadows. Hallelujah! the blind can see again; the water is fine.9 And then Ad Reinhardt'smanifestofor his own "Art as Art" principle: No lines or imaginings,no shapes or composingsor representings,no visionsor sensationsor impulses,no symbolsor signsor impastos,no decoratingsor coloringsor picturings,no pleasures or pains, no accidents or ready-mades,no things,no ideas, no relations,no attributes, no qualities--nothing that is not of the essence.'0 Ad Reinhardt'sempiricistAmerican formalism(condensed in his "Art as Art" formula)and Duchamp's critique of visuality(voiced for example in the The firstof the two quotationsis to be foundin Ad Reinhardt'sSkowhegan lecture,delivered 8. in 1967, quoted by Lucy Lippard in Ad Reinhardt(New York, 1981), p. 195. The second statement appears in an interviewwith Mary Fuller, published as "An Ad ReinhardtMonologue," Artforum, vol. 10 (November 1971), pp. 36-41. 9. John Cage (statementin reaction to the controversyengendered by the exhibitionof Rauschenberg's all-whitepaintingsat the Stable Gallery,September 15-October 3, 1953). Printed in EmilyGenauer's column in the New YorkHerald Tribune,December 27, 1953, p. 6 (section 4). Ad Reinhardt,"Art as Art," ArtInternational(December 1962). Reprintedin Artas Art:The 10. SelectedWritings ofAd Reinhardt,ed. Barbara Rose (New York: Viking, 1975), p. 56. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 113 famous quip: "All my work in the period before the Nude was visual painting. Then I came to the idea. "") appear in the historicallyratherunlikelyfusion ... the two positionsin the mid-1960s, leading to of Kosuth's attemptto integrate his own formula,which he deployed startingin 1966, "Art as Idea as Idea." It should be noted, however,thatthe strangeadmixtureof the nominalistposition of Duchamp (and its consequences) and the positivistpositionof Reinhardt(and its implications)was not only accomplished in 1965 with the beginnings of Conceptual Art but was well-preparedin the work of Frank Stella, who in his Black Paintingsfrom 1959 claimed both Rauschenberg'smonochromepaintings and Reinhardt'spaintingsas pointsof departure. Finally,it was the work of Sol - thatdemarcatesthatprecise LeWitt- in particularworksuch as his Structures transition,integratingas they do both language and visual sign in a structural model. The surfacesof these Structuresfrom 1961 to 1962 (some of which used singleframesfromMuybridge'sserialphotographs)carriedinscriptionsin bland the hue and shape of those surfaces(e.g., "RED SQUARE") letteringidentifying and the inscriptionitself(e.g., "WHITE LETTERS"). Since these inscriptions named either the support or the inscription(or, in the middle section of the painting,both supportand inscriptionin a paradoxical inversion),theycreated a continuousconflictin the viewer/reader.This conflictwas notjust over whichof the two roles should be performedin relationto the painting.To a largerextent it concerned the reliabilityof the given informationand the sequence of that information:was the inscriptionto be given primacyover the visual qualities identifiedby the linguisticentity,or was the perceptualexperience of the visual, formal,and chromaticelement anteriorto its mere denominationby language? Clearly this "mapping of the linguisticonto the perceptual" was not arguin ing favorof "the idea" -or linguisticprimacy- or the definitionof the work of art as an analyticproposition.Quite to the contrary,the permutationalcharacter of the work suggestedthat the viewer/readersystematically performall the visual and textual options the painting'sparametersallowed for. This included an acknowledgmentof the painting'scentral,square element:a spatial void that revealed the underlyingwall surface as the painting's architecturalsupport in actual space, therebysuspendingthe reading of the paintingbetween architectural structureand linguisticdefinition. Rather than privilegingone over the other, LeWitt's work (in its dialogue withJasperJohns'slegacyof paradox) insistedon forcingthe inherentcontradictions of the two spheres (that of the perceptual experience and that of the linguisticexperience) into the highestpossible relief. Unlike Frank Stella's reone step furtherinto sponse to Johns,whichforcedmodernistself-referentiality the ultimatecul de sac of itspositivistconvictions(his notoriousstatement"what 11. Marcel Duchamp, interviewwithFrancis Roberts (1963), ArtNews,(December 1968), p. 46. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Sol LeWitt. Untitled(Red Square,WhiteLetters). 1962. !!mulTE FIT" WHITE :i:i i i ...:i-iii:i:l; ... ........:i-;i-iiii:-:ii: ...... :iii ,: RED WHITE SQUARE LETT :i::jiiiili- ,::Fil you see is whatyou see" would attestto thatjust as muchas the developmentof his later work),12Sol LeWitt's dialogue (with both Johns and Stella, and ulti- 12. Stella's famous statementwas of course made in the conversationbetween Bruce Glaser, Donald Judd, and himself,in February 1964, and published in Art News (September 1966), pp. 55-61. To what extent the problem of this dilemma haunted the generationof Minimal artists becomes evident when almost ten years later, in an interviewwithJack Burnham,Robert Morris would stillseem to be responding(if perhaps unconsciously)to Stella's notoriousstatement: Paintingceased to interestme. There were certainthingsabout it that seemed very problematicto me. ... There was a big conflictbetweenthe factof doing thisthing, and what it looked like later. It just didn't seem to make much sense to me. Primarily This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 115 mately,of course, withGreenberg) developed a dialecticalpositionwithregard to the positivistlegacy. In contrastto Stella, his work now revealed thatthe modernistcompulsion for empiricistself-reflexiveness not only originated in the scientificpositivism which is the foundinglogic of capitalism(undergirdingits industrialformsof productionjust as muchas itsscienceand theory),but that,foran artisticpractice that internalizedthis positivismby insistingon a purelyempiricistapproach to vision, there would be a final destiny.This destinywould be to aspire to the conditionof tautology. It is not surprising,then,that when LeWitt formulatedhis second text on Conceptual Art-in his "Sentences on Conceptual Art" from the spring of firstsentence should programmaticallystate the radical difference 1969-rthe between the logic of scientificproductionand that of aestheticexperience: 1. Conceptual artistsare mysticsratherthan rationalists.They leap to conclusionsthat logic cannot reach. 2. Rationaljudgments repeat rationaljudgments. 3. Irrationaljudgments lead to new experience.13 RobertMorris'sParadoxes Theproblemhas beenfor sometimeone ofideas-those mostadmiredare theoneswiththebiggest, mostincisiveideas (e.g.,Cage & Duchamp) . I thinkthattodayart is a formofart history. - Robert Morris,letterto Henry Flynt,8/13/1962 Quite evidently,Morris's approach to Duchamp, in the early 1960s, had already been based on reading the readymade in analogy with a Saussurean model of language: a model where meaning is generated by structuralrelationships.As Morrisrecalls,his own "fascinationwithand respectforDuchamp was related to his linguisticfixation,to the idea that all of his operations were ultimatelybuilt on a sophisticatedunderstandingof language itself."'4Accordingly, Morris's early work (from 1961 to 1963) already pointed toward an understandingof Duchamp thattranscendedthe limiteddefinitionof the readybecause there was an activityI did in time,and there was a certainmethod to it. And thatdidn't seem to have any relationshipto the thingat all. There is a certainresolution in the theaterwhere thereis real time,and whatyoudo is whatyoudo. (emphasisadded) Robert Morris, unpublished interviewwithJack Burnham, November 21, 1975, Robert Morris Archive.Quoted in Maurice Berger,Labyrinths: RobertMorris,Minimalism, and the1960s (New York: Harper & Row, 1989), p. 25. 13. Sol LeWitt, "Sentences on Conceptual Art," firstpublished in 0-9, New York (1969), and Art-Language,Coventry(May 1969), p. 11. 14. Robert Morrisas quoted in Berger,Labyrinths, p. 22. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 116 OCTOBER made as the mere displacementof traditionalmodes of artisticproductionby a new aestheticof the speech act ("this is a workof art ifI say so"). And in marked distinctionfromthe Conceptualists'subsequentexclusivefocuson the unassisted readymades, Morris had, from the late 1950s when he discovered Duchamp, been particularlyengaged withwork such as ThreeStandard Stoppagesand the Notesfor theLarge Glass (The GreenBox). Morris'sproductionfromthe early 1960s, in particularworkslike Card File (1962), MeteredBulb (1963), I-Box (1963), Litanies,and the Statement ofAesthetic also entitledDocument(1963), indicateda reading of Duchamp that Withdrawal, clearlywentbeyondJohns's,leading towardsa structuraland semioticdefinition of the functionsof the readymade. As Morrisdescribed it retrospectively in his 1970 essay "Some Notes on the Phenomenologyof Making": There is a binaryswingbetweenthe arbitraryand the nonarbitraryor "motivated" which is . . . an historical,evolutionary,or diachronic featureof language's developmentand change. Language is not plasticart but bothare formsof human behaviorand the structuresof one can be compared to the structuresof the other.'5 While it is worthnoticingthatby 1970 Morrisalready reaffirmed apodictithe ontological characterof the category"plastic" art versus that of "lancally guage," it was in the early 1960s that his assaultson the traditionalconcepts of visualityand plasticityhad already begun to lay some of the crucial foundations for the developmentof an art practiceemphasizingits parallels,if not identity, withthe systemsof linguisticsigns,i.e., Conceptual Art. Most importantly,as early as 1961 in his Box withtheSound of Its Own Making, Morris had ruptured both. On the one hand, it dispenses with the Modernist quest for medium-specificpurityas much as with its sequel in the positivistconvictionof a purelyperceptualexperienceoperatingin Stella's visual tautologiesand the earlyphases of Minimalism.And on the other,by counteracting the supremacyof the visualwiththatof an auditoryexperienceof equal ifnot higher importance,he renewed the Duchampian quest for a nonretinalart. In Box withtheSound ofIts Own Making,as much as in the subsequent works,the critique of the hegemonyof traditionalcategories of the visual is enacted not only in the (acoustic or tactile) disturbanceof the purityof perceptual experience, but it is performedas well througha literalistact of denyingthe viewer practicallyall (at least traditionallydefined)visual information. This strategyof a "perceptual withdrawal"leads in each of the worksfrom the early 1960s to a differentanalysisof the constituentfeaturesof the structured object and the modes of reading it generates. In I-Box, for example, the vieweris confrontedwitha semioticpun (on the wordsI and eye)just as much as Robert Morris, "Some Notes on the Phenomenologyof Making: The Search for the Moti15. vol. 9 (April 1970), p. 63. vated," Artforum, This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions RobertMorris.I-Box. 1962. ?84iiiiiii-lj l iiii?ii iiii :,; ii:: iiiii . . . .. . .... .... .......... :F ........................................ .................. .......................... I.................. 1Omni: a, : .......... M W ................ .................... . ..... M N ~ ~~ i ::il ~iliiillM ONli ............. ~ ... W ?WWR: ~~"~~"~~ 8esle ~ i_:: witha structuralsleightof hand fromthe tactile(the viewerhas to manipulate the box physicallyto seetheI of theartist)throughthe linguisticsign(the letterI definesthe shape of the framing/display device: the "door" of the box) to the visualrepresentation(the nude photographicportraitof theartist)and back. It is of course this very tripartitedivisionof the aestheticsignifier- its separation into object, linguisticsign, and photographicreproduction-that we will encounter in infinitevariations,didacticallysimplified(to operate as stunning tautologies)and stylistically designed (to take the place of paintings)in Kosuth's after 1966. Proto-Investigations In Document(Statementof AestheticWithdrawal),Morris takes the literal negationof the visual even further,in clarifyingthatafterDuchamp the readymade is notjust a neutralanalyticproposition(in the mannerof an underlying statementsuch as "this is a work of art"). Beginningwiththe readymade,the workof art had become the ultimatesubjectof a legal definitionand theresultof institutional validation.In the absence of any specifically visualqualitiesand due This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 118 OCTOBER to the manifestlack of any (artistic)manual competenceas a criterionof distinction, all the traditional criteria of aesthetic judgment--of taste and of - have been programmatically voided. The resultof thisis that connoisseurship the definitionof the aestheticbecomes on the one hand a matterof linguistic convention and on the other the functionof both a legal contract and an institutionaldiscourse(a discourseof power ratherthan taste). This erosion works,then,notjust againstthe hegemonyof the visual,but against the possibilityof any other aspect of the aestheticexperience as being autonomousand self-sufficient. That the introductionof legalisticlanguage and an administrativestyleof the materialpresentationof the artisticobject could effectsuch an erosion had of course been prefiguredin Duchamp's practiceas well. In 1944 he had hireda notaryto inscribea statementof authenticity on his 1919 L.H.O.O.Q., affirming that ". . . this is to certifythat thisis the original :i:`i-i::: -'::;~'~~~~~~:ii-' ...... ....ii~ll":l:? ilk ....... . ..... :::_::-::?::-::. _: ::::-::::::::::: -. 'j~j-:-!~----:.~~~i~ 'fa "~-jri-t~'a~-: i~i~~ii~~tP:~~ar ::IP.............. .. ..-:-. --I-I . .... ... .... il~ii~ii: -........... I. :i~il_i............... '.............: .,,il-;:_ :-i:?:--::-::: ii-iii i,-iiiiiii'..... ......1. 1iffiak:: :~i-iii~~i~Wlb, FN w :-:-:::::::: ii';ili:'?-5:::;l`~::?l~~iiiiii -.._ ..::-----:-I--:I-:.......... ::-:::: -:::-:i:: i~i ii~ii--_ ..::: :? i-:.. 1:: i SrIN :-.::. :''i:-r~k~ :::.:.: i~i~i~i~iiL-ili~-:: :::.:: ::.....:.: :::::-:l:i;_-:?:..............?::: : .....i :-i-j ___: _:::::_............ i: -:~: iiiii~l~i: ?::. :"I:i:j::::::::i:: :-::::::::~:li'_:-::-_i~i-::::I-":: :o ...... ...... .. of Aesthetic Robert Morris.Untitled(Statement 1963. Withdrawal). This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ..... ConceptualArt 1962-1969 119 'ready-made'L.H.O.O.Q. Paris 1919." What was possiblystilla pragmaticmaneuver with Duchamp (although certainlyone in line withthe pleasure he took in contemplatingthe vanishingbasis forthe legitimatedefinitionof the workof art in visual competence and manual skill alone) would soon become one of the constituentfeaturesof subsequent developmentsin Conceptual Art. Most obviouslyoperatingin the certificatesissued by Piero Manzoni definingpersonsor partial persons as temporaryor lifetimeworks of art (1960-61), this is to be found at the same timein Yves Klein's certificatesassigningzones of immaterial pictorialsensibilityto the various collectorswho acquired them. But thisaestheticof linguisticconventionsand legalisticarrangementsnot the validityof the traditionalstudio aesthetic,it also cancels the denies only aestheticof productionand consumptionwhichhad stillgoverned Pop Art and Minimalism. Justas the modernistcritique(and ultimateprohibition)of figurativerepresentationhad become the increasinglydogmatic law for pictorialproductionin the firstdecade of the twentiethcentury,so Conceptual Art now instatedthe prohibitionof any and all visualityas the inescapableaestheticrule forthe end of the twentiethcentury.Just as the readymade had negated not only figurative representation,authenticity,and authorship while introducingrepetitionand the series(i.e., the law of industrialproduction)to replace the studioaestheticof the handcraftedoriginal,Conceptual Art came to displace even thatimage of the mass-producedobject and its aestheticizedformsin Pop Art, replacing an aestheticof industrialproductionand consumptionwithan aestheticof administrative and legal organizationand institutionalvalidation. Edward Ruscha's Books One major example of these tendencies--acknowledged both by Dan Graham as a major inspirationfor his own "Homes for America" and by Kosuth, whose "Art afterPhilosophy" names him as a proto-Conceptualartist-would be the early book work of Edward Ruscha. Among the key strategiesof future Conceptual Art that were initiatedby Ruscha in 1963 were the following:to chose the vernacular (e.g., architecture)as referent;to deploy photography as the representationalmedium; and to develop a new form of systematically distribution(e.g., the commerciallyproduced book as opposed to the traditionally craftedlivred'artiste. Typically,referenceto architecturein any formwhateverwould have been unthinkablein the context of American-typeformalismand AbstractExpressionism(or withinthe European postwaraestheticforthatmatter)untilthe early 1960s. The devotion to a privateaestheticof contemplativeexperience,withits concomitantabsence of any systematicreflectionof the social functionsof artistic production and their potential and actual publics, had, in fact,precluded any explorationof the interdependenceof architecturaland artisticproduction,be it This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions VARIOUS Edward Ruscha. Four Books. 1962-1966. .... ........ ASo LINE SMALL X, Asommm s ift iL ~~~~... FIRES .. . . ... .... ?... S TATsIONS NINE REAL SWIMMING ESTATE POOLS oPPORTUmms3 AndyWarhol.FromThirteen Most Wanted Men. 1964. even in the mostsuperficialand trivialformsof architecturaldecor.16 It was not untilthe emergenceof Pop Art in the early 1960s, in particularin the workof Bernd and Hilla Becher, Claes Oldenburg, and Edward Ruscha, thatthe references to monumentalsculpture(even in itsnegationas theAnti-Monument) and to vernaculararchitecturereintroduced(even ifonlyby implication)a reflectionon public (architecturaland domestic)space, therebyforegroundingthe absence of a developed artisticreflectionon the problematicof the contemporarypublics. In January1963 (the year of Duchamp's firstAmericanretrospective, held at the Pasadena Art Museum), Ruscha, a relativelyunknownLos Angeles artist, GasolineStations.The book, modest decided to publisha book entitledTwenty-Six It would be worthwhileto explore the factthatartistslike ArshileGorkyunder the impactof 16. the WPA programwould stillhave been concernedwiththeaestheticsof muralpaintingwhenhe was commissionedto decorate the NewarkAirportbuilding,and thateven Pollock tinkeredwiththe idea of an architecturaldimensionfor his paintings,wonderingwhethertheycould be transformedinto architecturalpanels. As is well known,Mark Rothko'sinvolvementwiththe Seagram Corporationto produce a set of decorativepanels for theircorporate headquartersended in disaster,and Barnett Newman's synagogueprojectwas abandoned as well. All of theseexceptionswould confirmthe rule that the postwar aesthetichad undergone the most rigorous privatizationand a reversal of the reflectionon the inextricablelink between artisticproductionand public social experienceas they had markedthe 1920s. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions :::i-;:::::: *? ~:;iiiiiriii'i-ii ~iii~i~ i-,:iii:::::-_ ::; -:?~ :.-. ir-i~:-l~ :-::: f :::-: iiijii:i -:::-:~' : ' : : : ::~-:~: a :: :ip? "'rd . e ::':: ::::::: ::::-: iiii a :: : ::E : : ::: ::::: -::?:-:::: :: ~clm B~iD??::: I;wL~" :.:: : : .::.::-:. . : ::: : :: --::::::::i:~: I~:~:::: : ::: :::: ::-::i:- :::::i : i: ---:~ * rl~~:-~B~J~FF~"": :::::::::_- a ::? :; 1 I ::::.f: ff: ~Pa~ -:O ::::: : ::::: :: :::::iii_? :1::i.-:-:::: :::::::::::-_;"Y)~ilrr~_:::::_:_::l-i::. * :::_:--::::::;: I:::: ::,ii::i: .. :: -:::: ?ii:iiiiiiili ::: i?:i-':'-:-::: :::: -::: 'i::_i '~::: ~:iii :-:::?-:::::~:?:i_:l: :?::_-:?:i:ii .::..:.: ::.-. ?:?iii~-;il-ii-: ~:::: ?:::::-:i ii::i -li ~;a?i ::.: :::::?::: i:-:::--:: :i-i:I::: :..:.:---.., ""._Bb;l C:~:ir:: : iwi :i Li*si~::-~ ~90;' i:: :I:I::.:.:?::: : ?:: :::?i:i, :::: :4 Biiililiiiiiii'ii'iiIiii? r-:-??i :? ::?;::?:::::??::::-:i:: ::i::'::':::::': :': :':' ':':' ''':':' ::?,,ii-iiiii:::'iiiiiiii~~-:::l?-iii:: :-:: :::: ::::-:::':-:':";:':': _i:i::::::?iiiiii:-:?:::~:":ii : ::::::::?:::':: :? :" :.::.'::'" :::_--:i:::-: :~:;:::1;XI:-'::6::li:::::i:.-~: i:::-::: _:;ilir'g-_i:i:9:r:--:~:?i::::: :_:: ::-._r~?:--":-"-_ ::::::::::: E:::::::: ~i_ii? :: iiii"';~i.:?:i::Eiiii' i:; 'iiiiiii-i~ ::i,;l:i_, :.:.: . i-:i;ii::::iiiiiii?i~rlii::i;~iiii-i-:i:;i ;ii;::i;:;i.-- ::: : : : :?:: :::-:? : ::':'.-...:. i: :iiii:--_i:i::-~: .:,ii?-ii-ii-iii~c' ~:::::-_::ii::ii: ?::::-:::::1:;:::: ii'iii:ii:l-i'iii:'i":iii~-iia~~i:il ~::ii.:':,:i L.i:i-:.ii;iiili.iiiiiiij:ijij:: :i:i-jiiji:ii:i:i:ii:i: i-:::i-i:jj:i: ::::: i:i-::;iiiiiiiii:iji:-:i:i_-:: i~~"'~'2~8~88~8P~P~~B~L~$~g~ia~ ^ : 1: *I! :i:i:::il.?I:?-::::: ?i:-': iiiiii ri~P--.-:inei?.~:82?I~?i?;i ~sLiL-~?i ::::::::-__ ::::::: [ii:iF :.: iuD?_~ . :_:_-::::?::: :. :::: ~-i~:i ::-- ? :::::::;:"": ::::'::-':- r_ ::::-: ::::::'-::: :-:::-i I::_:/::_::.: .::: --:-::'-'-:'-::: .--:-:?:'::-:-:i:-:-_?:.:::,:,--i-j: :-::i:::: :_:~:- F;i:::::::.:i:~:i~ ~:iiii::i:i-Zii~ ~:_:-::::: ii ::-: ::1::i::i :;:;::-?:::::::: :::-:j:,:::::-::: ::-:::~:::-_: ::-:i-i-i:.i . .: i:_::S:-:-::::i:i:i iii-ii::::::':'I' :':"~~ji~: :i:?::.:::----:ii::::ii::-:-:?i -.i::ii;~;;-aiiiiiii:ii:-?:l:ii?:i::_::: :::. j ?---i_-_:~ in formatand production,was as removedfromthe traditionof the artist'sbook as itsiconographywas opposed to everyaspect of the officialAmericanart of the 1950s and early '60s: the legacy of AbstractExpressionismand Color Field painting.The book was, however, not so alien to the artisticthoughtof the emerginggeneration,if one remembersthatthe year beforean unknownartist fromNew York bythe name of AndyWarholhad exhibiteda serialarrangement of thirty-two stenciledpaintingsdepicting Campbell Soup cans arranged like objectson shelvesin the Ferus Gallery.While both Warhol and Ruscha accepted a notionof public experiencethatwas inescapablycontainedin the conditionsof consumption,both artistsaltered the mode of productionas well as the formof distributionof theirworksuch thata different public was potentiallyaddressed. Ruscha's vernaculariconographyevolved to the same extentas Warhol's had fromthe Duchamp and Cage legacyof an aestheticof "indifference,"and fromthe commitmentto an antihierarchicalorganizationof a universallyvalid Indeed, random samplingand aleatory facticity, operatingas total affirmation. of possibleobjects (Ruscha's Twenty-Six choice froman infinity GasolineStations, Warhol's ThirteenMost WantedMen) would soon become essentialstrategiesof the aestheticof Conceptual Art: one thinksof AlighieroBoetti's The Thousand LongestRivers,of Robert Barry'sOne Billion Dots, of On Kawara's One Million This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions OCTOBER 122 in thiscontext,of Doug Huebler's life-longproject, Years,or, mostsignificantly entitledVariablePiece: 70. This workclaims to documentphotographically"the existenceof everyonealive in order to produce the mostauthenticand inclusive representationof the human species that may be'assembled in that manner. Editions of this work will be periodicallyissued in a varietyof topical modes: '100,000 people,' '1,000,000 people,' '10,000,000 people,' . . . etc." Or again, thereare the worksby StanleyBrouwn or Hanne Darboven where in each case an arbitrary,abstractprincipleof pure quantificationreplaces traditionalprinciples of pictorial or sculptural organization and/or compositional relational order. In the same mannerthatRuscha's books shiftedthe formalorganizationof the representation,the mode of presentationitselfbecame transformed:instead of liftingphotographic(or print-derived) imageryfrommass-culturalsourcesand transformingthese images into painting (as Warhol and the Pop Artistshad practicedit), Ruscha would now deploy photographydirectly,in an appropriate printingmedium. And it was a particularlylaconic typeof photographyat that, one thatexplicitlysituateditselfas muchoutsideof all conventionsof art photographyas outside of those of the venerable traditionof documentaryphotography,least of all thatof "concerned" photography.This devotion to a deadpan, anonymous,amateurishapproach to photographicformcorrespondsexactlyto Ruscha's iconographicchoice of the architecturalbanal. Thus at all three levels -the given forms -iconography, representationalform,mode of distribution of artisticobject no longer seemed acceptable in their traditionallyspecialized and privilegedpositions. As Victor Burgin put it with hindsight:"One of the thingsConceptual Art attemptedwas the dismantlingof the hierarchyof media according to which painting (sculpture trailingslightlybehind it) is assumed inherentlysuperiorto, most notably,photography.""7 Accordingly,even in 1965- 66, withthe earlieststagesof Conceptual practices, we witnessthe emergence of diametricallyopposed approaches: Joseph on the one hand (according to their author conKosuth's Proto-Investigations ceived and produced in 1965);18 and a work such as Dan Graham's Homesfor Victor Burgin, "The Absence of Presence," in The End of Art Theory(Atlantic Highlands, 17. 1986), p. 34. In the preparationof thisessay,I have not been able to finda singlesource or documentthat 18. would confirmwith definitecredibilityKosuth's claim that these works of the Proto-Investigations were actuallyproduced and existed physicallyin 1965 or 1966, when he (at that time twentyyears old) was stilla studentat the School of Visual Artsin New York. Nor was Kosuthable to provideany documentsto make the claimsverifiable.By contrastthese claimswere explicitlycontestedby all the artistsI interviewedwho knew Kosuth at that time, none of them rememberingseeing any of the ArtbyFour Young before February 1967, in the exhibitionNon-Anthropomorphic Proto-Investigations Artists,organized by Joseph Kosuth at the Lannis Gallery. The artistswith whom I conducted interviewswere Robert Barry,Mel Bochner,Dan Graham,and Lawrence Weiner. I am not necessarcould not have been done by Kosuth at the age of twenty ilysuggestingthat the Proto-Investigations or that the logical steps (afterall, Frank Stella had painted his Black Paintingsat age twenty-three), This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Homes for AflBerica ..................... .................. -----------........... ............. ............... ... ....... ............ ......... 11BAVIC1011 BAIXIAAW? RB(,CDDAA MAXAPMA IIAM)AACC JJDACW)AC R8J)1XX'AA JIM".'kb MA (X',XvK)DB8 CADWAOR Early 20th-Century CCO-DKIIAN CTVACORA Possessable House YA)AAB9(.'(., DACNOAKIS to the Quasi-Discrete Of MBAACC DB ACIAIAC DOMCCAA TJ8k':"M.A of '66 Cell A lm DT)CCAABA EICAADC4,13, i-a"11 ?!11DDCCbBAA 1`w st?f:tWw-oll, t" tlle_ mfariwg pwi D. GRAJ IANI ti;v iiall follolz-? A ki,,, 1 ehlf> n?-Ids. 4"'. e4sl K;Kl Belloplai" O*rdeft'Clly z-"IiV'RJ,." '.;n; Pa.* 1ift iti; l"A? -1, lm' -?; set Ikv.4c, GardenChy Colania rN! Swu?a colonia Ma Gre"law" island Par*A Wl"hp Fai Haven Levilown Fair Low" Viddumlia WO", palle? Gtoohn" Pork I. Now F' 1'1,e V'4"' Village City Green Pine Lawn Y."The", 'qA( Village plaintliborb Plainview Pleasw Grove Ft,, R Plandame, Monbr W--,h pleelika"I Plains ple"Antal" Sunset Hill Gordon plo"antwille 0;;' ':f:nton nkt, ft?.. "If, Jvvvlopi mlo' 'i-q:';?.Iwd ?oikkiil 'n-t'z Owiv 46-, 'Islk" j:1 a,: Il'sift l?lln? tli"'lltaimvl 01I.-iis v;, if luid a vhoz? ;I" .1u, it alt'.& ....... k h Rig 'O?q' 'A" iih 0'" ohl f'-huqd ';al li'-' aand 1a? hI,, 1-11, tel it "'ife" is?l'l alid wale f"%sl ii'r "of, Adait an.,! Imn'6e r,+,r A'sig-i ,1 a, ?.f it 'J aS!u' t'-m is 1" 4likia -'lq'?m aw'v. -Oe??' 1'? Ix"'I'lowR?ifj sr, ef'!'jg"ef ..ss at wn?" ""A ,a Mah. ?h'plf' Ilf wV??' Til'.m aw not !., ft?ieirln-li'l"t C"Ur j\,aivld4A'1 toN'.nn'i t'ilk" ?4?1 to Mile J?Ilia", wid hud "W-l f'w4!'p r"t 41 Ihi. f?fml Sloo: kste'?'f' IPm': tti.vimo-, lk, Lal? -I, 'kwii 0o, 1-4 s" 04, Y lik"'. It i?it" awbiw?; hi" D-vbq ?::txj ia'l ?I"" it, "J", th" C;';Y" ??A?'j-tall, -imr. Aw-d "I'i?tand 't I,, -'(JO .bh,?t, id", in [I.fill Af?_'O' lawl zhi! La?,tsl Cf?-i,,IAI'l" Chim", ,i'nlI,,W I?'I. ij IMIXI I'.: 11ON", bmlll? Ow it,.'t nlo'!O' 6"' Wshl'k t?' W ul"?' 'And flnu t'Aws v L. I" I?R. 'A "'a" I$ hii?' KJI?O 'oapt atft.mpf t;i: "w. This a, Thrw j miit, f"'s I: 4?'G;t? ?,fp?mk ixmil"w d"t"' 4M'd 5'i? gwj Tia, a'i' Moc-:;'t Oil, I"y"( eowleOvll? f"In ad'ano the m'?O plalmj _"'O le,,%'-th, A I,,: ?v-"i 'lIl ni'a' ?'a:d w", III,, 'g, ;.li the? op pw int'i in"t It, ma" fa?";"' ;w-'o"WN !m' 144*3trtl J.10A. a "I'x1-1. fir The SOMNAD6 "i F?-:i i" is iit tlilzsi A "a:Kti 1, 'Visi 11""l4Owielt'm'? ifIt: I 'Mw' 1: N.J. '(:;m; wt ir. W"k ?f-'a 'fop i??l 11??O Sw:;: gt 4?ti' ?pht ai -Wi,? ,nwNic1l, 1""'Vn Gr""" Vtll-; 'mo'? ill t-1 Ot'i' ?igltf: NJ, ji?ffxt?'thl, ;-014Jw P'Ne, Whit'. lw-z,,( PiA - 'Al 1" b"%"., "'A ....... k"! I'1".-4;1 7; 11 la-lf it" Th' 10t i?fl 61", i,ct?: Nk !'I(A U" 4o?vw? "Ij? ?!onlamed SI, "Z'? IIL?' m n 0,11 '1"?!f-d -I, a"'J?111':'111111"Ili A, ifI.... ?i'ql;i" J" "a, I,ill, '?l i"+'?"i'"'M< .I,-! to .j ?Itffi'rf?nt 1, ii'tl U, wi"& III, f??w OV Own -I'm fc?t' Ihf.n ?rom , 'T ;;iih: i,aan'WV; 1 f'il?W -1-a 1;i il-A r?-h -I'v 4"':tit.l? i?Iw i"'d W :i-F, ?V.Mji 1) It"At K: 5dll!arzi 1? 1' lis wl 14. 1; U116. j AA( ACIMACIOB it js Ai"', Ivy, A.AfAXICB), AlMiCAPW to 4I'm fw "'VIAM130 Ii.M;BAIX?ii -------------_- ARTS MAGA:9m? ............ ........... .......................... Dan Graham.HomesforAmerica(ArtsMagazine). December1966. Americaon the other.Publishedin ArtsMagazinein December 1966, the latteris a work which- unknownto most and long unrecognized-programmatically emphasized structuralcontingencyand contextuality,addressingcrucial questionsof presentationand distribution,of audience and authorship.At the same aestheticsof pertime the work linked Minimalism'sesotericand self-reflexive mutationto a perspectiveon the architectureof massculture(therebyredefining the legacyof Pop Art). The Minimalists'detachmentfromany representationof contemporarysocial experience upon which Pop Art had insisted,however resultedfromtheirattemptto constructmodels of visual meaningand furtively, experiencethatjuxtaposed formalreductionwitha structuraland phenomenological model of perception. fusingDuchamp and ReinhardtwithMinimalismand Pop Art leading up to the Proto-Investigations could not have been takenbyan artistof Kosuth'shistoricalawarenessand strategicintelligence.But I am sayingthatnone of the workdated by Kosuth to 1965 or 1966 can-until furtherevidence is produced-actually be documentedas 1965 or 1966 or dated withany credibility.By contrast,the at thattime),such as Something, wordpaintingsof On Kawara (whose studioKosuthvisitedfrequently are reproduced and documented. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions OCTOBER 124 By contrast,Graham's workargued foran analysisof (visual) meaningthat defined signs as both structurallyconstitutedwithinthe relationsof language's systemand grounded in the referentof social and politicalexperience. Further, Graham's dialectical conception of visual representationpolemicallycollapsed the differencebetweenthe spaces of productionand those of reproduction(what Seth Siegelaub would,in 1969, call primaryand secondaryinformation).'9Anticipating the work's actual modes of distributionand reception withinits very structureof production,HomesforAmericaeliminatedthe differencebetweenthe artisticconstructand its(photographic)reproduction,the differencebetweenan exhibitionof art objects and the photographof its installation,the difference betweenthe architecturalspace of the galleryand the space of the catalogue and the art magazine. JosephKosuth'sTautologies In oppositionto this,Kosuth was arguing,in 1969, preciselyforthe continuation and expansion of modernism'spositivistlegacy,and doing so withwhat musthave seemed to him at the timethe mostradical and advanced tools of that tradition:Wittgenstein'slogical positivismand language philosophy(he emphaticallyaffirmedthiscontinuitywhen,in the firstpartof "Art afterPhilosophy,"he states,"Certainlylinguisticphilosophycan be considered the heir to empiricism . ."). Thus, even while claimingto displace the formalismof Greenberg and For Kosuth Fried, he in fact updated modernism'sproject of self-reflexiveness. art by subjectingboth stabilizedthe notion of a disinterestedand self-sufficient -the Wittgensteinianmodel of the language game as well as the Duchampian model of the readymade- to the stricturesof a model of meaningthatoperates in the modernisttraditionof that paradox Michel Foucault has called modthought.This is to say that in 1968 artistic ernity's"empirico-transcendental" for is still the result, Kosuth,of artisticintentionas it constitutesitself production above all in self-reflexiveness (even if it is now discursiveratherthan perceptual, than rather essentialist).20 epistemological 19. "For many years it has been well known that more people are aware of an artist'swork through(1) the printedmedia or (2) conversationthanby directconfrontationwiththeart itself.For paintingand sculpture,where the visual presence-color, scale, size, location-is importantto the work, the photograph or verbalizationof that work is a bastardizationof the art. But when art concernsitselfwiththingsnot germaneto physicalpresence,itsintrinsic(communicative)value is not altered by its presentationin printedmedia. The use of catalogues and books to communicate(and disseminate)art is the most neutralmeans to presentthe new art. The catalogue can now act as the primaryinformationforthe exhibition,as opposed to secondaryinformationaboutart in magazines, catalogues, etc. and in some cases the 'exhibition' can be the 'catalogue."' (Seth Siegelaub, "On Exhibitionsand the World at Large" [interviewwith Charles Harrison],StudioInternational,[December 1969].) This differentiation is developed in Hal Foster's excellent discussionof these paradigmatic 20. differencesas theyemerge firstin Minimalismin his essay "The Crux of Minimalism,"in Individuals (Los Angeles: The Museum of ContemporaryArt, 1986), p. 162-183. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 125 At the very moment when the complementaryformationsof Pop and MinimalArt had, forthe firsttime,succeeded in criticizingthe legacyof Amerithis project is all the can-typeformalismand its prohibitionof referentiality, more astounding. The privilegingof the literal over the referentialaxis of (visual) language- as Greenberg's formalistaesthetichad entailed- had been countered in Pop Art by a provocativedevotion to mass-culturaliconography. Then, both Pop and Minimal Art had continuouslyemphasized the universal presence of industrialmeans of reproductionas inescapable framingconditions for artisticmeans of production,or, to put it differently, theyhad emphasized thatthe aestheticof the studio had been irreversibly replaced by an aestheticof Minimal And and Art had exhumed and consumption. finally,Pop production the repressed historyof Duchamp (and Dadaism at large), phenomena equally unacceptable to the reigningaestheticthoughtof the late 1950s and early '60s. Kosuth's narrowreading of the readymadeis astonishingforyetanotherreason. In 1969, he explicitlyclaimed that he had encountered the work of Duchamp primarilythroughthe mediation of Johns and Morris rather than throughan actual studyof Duchamp's writingsand works.21 As we have seen above, the firsttwo phases of Duchamp's reception by Americanartistsfromthe early 1950s (Johnsand Rauschenberg)to Warhol and Morrisin the early 1960s had graduallyopened up the range of implicationsof Duchamp's readymades.22It is thereforeall the more puzzling to see that after 1968-what one could call the beginning of the third phase of Duchamp See note 5 above. 21. As Rosalind Krauss has suggested,at leastJohns's understandingat that point already tran22. scended the earlier reading of the readymade as merelyan aestheticof declarationand intention: If we consider that Stella's paintingwas involvedearly on, in the work of Johns,then Johns'sinterpretationof Duchamp and the readymade-an interpretationdiametricallyopposed to thatof the Conceptualistgroup outlinedabove - has some relevancein thisconnection.For Johnsclearlysaw the readymadeas pointingto the factthatthere need be no connectionbetween the finalart object and the psychologicalmatrixfrom whichit issued,since in the case of the readymadethispossibilityis precluded fromthe start. The Fountain was not made (fabricated)by Duchamp, only selected by him. Therefore there is no way in which the urinal can "express" the artist. It is like a sentence which is put into the world unsanctionedby the voice of a speaker standing behind it. Because makerand artistare evidentlyseparate,thereis no wayforthe urinal to serve as an externalizationof the state or statesof mind of the artistas he made it. And by not functioningwithinthe grammarof the aestheticpersonality,the Fountain can be seen as puttingdistancebetween itselfand the notion of personalityper se. The relationshipbetweenJohns'sAmericanFlag and his reading of the Fountainisjust this: the arthood of the Fountainis not legitimizedby itshavingissued stroke-by-stroke from the privatepsycheof the artist;indeed it could not. So it is like a man absentmindedly hummingand being dumbfoundedifasked ifhe had meantthattune or ratheranother. That is a case in which it is not clear how the grammarof intentionmightapply. vol. 12 (November 1973), pp. 43-52, n. 4. Rosalind Krauss, "Sense and Sensibility,"Artforum, This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions OCTOBER 126 reception- the understandingof this model by Conceptual Artistsstill foregroundsintentionaldeclarationover contextualization.This holds true not only for Kosuth's "Art afterPhilosophy,"but equally forthe BritishArt& Language Group, as, in the introductionto the firstissue of thejournal in May 1969, they write: To place an object in a contextwhere the attentionof any spectator willbe conditionedtoward the expectancyof recognizingart objects. For example placingwhatup to thenhad been an object of alien visual characteristicsto those expected withinthe frameworkof an art ambience, or by virtue of the artistdeclaring the object to be an art object whetheror not it was in an art ambience. Using these techniques whatappeared to be entirelynew morphologieswere held out to qualifyfor the statusof the membersof the class "art objects." For example Duchamp's "Readymades" and Rauschenberg's "Portraitof Iris Clert."23 A few months later Kosuth based his argument for the development of Conceptual Art on just such a restrictedreading of Duchamp. For in its limiting view of the historyand the typologyof Duchamp's oeuvre, Kosuth's argument -like that of Art & Language- focuses exclusivelyon the "unassistedreadymades." Thereby early Conceptual theory not only leaves out Duchamp's painterlywork but avoids such an eminentlycrucial workas the ThreeStandard Stoppages(1913), not to mentionTheLarge Glass (1915-23) or the Etantsdonne (1946 - 66) or the 1943 Boiteen valise. But what is worse is thateven the reading of the unassistedreadymadesis itselfextremelynarrow,reducingthe readymade model in factmerelyto that of an analyticalproposition.Typically,both Art & Language and Kosuth's "Art afterPhilosophy"referto Robert Rauschenberg's notoriousexample of speech-actaesthetics("This is a portraitof Iris ClertifI say so") based on the rather limitedunderstandingof the readymade as an act of willfulartisticdeclaration. This understanding,typicalof the early 1950s, continues in Judd's famous lapidary norm (and patentlynonsensical statement), ." quoted a littlelaterin Kosuth's text: "if someone saysit's art,thenit is art In 1969, Art & Language and Kosuth shared in foregroundingthe... "analyticproposition" inherentin each readymade,namelythe statement"this is a workof art," over and above all other aspects impliedby the readymade model (its structurallogic, its featuresas an industriallyproduced object of use and consumption,its seriality,and the dependence of its meaning on context).And most importantly,according to Kosuth, this means that artisticpropositions be it that of the constitutethemselvesin the negation of all referentiality, historicalcontextof the (artistic)sign or that of its social functionand use: 23. Introduction,Art& Language, vol. 1, no. 1 (May 1969), p. 5. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions \il ~: 4 4: :?:::2: ?: Worksofartare analyticpropositions. That is,ifviewedwithintheir no information what-so-ever about any context-as-art, theyprovide matter offact.A workofartisa tautology inthatitisa presentation of theartist'sintention, thatis,he is sayingthatthatparticular workof artis art,whichmeans,isa definition ofart.Thus,thatitisartistruea priori(whichis whatJuddmeanswhenhe statesthat"ifsomeonecalls it art,it'sart").24 1969 Or, a littlelaterin the same year,he wrotein TheSixthInvestigation 14 (a textthathas mysteriously vanishedfromthecollectionof his Proposition writings): If one considersthattheformsarttakesas beingart'slanguageone can realizethenthata workofartis a kindofproposition presented withinthecontextofartas a comment on art.An analysis ofproposi24. Joseph Kosuth, "Art after Philosophy," Studio International,nos. 915-917 December 1969). Quoted here fromJoseph Kosuth, The MakingofMeaning,p. 155. (October- Kosuth.FiveFives(to DonaldJudd).1965 (). Joseph This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 128 OCTOBER tion typesshows art "works" as analyticpropositions.Works of art that tryto tell us somethingabout the world are bound to fail. The absence of realityin art is exactlyart's reality.25 Kosuth's programmaticeffortsto reinstatea law of discursiveself-reflexiveness in the guise of a critique of Greenberg's and Fried's visual and formal are all the more astonishingsince a considerablepart of "Art self-reflexiveness afterPhilosophy" is dedicated to the elaborate constructionof a genealogy for Conceptual Art,in and of itselfa historicalproject(e.g., "All art [afterDuchamp] is conceptual [in nature] because art exists only conceptually"). This veryconstructionof a lineage already contextualizesand historicizes,of course, in "telling us somethingabout the world"-of art, at least; that is, it unwittingly operates like a syntheticproposition(even if only withinthe conventionsof a particularlanguage system)and thereforedenies both thepurityand the possibilityof an autonomous artisticproductionthat would function,withinart's own as mere analyticproposition. language-system, one Perhaps mighttryto argue that,in fact,Kosuth's renewed cult of the the Symbolistproject to fruition.It mightbe said, forexample, tautologybrings that thisrenewal is the logical extensionof Symbolism'sexclusive concern with the conditionsand the theorizationof art's own modes of conceptionand reading. Such an argument,however,would stillnot allay questions concerningthe altered historicalframeworkwithinwhich such a cult must findits determination. Even withinitsSymbolistorigins,the modernisttheologyof art was already gripped by a polarized opposition. For a religiousvenerationof self-referential plasticformas the pure negationof rationalistand empiricistthoughtcan simultaneouslybe read as nothingother than the inscriptionand instrumentalization of preciselythatorder- even or particularlyin its negation- withinthe realm of the aestheticitself(the almostimmediateand universalapplicationof Symbolism for the cosmos of late nineteenth-century commodityproduction would attestto this). in the This dialecticcame to claim itshistoricalrightsall the more forcefully a acceleratFor the conditions of situation. rapidly given contemporary,postwar ing fusionof the cultureindustrywiththe lastbastionsof an autonomous sphere of highart,self-reflexiveness increasingly(and inevitably)came to shiftalong the borderline between logical positivismand the advertisementcampaign. And further,the rightsand rationaleof a newlyestablishedpostwarmiddle class,one whichcame fullyinto itsown in the 1960s, could assume theiraestheticidentity in the verymodel of the tautologyand itsaccompanyingaestheticof administration. For this aesthetic identityis structuredmuch the way this class's social identityis, namely,as one of merelyadministeringlabor and production(rather than producing) and of the distributionof commodities.This class, having be25. 1969 Proposition14. Joseph Kosuth, The SixthInvestigation This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 129 establishedas the mostcommonand powerfulsocial class of postwar come firmly one which,as H. G. Helms wrote in his book on Max Stirner, is the society, itself voluntarilyof the rightsto intervenewithinthe politicaldecision"deprives with the existing making process in order to arrange itselfmore efficiently conditions."26 political This aestheticof the newlyestablishedpower of administrationfound its firstfullydeveloped literaryvoice in a phenomenon like the nouveau romanof Robbe-Grillet.It was no accidentthatsuch a profoundlypositivistliteraryproject would then serve, in the Americancontext,as a point of departurefor Conceptual Art. But, paradoxically,it was at thisverysame historicalmomentthat the social functionsof the tautological principle found their most lucid analysis, througha criticalexaminationlaunched in France. In the early writingof Roland Barthes one finds,simultaneouslywiththe nouveau roman,a discussionof the tautological: Tautologie.Yes, I know,it's an uglyword. But so is the thing.Tautologyis the verbaldevice whichconsistsin defininglikeby like("Drama is drama"). . . . One takes refugein tautologyas one does in fear,or anger, or sadness, when one is at a loss for an explanation. . . . In tautology,there is a double murder: one kills rationalitybecause it resistsone; one kills language because it betraysone. . . . Now any refusalof language is a death. Tautology createsa dead, a motionless world.27 Ten years later,at the same momentthat Kosuth was discoveringit as the centralaestheticproject of his era, the phenomenonof the tautologicalwas once again opened to examinationin France. But now, ratherthan being discussedas a linguisticand rhetoricalform,it was analyzed as a general social effect:as both the inescapable reflexof behavior and, once the requirementsof the advanced culture industry(i.e., advertisementand media) have been put in place in the formationof spectacle culture, a universalcondition of experience. What still remainsopen fordiscussion,of course, is the extentto whichConceptual Artof a certaintypeshared these conditions,or even enacted and implementedthem in the sphere of the aesthetic-accounting, perhaps, for its subsequent proximity and success withina world of advertisementstrategists-or, alternatively,the extent to which it merelyinscribeditselfinto the inescapable logic of a totally administeredworld,as Adorno's notorioustermidentifiedit. Thus Guy Debord noted in 1967: The basically tautological character of the spectacle flowsfrom the simple fact that its means are simultaneouslyits ends. It is the sun 26. 27. Hans G. Helms, Die Ideologieder anonymenGesellschaft (Cologne, 1968), p. 3. Roland Barthes,Mythologies, pp. 152- 53. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 130 OCTOBER which never sets over the empire of modern passivity.It covers the entiresurfaceof the world and bathes endlesslyin its own glory.28 A Tale ofMany Squares The visual formsthatcorrespondmost accuratelyto the linguisticformof the tautologyare the square and itsstereometricrotation,the cube. Not surprisingly,these two formsproliferatedin the painterlyand sculpturalproductionof the early-to mid-1960s. This was the momentwhen a rigorousself-reflexiveness was bent on examiningthe traditionalboundariesof modernistsculpturalobjects to the same extent that a phenomenological reflectionof viewing space was insistanton reincorporatingarchitecturalparameters into the conception of paintingand sculpture. So thoroughlydid the square and the cube permeate the vocabulary of Minimalistsculpturethatin 1967 Lucy Lippard publisheda questionnaireinvestigatingthe role of theseforms,whichshe had circulatedamong manyartists.In his response to the questionnaire,Donald Judd, in one of his manyattemptsto detach the morphologyof Minimalismfromsimilarinvestigationsof the historical avant-gardein the earlier part of the twentiethcentury,displayedthe agressive dimensionof tautologicalthought(disguisedas pragmatism,as was usual in his case) by simplydenying that any historicalmeaning could be inherentin geometricor stereometricforms: I don't thinkthere is anythingspecial about squares, which I don't use, or cubes. They certainlydon't have any intrinsicmeaning or superiority.One thing though, cubes are a lot easier to make than spheres. The main virtue of geometric shapes is that they are not organic, as all art otherwiseis. A formthat's neithergeometricnor organic would be a great discovery.29 the square abolishes the As the central form of visual self-reflexiveness, traditionalspatial parametersof verticalityand horizontality,therebycanceling the metaphysicsof space and itsconventionsof reading. It is in thisway thatthe square (beginningwithMalevich's 1915 Black Square) incessantlypointsto itself: 28. Guy Debord, The SocietyoftheSpectacle(Detroit: Black & Red, 1970), n. p., section 13. First published,Paris, 1967. Donald Judd,in Lucy Lippard, "Homage to the Square," Artin America(July-August, 1967), 29. pp. 50-57. How pervasive the square actuallywas in the art of the early-to mid-1960s is all too obvious: the workfromthe late '50s, such as paintingsby Reinhardtand Rymanand a large number of sculpturesfromthe early 1960s onwards (Andre, LeWitt, and Judd), deployed the tautological formin endless variations.Paradoxicallyeven Kosuth's workfromthe mid-1960s- while emphasizing its departure frompainting'straditionalobject statusand visual/formaldesign-continues to displaythe definitionsof words on large, black, canvas squares. By contrastone only has to thinkof JasperJohns'sor BarnettNewman's workas immediatepredecessorsof thatgenerationto recognize how infrequent,if not altogetherabsent, the square was at that moment. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions RobertBarry.Paintingin Four Parts. 1967. * i~iiiii~iII U Uii~iii as spatial perimeter,as plane, as surface,and, functioningsimultaneously,as support.But, withthe verysuccess of thisself-referential gesture,markingthe formout as purely pictorial,the square paintingparadoxicallybut inevitably assumesthe characterof a relief/objectsituatedin actual space. It therebyinvites a viewing/readingof spatialcontingencyand architecturalimbeddedness,insisting on the imminentand irreversibletransitionfrompaintingto sculpture. This transitionwas performedin the proto-Conceptualart of the early-to mid-1960s in a fairlydelimitednumber of specificpictorialoperations. It occurred,firstof all, throughthe emphasison painting'sopacity.The object-status of the painterlystructurecould be underscoredby unifyingand homogenizing its surfacethroughmonochromy,serializedtexture,and gridded compositional structure;or it could be emphasized by literallysealing a painting's spatial transparency,by simplyalteringits materialsupport:shiftingit fromcanvas to unstretchedfabricor metal. This typeof investigationwas developed systematically, for example, in the proto-Conceptualpaintingsof Robert Ryman,who employedall of these optionsseparatelyor in varyingcombinationsin the earlyto mid-i1960s;or, after1965, in thepaintingsof RobertBarry,Daniel Buren,and Niele Toroni. Secondly- and in a directinversionand countermovementto the firstobject-statuscould be achieved by emphasizing,in a literalistmanner,painting's This entailed establishinga dialectic between pictorial surface, transparency. frame,and architecturalsupportby eithera literalopening up of the painterly or by the insertionof translucentor support,as in Sol LeWitt's earlyStructures, surfaces the frame of viewing,as in Ryman's into conventional transparent Buren's fiberglasspaintings, earlynylonpaintings,or Michael Asher's and Ger- This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Robert Morris.FourMirroredCubes.1965. hard Richter'sglass panes in metal frames,both emergingbetween 1965 and 1967. Or, as in the earlyworkof RobertBarry(suchas hisPaintingin FourParts, 1967, in the FER-Collection),where the square, monochrome,canvas objects now seemed to assume the role of mere architecturaldemarcation.Functioning as decenteredpainterlyobjects,theydelimitthe externalarchitecturalspace in a manneranalogous to the serial or centralcompositionof earlier Minimalwork that stilldefinedinternalpictorialor sculpturalspace. Or, as in Barry'ssquare canvas (1967), which is to be placed at the exact center of the architectural shiftingthe reading of it supportwall, a workis conceived as programmatically froma centered,unified,pictorialobject to an experience of architecturalcontingence,and as therebyincorporatingthe supplementaryand overdetermining strategiesof curatorialplacementand conventionsof installation(traditionally of the work itself. disavowed in paintingand sculpture)into the conception And thirdly--and most often--this transitionis performedin the "simple" rotationof the square, as originallyevident in Naum Gabo's famous diagram from1937 where a volumetricand a stereometriccube are juxtaposed in order to clarifythe inherentcontinuitybetweenplanar,stereometric,and volumetric forms. This rotation generated cubic structuresas diverse as Hans Haacke's CondensationCube (1963-65), Robert Morris's Four MirroredCubes (1965), or LarryBell's simultaneously produced MineralCoatedGlass Cubes,and :.::i::::::':::: ::::-'::::l:i::::i:-:::?::-:~:'::"~~:::: :- ::,_:::i:_:.:::::_::?_ ::: :::::? ~ iiiii::i:iii i-:--::- 1~ ::~s: : :::: ::::::::::`:::::: :::::::i ::?::::::::: :.:::::: ::::: ~:_I :::::-::1::::--::I-:: : ;-:::::ii: ::i:::: ::.::::::: ::::::::::::::':; ::~::~xi-::;:-::::::;i:_;:i:::;i::::,: ::::::-: ::j :::::: ::I::::: il~::3i:i i::-::-::: - -----: :-S--i:---::'-'i~~'~ril:~iiiiii-iiiilil~ ?:-::::: ~::::i:: --:-- ~':~-:~--'I::-:::-i: ---::::::i::::-?:l~" :::::: -:::i;~~~zii:iii:ii:~i,-aiiii:::-;~~i~; ::?`?:iii':ii'~iiiii:iiii;iiii~aiili :::::_::i~i -:':':'i:ii :::::: ::':::' _~::::::;-:~:~::.;:: i;~.l~iiiiiii:i~i::i:::i~:::iii-: .---_i ::-:-:-;::-:i:::: _::_:::-::::: ::-:::: :::::-:::i~::::-: Li-iliB This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Cube. 1963-65. Hans Haacke.Condensation Sol LeWitt's Wall-FloorPiece(ThreeSquares), 1966. All of these (beyondsharing the obvious morphologyof the cube) engage in the dialectic of opacity and as in transparency(or in the synthesisof that dialectic in mirror-reflection Morris'sMirroredCubesor LarryBell's aestheticizedvariationsof the theme).At the same timethattheyengage in the dialecticof frameand surface,and thatof object and architecturalcontainer,theyhave displacedtraditionalfigure-ground relationships. The deploymentof any or all of these strategies(or, as in mostcases, their varyingcombination)in the contextof Minimaland post-Minimalart,i.e., protoconceptualpaintingand sculpture,resultedin a range of hybridobjects.They no longerqualifiedforeitherof the traditionalstudio categoriesnor could theybe identifiedas reliefor architecturaldecoration-the compromisetermstraditionallyused to bridge the gap between these categories. In this sense, these objects demarcated another spectrumof departurestowards Conceptual Art. Not onlydid theydestabilizethe boundariesof the traditionalartisticcategories of studioproduction,byerodingthemwithmodes of industrialproductionin the manner of Minimalism,but they went furtherin their criticalrevisionof the discourse of the studio versus the discourse of production/consumption.By ultimatelydismantlingboth along withthe conventionsof visualityinherentin them,theyfirmlyestablishedan aestheticof administration. III IOWN _K- .. 'K, Wv W, icy W *4 AW, "n $ 4001 % ?k ...... NI qqpp ?w : AM A 7, IC-1 QA to, ZOO X x ATS Ilk a=* f, JOIN '?r-, C law ?w' %n WX aI. '.?Vo TAT .Fl _7117, ... ........... This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 134 OCTOBER The diversityof these protoconceptualobjects would at firstsuggestthat theiractual aestheticoperationsdifferso profoundlythata comparativereading, operatingmerelyon the grounds of theirapparent analogous formaland morphologicalorganization- the visualtopos of the square- would be illegitimate. Art historyhas accordinglyexcluded Haacke's CondensationCube,for example, from any affiliationwith Minimal Art. Yet all of these artistsdefine artistic productionand receptionby the mid-1960s as reachingbeyond the traditional thresholdsof visuality(both in termsof the materialsand productionprocedures of the studio and those of industrialproduction),and it is on the basis of this parallel thattheirworkcan be understoodto be linkedbeyond a mere structural or morphologicalanalogy. The proto-conceptualworksof the mid-1960s redefine aesthetic experience, indeed, as a multiplicityof nonspecializedmodes of object-and language-experience.Accordingto the reading these objects generate, aestheticexperience-as an individualand social investmentof objects with meaning-is constitutedby linguisticas well as by specularconventions,by the institutionaldeterminationof the object's status as much as by the reading competence of the spectator. Within this shared conception,what goes on to distinguishthese objects from each other is the emphasis each one places on differentaspects of that deconstructionof the traditionalconceptsof visuality.Morris'sMirroredCubes, for example (once again in an almost literalexecution of a proposal found in Duchamp's GreenBox),situatethe spectatorin thesutureof the mirrorreflection: that interfacebetween sculpturalobject and architecturalcontainerwhere neitherelementcan acquire a positionof priorityor dominancein the triadbetween spectator,sculpturalobject, and architecturalspace. And in so far as the work acts simultaneouslyto inscribea phenomenologicalmodel of experience into a traditionalmodel of purelyvisual specularityand to displace it, itsprimaryfocus remainsthe sculpturalobject and its visual apperception. By contrast,Haacke's CondensationCube-while clearlysufferingfroma now even more rigorouslyenforced scientisticreductivismand the legacy of - moves modernism'sempiricalpositivism away froma specular relationshipto the object altogether,establishinginsteada bio-physicalsystemas a linkbetween viewer,sculpturalobject, and architecturalcontainer.If Morrisshiftsthe viewer froma mode of contemplativespecularityintoa phenomenologicalloop of bodily movementand perceptual reflection,Haacke replaces the once revolutionary concept of an activating"tactility"in the viewing experience by a move to bracketthe phenomenologicalwithinthe determinacyof "system."For his work now suspends Morris's tactile"viewing" withina science-basedsyntagm(in this particularcase that of the process of condensationand evaporation inside the cube broughtabout by temperaturechanges due to the frequencyof spectators in the gallery). And finally,we should consider what is possiblythe last credible transformationof the square, at the heightof Conceptual Art in 1968, in two worksby This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions iii' jiiiiiiiiii iiiii-i-iii iil: :i~j::::-:ii::':::i- ._: .......:: ::? ::I -:i: ...iiiiiiii~iii -i:-!iI :i:: :-i-lijiiil-ilii-:i:i jii:--; :iii-iii'_? :???:: i1::::::?_:::?:::::::::: ??:!i~~i ::-:.-_:::::_i: ::-i:iii:i:_r: : ::i:::::::: :::-:::: Lawrence Weiner,respectively entitledA Square Removalfrom a Rug in Useand A 36" X 36" Removalto theLathingor SupportWall ofPlasteror Wallboardfroma Wall (both publishedor "reproduced" in Statements, 1968), in whichthe specific Art with initiates paradigmaticchanges Conceptual regard to the legacy of - while maintainreductivistformalismare clearlyevident. Both interventions their structural and links with formal traditions ing morphological by respecting classicalgeometryas theirdefinitionat the level of shape--inscribe themselves in the supportsurfacesof the institutionand/or the home whichthattradition had alwaysdisavowed. The carpet (presumablyfor sculpture)and the wall (for painting),which idealistaestheticsalwaysdeclares as mere "supplements,"are foregroundedhere not onlyas partsof theirmaterialbasis but as the inevitable futurelocation of the work. Thus the structure,location,and materialsof the at the verymomentof theirconception,are completelydetermined intervention, their future destination.While neithersurfaceis explicitlyspecifiedin terms by of its institutionalcontext,this ambiguityof dislocationgeneratestwo oppositional,yetmutuallycomplementaryreadings.On the one hand, it dissipatesthe traditionalexpectationof encounteringthe workof art onlyin a "specialized" or "qualified" location(both "wall" and "carpet" could be eitherthoseof the home or the museum,or, for that matter,could just as well be found in any other location such as an office,for example). On the other, neither one of these surfacescould ever be consideredto be independentfromits institutionallocation, since the physicalinscriptioninto each particularsurfaceinevitablygenerates contextualreadingsdependent upon the institutionalconventionsand the particularuse of those surfacesin place. A 36" x 36" SquareRemovalto Lawrence Weiner. theWallboardor Lathingfroma Wall.1968. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions OCTOBER 136 Transcending the literalistor perceptual precision with which Barryand Rymanhad previouslyconnectedtheirpainterlyobjectsto the traditionalwallsof display,in order to make theirphysicaland perceptual interdependencemanifest,Weiner's two squares are now physicallyintegratedwithboththese support surfacesand theirinstitutionaldefinition.Further,since the work's inscription paradoxicallyimpliesthe physicaldisplacementof the supportsurface,it engenders an experienceof perceptualwithdrawalas well. Andjust as the worknegates the specularityof the traditionalartisticobject by literallywithdrawingrather than adding visual data in the construct,so this act of perceptualwithdrawal operatesat the same timeas a physical(and symbolic)interventionin the institutional power and property relations underlyingthe supposed neutralityof "mere" devices of presentation.The installationand/or acquisitionof eitherof these works requires that the futureowner accept an instance of physicalreon both the level of institutionalorder and on moval/withdrawal/interruption that of privateownership. It was only logical that, on the occasion of Seth Siegelaub's firstmajor exhibitionof Conceptual Art, the show entitledJanuary5-31, 1969, Lawrence Weiner would have presented a formula that then functionedas the matrix underlyingall his subsequent propositions.Specificallyaddressingthe relations withinwhich the work of art is constitutedas an open, structural,syntagmatic formula,thismatrixstatementdefinesthe parametersof a workof art as thoseof the conditionsof authorshipand production,and their interdependencewith thoseof ownershipand use (and not leastof all, at itsown propositionallevel,as a contingentupon and determinedby all of theseparametersin definition linguistic theircontinuouslyvaryingand changingconstellations: Withrelationto thevariousmannersofuse: thepiece 1. The artistmayconstruct 2. The piecemaybefabricated 3. The pieceneed notto be built withtheintentoftheartistthedecisionas to Each beingequal and consistent conditionrestswiththereceiverupon theoccasionof receivership What begins to be put in play here, then,is a critiquethat operates at the level of the aesthetic"institution."It is a recognitionthat materialsand procedures, surfacesand textures,locationsand placementare not only sculpturalor painterlymatterto be dealt with in terms of a phenomenologyof visual and cognitiveexperienceor in termsof a structuralanalysisof the sign(as mostof the artistshad stillbelieved), but thattheyare always Minimalistand post-Minimalist already inscribedwithinthe conventionsof language and therebywithininstitutionalpower and ideological and economic investment.However, if,in Weiner's and Barry'swork of the late 1960s, thisrecognitionstillseems merelylatent,it was to become manifestveryrapidlyin the workof European artistsof the same generation,in particularthat of Marcel Broodthaers,Daniel Buren, and Hans This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 137 Haacke after1966. In factan institutional critiquebecame thecentralfocusofall threeartists'assaultson the falseneutralityof visionthatprovidesthe underlying rationalefor those institutions. In 1965, Buren-like his Americanpeers--took offfroma criticalinvestigationof Minimalism.His earlyunderstandingof the workof Flavin,Ryman, and Stella rapidly enabled him to develop positions from within a strictly painterlyanalysisthatsoon led to a reversalof painterly/sculptural conceptsof Buren was on the one hand with a critical reviewof visualityaltogether. engaged the legacyof advanced modernist(and postwarAmerican)paintingand on the otherin an analysisof Duchamp's legacy,whichhe viewedcriticallyas the utterly unacceptablenegationof painting.This particularversionof reading Duchamp and the readymade as acts of petit-bourgeoisanarchistradicality- while not necessarilycomplete and accurate-allowed Buren to constructa successful critique of both: modernistpaintingand Duchamp's readymade as its radical historicalOther. In his writingsand his interventionsfrom 1967 onwards, throughhis critique of the specular order of paintingand of the institutional i-ii-i-~ : ii~:ii:ii-iiii ili:iiii::?-i?ji:iii-i:iiii ;:iEii$B :::::''' Daniel Buren.Installationat the InternationalExhibition. Guggenheim 1971. ;,i-i~:: :::-: ::::: I:: -::-:i:::::-:9:i::-:i,-::' :%:-:::::: :i~.~k~$P:l:':~::i--~:i-jlB:, :: :::::~-:: _-:::-:::::--:i-:_-:?:_-:::::_ii::I-i:-:-_?:::~?9~s: :~-::::i-:i::-::l-:-i ::~--::~:'i:~ "?:::I:iZI::L: :'::": i.ii:-ii::::i-:~iii-'t I- ig?a~ i-si-ii~i?::-iiiiiliii~ This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Toroni. Buren,Mosset,Parmentier, NumberFour, September Manifestation 1967, FifthBiennalede Paris, Musie d'art modernede la Villede Paris. 1%S; ftkw-% VW v , W Is: l ft ? fl" forf,_ wX, frameworkdeterminingit, Buren singularlysucceeded in displacingboththe paradigmsof paintingand that of the readymade(even twentyyears later this critiquemakes the naive continuationof object productionin the Duchampian vein of the readymademodel appear utterlyirrelevant). From the perspectiveof the present,it seems easier to see that Buren's assault on Duchamp, especiallyin his crucial 1969 essay LimitesCritiques,was operativeand preprimarilydirectedat the conventionsof Duchamp reception dominantthroughoutthe late 1950s and early '60s, ratherthan at the actual implicationsof Duchamp's model itself.Buren's centralthesiswas thatthe fallacy of Duchamp's readymade was to obscure the very institutionaland discursive framingconditionsthat allowed the readymade to generate its shiftsin the assignmentof meaningand the experience of the object in the firstplace. Yet, one could just as well argue, as Marcel Broodthaerswould in factsuggestin his catalogue of the exhibitionTheEaglefromtheOligoceneto Todayin Dfisseldorfin constructionof the workof 1972, thatthe contextualdefinitionand syntagmatic art had obviouslybeen initiatedby Duchamp's readymademodel firstof all. In his systematicanalysisof the constitutingelementsof the discourseof painting,Buren came to investigateall the parametersof artisticproductionand reception (an analysisthat, incidentally,was similarto the one performedby Lawrence Weiner in arrivingat his own "matrix" formula). Departing from of paintMinimalism's(especiallyRyman'sand Flavin's)literalistdismemberment ing, Buren at firsttransformedthe pictorialinto yet another model of opacity and objecthood. (This was accomplished by physicallyweaving figure and This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 139 ground together in the "found" awning material, by making the "grid" of vertical parallel stripes his eternallyrepeated "tool," and by mechanicallyalmostsuperstitiously or ritualistically, one could say withhindsight-applying a coat of white paint to the outer bands of the grid in order to distinguishthe pictorialobject froma readymade.) At the same time that the canvas had been removed fromitstraditionalstretchersupportto become a physicalcloth-object (reminiscentof Greenberg's notorious "tacked up canvas [which]already exists as a picture"),thisstrategyin Buren's arsenal founditslogical counterpartin the canvas leaning as an object against support wall and placement of the stretched floor. This shifingof supportsurfacesand proceduresof productionled to a wide range of formsof distributionwithinBuren's work: fromunstretchedcanvas to anonymouslymailed sheets of printed striped paper; from pages in books to billboards. In the same way, his displacementof the traditionalsites of artistic interventionand of reading resulted in a multiplicity of locations and formsof displaythatcontinuouslyplayed on the dialecticof interiorand exterior,thereby oscillatingwithinthe contradictionsof sculptureand paintingand foregrounding all those hidden and manifestframingdevices that structureboth traditions withinthe discourse of the museum and the studio. Furthermore,enacting the principles of the Situationistcritique of the bourgeois divisionof creativityaccording to the rules of the divisionof labor, Buren, Olivier Mosset,Michel Parmentier,and Niele Toroni publiclyperformed (on various occasions between 1966 and 1968) a demolitionof the traditional separationbetween artistsand audience, witheach given theirrespectiveroles. Not only did they claim that each of their artisticidioms be considered as absolutely equivalent and interchangeable,but also that anonymous audience productionof these pictorialsignswould be equivalentto those produced by the artiststhemselves. With its stark reproductionsof mug shots of the four artiststaken in photomats,the poster for their fourthmanifestationat the 1967 Biennale de Paris inadvertently pointsto anothermajor source of contemporarychallengesto the notion of artisticauthorshiplinked witha provocationto the "audience" to participate:the aestheticof anonymityas practicedin Andy Warhol's "Factory" and its mechanical(photographic)procedures of production." The criticalinterventionsof the four into an established but outmoded culturalapparatus (representedby such venerable and importantinstitutionsas the Salon de la Jeune Peintureor the Biennale de Paris) immediatelybroughtout in the open at least one major paradox of all conceptual practices(a paradox, 30. Michel Claura, at the time the critic activelypromotingawareness of the affiliatedartists Buren, Mosset,Parmentier,and Toroni, has confirmedin a recentconversationthatthe referenceto Warhol, in particularto his series The ThirteenMost WantedMen, which had been exhibitedat the Ileana Sonnabend Gallery in 1967, was quite a conscious decision. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 140 OCTOBER incidentally,which had made up the single most original contributionof Yves Klein's workten yearsbefore). This was thatthe criticalannihilationof cultural conventionsitselfimmediatelyacquires the conditionsof the spectacle,that the insistenceon artisticanonymityand the demolitionof authorshipproduces instantbrand names and identifiableproducts,and that the campaign to critique conventionsof visualitywith textual interventions,billboard signs,anonymous handouts,and pamphletsinevitablyends by followingthe preestablishedmechanismsof advertisingand marketingcampaigns. All of the works mentionedcoincide, however,in theirrigorousredefinitionof relationshipsbetweenaudience, object,and author. And all are concerted in the attemptto replace a traditional,hierarchicalmodel of privilegedexperience based on authorialskillsand acquired competenceof receptionby a structural relationshipof absolute equivalents that would dismantle both sides of the equation: the hieraticpositionof the unifiedartisticobjectjust as muchas the privilegedpositionof the author. In an earlyessay(published,incidentally,in the same 1967 issue of AspenMagazine- dedicated by itseditorBrian O'Doherty to St6phane Mallarm --in whichthe firstEnglishtranslationof Roland Barthes's "The Death of the Author" appeared), Sol LeWitt laid out these concernsfora programmaticredistributionof author/artistfunctionswithastonishingclarity, presentingthemby means of the rathersurprisingmetaphorof a performanceof daily bureaucratictasks: The aim of the artistwould be to give viewersinformation.. . . He would follow his predeterminedpremise to its conclusion avoiding subjectivity.Chance, tasteor unconsciouslyrememberedformswould play no part in the outcome. The serial artistdoes not attemptto as a clerk produce a beautifulor mysteriousobject but functionsmerely results his the of premise(italicsadded).31 cataloguing Inevitablythe questionariseshow such restrictivedefinitionsof the artistas a cataloguingclerkcan be reconciledwiththe subversiveand radical implications of Conceptual Art. And this question must simultaneouslybe posed withinthe specifichistoricalcontext in which the legacy of an historicalavant-garde-and Productivism-had only recentlybeen reclaimed. How, we Constructivism can these practices be aligned with that historicalproduction that mightask, artistslike Henry Flynt,Sol LeWitt,and George Maciunas had rediscovered,in the early '60s, primarilythroughthe publication of Camilla Gray's The Great Russian Art 1863-1922.32 This question is of particularimportance Experiment: since manyof the formalstrategiesof earlyConceptual Artappear at firstglance 31. Sol LeWitt,"Serial Project#1, 1966," AspenMagazine,nos. 5-6, ed. Brian O'Doherty, 1967, n. p. The importanceof this publicationin 1962 was mentioned to me by several of the artists 32. interviewedduring the preparationof thisessay. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 141 to be as close to the practicesand proceduresof the Constructivist/Productivist avant-gardeas Minimal sculpturehad appeared to be dependent upon its materials and morphologies. The profoundlyutopian (and now unimaginablynaive) natureof the claims associated withConceptual Art at the end of the 1960s were articulatedby Lucy Lippard (along with Seth Siegelaub, certainlythe crucial exhibitionorganizer and criticof that movement)in late 1969: Art intended as pure experience doesn't exist untilsomeone experiences it, defyingownership,reproduction,sameness. Intangible art could break down the artificialimpositionof "culture" and provide a broader audience for a tangible,object art. When automatismfrees millionsof hours for leisure,art should gain ratherthan diminishin importance,for while art is not just play, it is the counterpointto work. The time may come when art is everyone's daily occupation, though there is no reason to thinkthisactivitywill be called art.33 While it seems obvious that artists cannot be held responsible for the culturallyand politicallynaive visionsprojected on theirworkeven by theirmost competent,loyal,and enthusiasticcritics,it now seems equally obvious thatit was preciselythe utopianismof earlieravant-gardemovements(the typethatLippard desperatelyattemptsto resuscitatefor the occasion) that was manifestlyabsent from Conceptual Art throughout its history(despite Robert Barry's onetime invocation of Herbert Marcuse, declaring the commercial gallery as "Some places to whichwe can come, and fora while 'be freeto thinkabout whatwe are going to do'"). It seemsobvious,at least fromthe vantageof the early 1990s, that fromits inceptionConceptual Art was distinguishedby itsacute sense of discursive and institutionallimitations,itsself-imposedrestrictions, itslack of totalizing vision, its criticaldevotion to the factual conditionsof artisticproduction and reception withoutaspiring to overcome the mere facticityof these conditions. This became evident as works such as Hans Haacke's series of Visitors'Profiles (1969- 70), in itsbureaucraticrigorand deadpan devotionto the statisticcollection of factual information,came to refuse any transcendental dimension whatsoever. Furthermore,it now seems thatit was preciselya profounddisenchantment withthose political master-narratives thatempowered most of '20s avant-garde art that,acting in a peculiar fusionwiththe mostadvanced and radical formsof critical artisticreflection,accounts for the peculiar contradictionsoperating within(proto) Conceptual Art of the mid- to late-1960s. It would explain why thisgenerationof the early '60s-in itsgrowingemphasison empiricismand its scepticismwithregard to all utopianvision- would be attracted,forexample, to 33. Lucy Lippard, "Introduction,"in 955.000 (Vancouver: The Vancouver Art Gallery,January 13- February8, 1970), n. p. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions OCTOBER 142 ...... % ~FRoom-, . .... Toroni.Installationat Buren,Mosset,Parmentier, Museum MarcelBroodthaers's (Plaque).1971. and would confoundthe affirmative the logical positivismof Wittgenstein petitof Alain Robbe-Grillet withthe radical atopismof Samuel bourgeois positivism Beckett,claimingall of themas theirsources. And it would make clear how this generationcould be equallyattractedbythe conservativeconceptof Daniel Bell's "end of ideology" and Herbert Marcuse's Freudo-Marxist philosophy of liberation. What ConceptualArtachievedat leasttemporarily, however,was to subject the last residues of artisticaspirationtoward transcendence(by means of traditional studio skills and privileged modes of experience) to the rigorous and relentlessorder of the vernacularof administration. Furthermore,it managed to the artistic of towards an affirmative collaboration production aspiration purge withthe forcesof industrialproductionand consumption(the last of the totalizing experiences into which artisticproductionhad mimeticallyinscribeditself withcredibilityin the contextof Pop Art and Minimalismfor one last time). Paradoxically,then,it would appear thatConceptual Art trulybecame the most significant paradigmaticchange of postwarartisticproductionat the very This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ConceptualArt 1962-1969 143 moment that it mimed the operating logic of late capitalismand its positivist in an effortto place itsauto-criticalinvestigations at the serviceof instrumentality of aesthetic even the last remnants traditional experience. In that liquidating in of itself succeeded it purging entirely imaginaryand bodily experiprocess and the of substance ence, physical space of memory,to the same extentthat it effacedall residues of representationand style,of individualityand skill. That was the momentwhen Buren's and Haacke's work fromthe late 1960s onward turnedthe violence of that mimeticrelationshipback onto the ideological apparatus itself,using it to analyze and expose the social institutionsfromwhichthe and the logic of administrationemanate in the laws of positivistinstrumentality firstplace. These institutions,which determinethe conditionsof culturalconsumption,are the veryones in which artisticproduction is transformedinto a tool of ideological controland cultural legitimation. It was leftto Marcel Broodthaersto constructobjects in whichthe radical achievementsof Conceptual Art would be turnedinto immediatetravestyand in which the seriousnesswith which Conceptual Artistshad adopted the rigorous mimeticsubjectionof aestheticexperience to the principlesof whatAdorno had called the "totallyadministeredworld" were transformedinto absolute farce. And it was one of the effectsof Broodthaers'sdialecticsthatthe achievementof Conceptual Art was revealed as being intricatelytied to a profoundand irreversible loss: a loss not caused by artisticpractice,of course, but one to which that practiceresponded in the fulloptimismof itsaspirations,failingto recognizethat the purging of image and skill,of memoryand vision, withinvisual aesthetic representationwas not just another heroic step in the inevitable progress of Enlightenmentto liberate the world from mythicalformsof perception and hierarchicalmodes of specialized experience, but that it was also yet another, perhaps the last of the erosions (and perhaps the most effectiveand devastating one) to which the traditionallyseparate sphere of artisticproductionhad been subjected in its perpetual effortsto emulate the regnant episteme withinthe paradigmaticframeproper to art itself. of Conceptual Art-its Or worse yet, that the Enlightenment-triumph of audiences and distribution,its abolition of object statusand transformation commodityform--would most of all only be shortlived,almost immediately giving way to the return of the ghostlikereapparitionsof (prematurely?)displaced painterlyand sculptural paradigms of the past. So that the specular regime,whichConceptual Art claimed to have upset, would soon be reinstated withrenewed vigor. Which is of course what happened. This content downloaded on Mon, 14 Jan 2013 05:22:16 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions