The Me (belongs to the past) THE ME IS NOT AN AGENT, NOT A CONSCIOUSNESS, IT DOESN’T DO, FEEL OR THINK ANYTHING Image Role/Performance Idea Ideal Narrative The Internalization of the Generalized Other The I (belongs to the present) Consciousness Freedom Novelty Creativity The Unique, Creative and Novel Response to the Me To have a self or to be a self requires that one take oneself as an object (a ME) in a social context. But who or what is responsible for HOW one TAKES ONESELF as an object? Clearly individuals can mix it up, abandon, or choose between competing mes and to that extent there is considerable room here for an understanding of the me that is not reducible to a sociological phenomenon alone. But we ought not to rule out either the possibility that the I is what Mead himself says it is, namely a potentially novel and creative response to the me or to society in general. Options for the I 1. If the I is a novel reply to the me or author of the me, the me cannot be a sociological phenomenon alone. 2. If the me is a sociological phenomenon alone the I must be a narrator or performer of a story it did not write. 3. If the me is a product of both the I and society the I will be better construed as a co-author of the me that adapts, adjusts and transforms social identities in concert with others. 4. Or perhaps the I is a kind of juggler and manager of social identities and roles, capable of choosing between competing identities, abandoning identities and of choosing new ones Mead on the Self (Key Points and Questions) The Me 1. According to Mead to have a self means to be able to take oneself as an object or more simply put it means to be able to reflect on oneself. As we have seen if consciousness is a directedness (intentionality or transcendence) towards a perceived, imagined or cognitive object, one thing consciousness can perceive, imagine or think about is itself. 2. Now from Mead’s point of view when I reflect on myself the part of the self that is doing the reflecting is the “I” and the part that is reflected upon is the “me”. 3. Thus when I think about myself as a teacher, it is my I that does the reflecting and it is the role that I play or the image or idea that I have of myself as a teacher that is the “me”. But of course we also think about our own thinking all the time, for example whenever we reflect on what we have just said, whenever we wonder about why we have the thoughts we have or whenever someone else asks us to explain why we believe what we believe. Thus the thoughts that I have had (and can think about or reflect upon) also belong to my me. 4. It is important to understand then that the me does not imagine, think, perceive or do anything. The me is not a subject, it is not a consciousness and it certainly is not self-reflective, the me rather is a social role, image or idea that I might have about myself but it is also any aspect of myself that I can objectify like my dreams, my thoughts, my beliefs etc . 5. For instance when little boys and little girls are learning what it means to be a boy or a girl they are learning how to think about themselves in certain ways, how to embody certain ideals, how to “put on” or manufacture a certain image or look etc. The part of the self that does the learning, embodying, manufacturing and reflecting once again is the I, and on the other hand the ideal, idea and image etc. is the me to the extent that an I identifies with that ideal or sees itself as the embodiment of that ideal to some extent. 6. For Mead however I can only take myself as an object if I can see myself through the eyes of someone else, that is I must be able to see myself as I see others or to put this in another way I must be able to take myself as the other of someone else’s gaze. 7. To see oneself as a boy or girl then is to see oneself as the embodiment of an ideal that will be visible to others, in short I must perform myself as a certain version of masculinity or femininity that I know others will recognize. In other words to have a self requires that I must be able to take myself as an object or better socially defined role that can only exist in a socially determined “game.” Mead defines gaming in opposition to playing (see Hunting on Mead R99). 8. Mead defines the me as the “internalization of the generalized other” (and it can be linked as a result to Freud’s notion of the superego). Internalization is when you take the way someone else sees you and you come to see yourself that way too. Thus if a father is always telling his son that he thinks he is smart, the son will come to see himself that way, he will take the father’s view (which is external) and make it internal by adopting the same view. If the me is the “internalization of the generalized other” then all that means is that the me is a general role or ideal – that initially belongs to others - that the individual takes as its own. Thus for example a young teacher may try to be like the teachers he always liked. (Importantly as we will see shortly the internalization belongs to the I). 9. Mead’s baseball analogy is a simple yet far-reaching illustration of what the me is all about. Basically to learn how to play baseball means to learn certain roles, rules and goals. To learn the role of first baseman for example is to learn what the objectives of the team on the field are and how those objectives are to be reached. More specifically however it is to learn what I can reasonably expect from others and what they can reasonably expect from me given what the roles, rules and objectives of the game are. Mead’s important claim however is that ALL social relations and ALL socially defined roles (mother/daughter, husband/wife, student/teacher, friend/friend, employer/employee etc.) function exactly like baseball. Thus to learn one’s role as a teacher is to know what you can reasonably expect from your students, and to learn one’s role as a student is to learn what you can reasonably expect from your teachers. But knowing what you can and cannot expect from your friends works the same way. And to the extent that the self is in part a me it is clear that the self is in large measure a product of the social games one must join in order to have a sense of who you are. 10) Knowing who you are then, that is, knowing what one’s role is, is all about knowing who you are NOT. But this exclusion extends to all social relations. For example to know one is a boy implies that you know what a girl is and that you are NOT that. To know you are the teacher is to know what it means to be a student and in what sense your rights and responsibilities are not the same. Part Two - The I 1. It is not surprising that Mead defines the self in largely social terms, that is, as the embodiment of social norms, values and more specifically roles. He is after all a sociologist. (Thus in the same way Plato thought the natural world is the embodiment of immaterial forms or ideals, Mead thought that part of the self, namely the me, is the embodiment of social forms or ideals). 2. On the other hand Mead recognizes that there is another part of the self that is not just about the embodiment of and identification with a socially defined ideal or role in a socially defined game, that part of the self is what makes us individuals and not just “generalized roles”; that part is the I. 3. The “I” is essentially the existential version of consciousness with which we are already familiar. Mead even goes so far as to say that the I is a “pure consciousness” and a “creative response” to the me. 4. He also says that the I is always in the present while the me is always in the past. What this means is that consciousness is always in the present but the social roles that we perform and embody belong to existing and often time worn ideals that belong to the past. Even a decision like deciding to become a student at Dawson illustrates this point. Thus it is the I that decides - in a present moment - to confirm the school’s acceptance, but as soon as the confirmation letter has been sent and the school fees have been paid the individual’s me has changed, because now the individual can identify themselves as a “Dawson Student.” But this identification (which owes to a past decision) can easily change of course as soon as the individual decides to stop their studies or to switch to another school. 5. Thus if according to Mead to have a self or to be a self requires that one take oneself as an object and one can only take oneself as an object in a social context, from the point of view of the I it is crucial that we underline that it is only the I that can perform this task of taking the views of others, taking the views of others perhaps only to reject them, to adapt or revise them. 6. This however has major implications for Mead’s theory for if the I can actually change the me, choose between competing mes (for example, choose between being a student at Dawson or Vanier), abandon past mes or perhaps even invent their own mes (for example, their own personalized way of being a teacher), then the me is not a product of society alone and the I might be rightly characterized as the existentialists argued as the author of the self. 7. At times Mead seems to want to have it both ways, that is, he wants to say that the me is a social phenomenon alone – the internalization of the generalized other – and also hold that the I is the seat of a unique voice, creative response and pure consciousness. But this is not possible. Either the I can be the author of the me or not, and if not the I will be better described as a narrator of social narratives and ideals it did not itself author. On the other hand if the I can determine the nature of the me, the me is not a social phenomenon alone. Or perhaps we can think of the I as a coauthor of the me or perhaps even as a juggler of multiple mes? Juggling Gender quotes “Jennifer’s appearance directly confronted my rigid notions of gender, her use of performance and the vehicle of the circus allowed me to look, to stare and to notice difference. I had started off by questioning the meaning of feminism but my quest was expanding, I now found myself asking what is a woman and what are the connections between appearance, gender identity and feminism.” Tami Gold My definition of gender is created not only by how I am and who I am but by my interaction with society so I would be glad to think of myself as a woman with a beard even though the category of woman – I’m speaking not of what we rigidly think of as a woman but something sort of expanded and more inclusive – but I have this experience in which I’m treated as a man often so after years of that I feel like that affects my character so in the cultural sense that my interaction with society affects my gender I feel something that is a little different than just a woman. Nachbar 1. A stereotype is an overly simplified conception of a type of thing, place or person that insists all members of that type must share certain properties. (ex all American cars are cheap, all cities are dirty, all hipsters have beards). 2. Thus a type is a category or kind of thing, whereas a stereotype makes false or unnecessarily narrowing claims regarding what properties a type of thing must have. 3. Stereotypes are especially dangerous when they are based on false, negative or damaging portrayals of a people. 4. Stereotypes are also dangerous when they are internalized, i.e. when people presume that they themselves must embody them. 5. Seven characteristics of a stereotype are that they are: erroneous simple shared by a group learned second hand can be internalized are difficult to change are direct expressions of belief Key Terms in Nachbar A Type is a kind of thing, person or place (ex. the general category of “American car.”) A type is a general category that admits variation. Thus there are many kinds of American cars. And thus there could be many ways of being an “adolescent”, “senior citizen”, “man”, “woman”, “Irishman”, “punk”, “hipster”, “American,” “Canadian”etc. It is simply untrue therefore that all adolescents are lazy, that all senior citizens are absent minded and close minded, that all men are egoists, that all woman are concerned about their appearance, that all Irishmen drink a lot of beer, that all punks wear dog collars, that all hipsters have beards, that all Americans are loud and belligerent or that all Canadians are nice). Stereotypes presume therefore that a kind of thing must have certain properties (ex. the presumption that ALL American cars are of poor quality.) Thus stereotypes don’t admit variation. Moreover stereotypes are also frequently based on outrageously false and demeaning claims, ex. that blacks or indigenous people are inferior to whites. The danger of the Internalization of Stereotypes according to Nachbar is the presumption that one must exhibit certain properties if one is to belong to a certain category (ex. to be a “man” one must be strong, to be a “woman” one must concern oneself with one’s appearance, to be an “Asian student” one must be good at math” and thus that if you are a man and not strong there is something wrong with you, that you are not a “real man”. Nachbar quotes A second danger of stereotyping is not quite as obvious as these actions because it is often the result of popular stereotypes which are neutral or even somewhat positive in nature. Yet this danger is responsible for a great deal of frustration and unhappiness. Essentially this second danger results from the fact that stereotypes are not merely descriptions of the way a culture views a specific group of people, but are also often prescriptions as well – thumbnail sketches of how a group of people is perceived and how members of that group perceives themselves. Stereotyping is, as we have seen, a natural ordering function of the human and social mind; stereotypes make reality easier to deal with because they simplify the complexity that makes people unique, and this simplification reflects important beliefs and values as well. These two characteristics combined mean that a society has two powerful motives to encourage people to “live up to their stereotypes”, to encourage them to act like the images a culture already has of them (popular culture is conservative) and to thereby fulfill their proper social roles. (R95-96) In other words stereotypes encourage people to internalize a cultural image, as their goal – a task which may be convenient for the culture (and especially for the power structure status quo) but this proves to be both impossible and damaging to the individuals being asked to mold themselves in such a narrow manner. As human beings each of us has a seemingly infinite number of choices about what kind of person we want to be. In fact, most of us choose to be several kinds of persons…we enjoy wearing different personalities for different occasions. If we accept someone else’s stereotyped image of what we ought to be, even if the image is a positive one, we sadly, perhaps even tragically limit the choices that are such a wonderful part of our humanity and confine ourselves to being narrow and standardized. We become less human and more like robots. The dangers of this kind of “internalized stereotype” –[i.e., ideal notions of Barbie Doll female beauty and heroic GI Joe masculinity] - are magnified by the ways in which advertisers exploit the fears engendered in individuals who have embarked on the futile task of attempting to squeeze themselves into one of society’s cookie cutters…Molds can produce only two things: perfect dolls and scarred human beings” (R96). Shusterman 1. All differentiation is based on the exclusion of what a thing is not. 2. By contrast encounters with others can throw light on who I am in unexpected ways. 3. By absorption or assimilation encounters with others (who are not playing the same game) can be transformative for the self when: the individual is open to seeing himself/herself differently, that is from the others point of view, or when the encounter with the other enables the individual to discover previously unrecognized qualities within himself or herself. Study Questions: Mead, Nachbar and Shusterman 1. What is Mead’s theory of the I? 2. What is Mead’s theory of the Me? In what sense exactly did Mead think that the me can only exist in a social context? 3. Explain Med’s “baseball analogy”. 4. In what sense is the me the “internalization of the generalized other’? 5. What is Mead’s distinction between “playing” and “gaming”? 6. Mead’s characterization of the I as an “absolute freedom”, “pure consciousness”, “novelty”, and “creative response” to the me would suggest that the I is an author of its me. But the I is perhaps best understood as a narrator, performer, manager, co-author or perhaps co-manger or coproducer of the me. Explain. 7. Perhaps the I is best understood as a “filter” that not only chooses between competing mes but also “sifts out” and variously recombines existing possibilities for the self. Explain. 8. Explain in what sense exactly the social performance theory of the self implies that one is different people all depending on the social context. 9. What are the seven key characteristics of a stereotype according to Nachbar? 10. Why does the Nachbar think stereotypes are not only erroneous but dangerous and even tragic? 11. Mead’s notion of the me in mind, how is it that Nachbar’s idea that the internalization of a stereotype is tragic might be wrong or at least overstated? 12. Nachbar’s idea that stereotyping is a “natural function of the human mind” is misleading. How so? 13. Shusterman explains that to know who you are is to know who you are not. This is entirely in keeping with Mead’s picture of the me and in particular his baseball analogy. Explain. 14. Shusterman’s argues that the self is open to transformation by way of contrast and absorption. Explain. 15. Shusterman thinks that the self benefits from travel and reading. How so? And how is this conception of the self in keeping with McAdam’s view that the more mature self will see the world through a more complex lens.