THOMAS HEYD Marks on rocks, painted, engraved, or sculpted, can be found worldwide, wherever there are suitable surfaces. In modern times, archaeologists and anthropologists increasingly have begun studying such marks in relation to their material and social contexts, insofar as available. Frequently, such marks, moreover, display values such as representational realism, abstraction of figures, attention to line and paint application, concern with the quality of the surfaces upon which paintings or engravings are placed, composition, and so on, any of which values may elicit aesthetic appreciation.1 Although apparently benign, such attention to marks on rocks from the aesthetic point of view may become subject to criticism, because it may be supposed to entail a (problematic) form of cultural appropriation. In the following, I begin by briefly reviewing the notion of cultural appropriation and the circumstances under which it may be seen as problematic. After this, I take note of claims to the effect that rock art aesthetics entails problematic cultural appropriation and show that, given proper care, the alleged problems can be avoided. I conclude by arguing that a strong case can be made for the aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks. I. APPROPRIATION AND CULTURAL APPROPRIATION i. Appropriation. As of late, appropriation as such has been treated as problematic on the basis that it is equated with an illegitimate borrowing or taking of a valued item. Nonetheless, until recently, appropriation had been considered in a positive light, and even as a telltale mark of humanity. It was understood to be a special capacity to separate out from nature what human beings find useful and to transform it for their own use in ways that other species supposedly cannot even imagine.2 To appropriate something is to make it one’s property, which entails a right to privileged use and to restrict access to it. Generally, this right is claimed on the basis of transfer in the course of legitimate purchase, gift, profit or earnings, traditional ownership, and, ultimately, through original acquisition from “the storehouse of nature.”3 When appropriation is seen as morally problematic, this is because it is perceived as not legitimate, not fair, or, in general, not attentive to the rights and needs of those with prior claims to the items appropriated. Notoriously, the appropriation of indigenous peoples’ lands in the Americas and Australia, on the basis of a false application of the concept of terra nullius, is a case in point. ii. Cultural appropriation and its problems. In the 1990s, the appropriation of culture, that is, cultural appropriation, came into the spotlight in countries such as Canada, the United States, and Australia in the context of the acquisition and transformation by members of mainstream society of ideas, images, and art styles originally generated by indigenous peoples and other minority groups. Criticisms have been raised, for example, with regard to stories adopted (and adapted) from certain Canadian First Nations groups; paintings reflecting imagery found on West Coast Native totem poles; and music, such as the blues, originally created by African Americans.4 Cultural appropriation may be seen as problematic in at least three ways. First, when cultural appropriation is perceived as the illegitimate taking of a cultural good, it constitutes The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61:1 Winter 2003 Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 Rock Art Aesthetics and Cultural Appropriation 38 1. The appropriation of cultural goods by outsiders to the original culture may lead to faulty portrayal of the members of that culture through misrepresentation. As a result of such misrepresentations, peoples from small-scale societies may alternatively enter our imaginations in a caricatured fashion as “savage,” “noble,” “childlike,” and so on. 2. Borrowed ideas, images, and art styles from indigenous and minority groups may end up being used in ways that make difficult any further use of such cultural goods by representatives of the original culture. The swastika sign, for example, cannot ever more be used naïvely, at least internationally, since its adoption by the National Socialist (Nazi) Party of Germany. Such borrowings cumulatively may erode a people’s capacity for selfrepresentation. 3. Insofar as the cultural appropriation is performed by people with different standards than those prevalent in the original culture, the application of those alien standards to their cultural goods may entail a subversion of the original culture’s voice.7 4. In cases in which cultural goods, such as certain images, function as insignia that customarily are subject to authorization for use, and that define the identity of a group, unauthorized use is equivalent to “the assumption of a right,” and in these cases, cultural appropriation may literally be the appropriation of identity.8 iii. Discussion. Criticisms of cultural appropriation such as these have themselves become subject to objections. Where some see cultural appropriation as theft, others see it as a legitimate, common (or even necessary) ingredient in cultural creation (and re-creation). Where cultural appropriation is seen as leading to the deprivation of income legitimately belonging to the groups that originally produced the cultural good, it is also seen as a propitious way of generating interest in the source group, thereby likely increasing its fortunes and standing. Where some see cultural appropriation as leading to inauthenticity, others see valuable cultural development. Where some see threats to the identity of indigenous and minority groups in such appropriations, others see cultural appropriations as ways in which hybrid cultures come about, which themselves may become reappropriated by the original groups as leavening for their own cultural renaissances. In general, where some see harms to indigenous, minority, and even mainstream cultures, others see overall benefits, which, on consequentialist grounds, supposedly justify cultural appropriation.9 Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 a straightforward moral problem. For instance, if cultural appropriation leads to a loss of potential income for the originary group, as may occur when a musical style such as the blues, jazz, and hip hop, or when Native North American images on T-shirts, are marketed by outsiders to the originary groups, it may be perceived as unfair. The unauthorized taking of ideas, images, and art styles from First Nations people and other minority groups has been seen as a continuation of European colonial appropriation of land and other resources, or, alternatively, as a continuation of the subjugation into slavery of African American people. As such, cultural appropriation has been perceived to entail something equivalent to theft.5 Second, cultural appropriation may also be seen as a cognitive problem, which itself may lead to a moral problem. Insofar as cultural goods go through cultural appropriation they may undergo certain changes, which may threaten their perceived authenticity.6 It has been proposed, for example, that the blues played by white people will fail to have certain essential features because white people lack the necessary experiences of suffering that are particular to African American history. The inauthenticity of the appropriated art form may, moreover, lead to a moral problem insofar as individuals both within and outside the originating culture may end up with cultural experiences of lesser value than they might have had. Third, cultural appropriation is also said to bring about a perceived ontological problem by possibly threatening the identity of members of the originary groups of the cultural goods in question. In this way, it may also entail a moral problem, since it may undermine the survival of such groups as distinct cultural collectivities and, ultimately, their standing as capable of self-governance. The threat may be seen to arise in at least four ways. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Heyd Rock Art Aesthetics and Cultural Appropriation II. AESTHETIC APPROPRIATION OF MARKS ON ROCKS i. Aesthetic appreciation. Aesthetic interest in marks on rocks is on the increase among nonindigenous as well as indigenous laypersons and rock art researchers. While scientific interest in rock art entails a focus on theory-dependent interpretation of observational givens, aesthetic appreciation entails a focus on the appearance of those givens. While in order to arrive at satisfactory explanations, scientific research tends to abstract from the way things seem to us, aesthetic appreciation makes the way things appear to us its subject matter. As we will see, that is not to say, however, that factual knowledge and science have nothing to contribute to aesthetic appreciation; on the contrary. When aesthetically appreciating something, it seems obvious that we would pay close attention to the immediate “sensory givens.” This is relevant with regard to aesthetic appreciation of the natural environment and of works in the visual arts, for example, but not with regard to works in literature, which may equally be rendered via diverse media (such as through sound recordings, tactile script, oral performance, handwritten, and so on) and, if printed, via diverse fonts, formats, or kinds of paper, and so forth. Aesthetic appreciation in the case of literature requires imaginative participation above all. In fact, the role of the imagination is essential even in the case of the aesthetic appreciation of the visual arts. For instance, aesthetic appreciation of a landscape painting relies on our imaginative attention to the way actual landscapes have appeared to us in the past to perceive the particular ways in which the artist challenges, complements, or twists our set ways of seeing. Aesthetic appreciation also calls for factual knowledge, since, to be fully appreciated, things need to be understood within their context. Notably, a painting with paint drips all over has a different aesthetic value if created in the Quattrocento than if made in the twentieth century (for example, by Jackson Pollock); the former likely is the result of an accident, whereas the latter finds a particular significance in the history of painting styles. So, insofar as it calls for sensory acquaintance with, imaginative participation in, and knowledgeable consideration of things, aesthetic appreciation requires information (possibly including information supplied by science).11 Nonetheless, even while aesthetic appreciation may be guided by factual information, it is evident that appreciation is deeply culturebound. Since it has to do with the way things appear to each of us as persons grounded in particular cultural milieux, aesthetic appreciation will be conditioned by the modes of perceiving, imagining, and thinking that individuals have acquired over time and in their particular cultural contexts. This fact has important consequences for the appreciation of manifestations across cultures, especially when those cultures Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 We cannot hope to fully address these issues here, but may observe that the discussion crucially revolves around the question whether cultural appropriation is harmful or beneficial, taking note of its effect both globally, with regard to humanity in general, and locally, with regard to the groups from whom cultural goods are being borrowed or taken.10 Although, as just noted, cultural appropriation often may be problematic, there are examples that show that appropriation may be rather benign, innocent, or beneficial. Consider, for example, the appropriation by rap musicians of stale mainstream songs, bringing those songs back to (a new) life; or the appropriation, both by professional and amateur dancers worldwide (even in Japan), of traditional, Gypsy flamenco dance styles; or the appropriation (and redeployment) by visual artists, such as de Chirico or Mimmo Paladino, of classical imagery long relegated to the museums. The self-conscious copying of historically “great art” in the 1980s, by artists such as Sherrie Levine, Elaine Sturtevant, and Mike Bidlo, labeled “appropriation art,” is an extreme example of appropriation for the sake of a revitalization of art. Given that at least some cultural appropriations may indeed be innocent, and possibly even useful, either globally or to the indigenous or minority groups affected through the stimulus that they may provide to cultural development, we may (roughly) distinguish between “problematic” and “unproblematic” appropriation. So, is the aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks, commonly called rock art, a form of cultural appropriation, and is it to be considered problematic? 39 40 ii. Aesthetic appropriation and its problems. Most marks on rocks that are considered “rock art” were made by people with very different ways of perceiving, imagining, and thinking from those of people rooted in mainstream historic European cultures.14 In this paper, I shall not attempt to determine whether these marks on rock justifiably may be called “art.”15 It is certain, in any case, that, insofar as contemporary people of European cultural descent see marks on rocks as related to what they consider art, they bring into play deeply entrenched ways of perceiving what most likely would be alien to both prehistoric and non-European makers of marks on rocks.16 For example, as Pippa Skotnes has pointed out, few rock art researchers of European cultural background have taken note of the possible variance in orientation from standard Renaissance expectations of South African Bushman (San) rock art images. On her view, “In many cases paintings made on ceilings of caves, high out of normal reach, or on walls of caves so shallow that the only possible viewing position is on one’s back” are such that, “re-orienting the paintings in reproduction according to Western (preModern) notions of the Vasarian frame may be robbing the originals of an important component of meaning.” She makes exemplary reference to a panel from Sevilla in the Western Cape region of South Africa that, on her account, has features that bring about “a circular composition contrasting strongly with the kind of orientation all reproductions of it suggest.”17 More broadly, it has been argued that philosophical aesthetics, along with the corresponding practice of appreciation, is an eighteenth-century European invention and, hence, idiosyncratic to our own culture.18 Larry Shiner, furthermore, has suggested that, since the notion of “art” is rooted in the cultures of modern European peoples, calling something from outside those cultures “art” constitutes a ploy enabling our artworld to control the cultural margins.19 Consequently, focusing on marks on rocks originating in prehistoric and non-European cultures from the aesthetic point of view may be perceived as a taking or borrowing of images, a kind of appropriation of culture. But, is it a problematic form of cultural appropriation? First, is it an illegitimate taking of a cultural good, thereby constituting a straightforward moral Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 are remote from each other in structure, geography, or time, since in those cases it is likely that ways of aesthetically appreciating will be quite different. Notably, while large-scale societies, such as have been constituted by Chinese, Indian, and European peoples, have developed distinct and explicit categories for things produced by recognized artists primarily for the sake of aesthetic pleasure, and a vocabulary for the critique and appraisal of such items as art, small-scale societies may have more integrated ways of categorizing, producing, critiquing, and appraising aesthetically interesting objects. Regarding the question “whether a people possess the concept of art,” Stephen Davies comments, “What matters is not that they separate art from other important concerns but that they make items presenting humanly generated aesthetic properties, which are essential to the main purposes served by those items.”12 For example, among the Yolngu of Northern Australia, particularly skilled individuals make designs with a brilliant shimmer (bir’yun). For the Yolngu, the brilliance of their paintings is a manifestation of ancestral power, and painters are distinguished by their skill in achieving this effect. Bir’yun may be called an aesthetic property, since it is assessed by the appearance of the paintings according to certain conventional standards, but to the Yolngu the property of bir’yun is relevant only by way of its effectiveness in eliciting ancestral power.13 To properly appreciate the aesthetic properties exhibited in manifestations by people of another culture, it may be necessary to acquire an understanding of the specifities of how the appreciation of aesthetic properties is integrated into their mentality and their practices. The consequence is that proper aesthetic appreciation of items offered for aesthetic appreciation across cultures constitutes a considerable challenge, not to be underestimated on the basis of the ease with which we may “recognize” certain familiar motifs, styles, or techniques. (Some prehistoric rock art may appear like twentieth-century abstract art; some African art may remind us of Picasso’s cubism; but such similarities surely can only set the stage for a questioning of the validity of our conventional categories for the assessment of the aesthetic import of those works.) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Heyd Rock Art Aesthetics and Cultural Appropriation of the item according to certain practice-internal standards. As noted already, the size of a society may make a difference with regard to the degree of specialization versus the degree of integration of aesthetics, both its productive and its receptive aspects, but not with respect to the very existence of art or aesthetic interest. We also have documented evidence among many nonEuropean peoples from both small- and largescale societies for the use of terms clearly expressive of aesthetic choices. These facts seem best explained by supposing that people from around the globe share a sense of aesthetic appreciation, even if it is expressed differently in different societies.23 Clearly, the aesthetic point of view per se is not an idiosyncratic European invention. It seems, rather, that the mode of aesthetic appreciation developed by European peoples simply represents one particular mode of aesthetic appreciation among many.24 Second, does taking the aesthetic point of view with regard to rock art pose a cognitive problem by threatening the authenticity of those cultural manifestations? To some people, the aesthetic point of view seems to imply that we focus on things in abstraction from the immediate functions that those things may have, or have had, in their original circumstances.25 So, while to the aesthetic appreciator a certain rock art panel may be of interest because its harmonious composition or delicacy of execution gives it standing as art, the image may have had a significantly different function in the lives of its original makers. It may have served religious or political aims by, respectively, indicating the presence of the spirit beings or by marking some important communal event. So, it may be argued that the effect of taking the aesthetic point of view is a distortion of the original meaning of such marks on rocks. We may observe, however, that, contrary to what we may suppose, aesthetic appreciation generally will be hampered if it does not take note of the function that the things appreciated have in their original contexts.26 This is evident in the aesthetic appreciation of artworks in the European tradition as well. For example, the convention of giving extraordinary size to certain figures, such as the image of the Virgin Mary, in pre-Renaissance European paintings Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 problem? Aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks certainly is not a literal taking of a good. It is, rather, more like the investment in a point of view, which may have repercussions because of the attitudes and actions that it may seem to legitimize. For instance, some rock art enthusiasts may treat it as their right, and perhaps even as their duty, to view rock art sites, even if thereby conflicting with the limitations set by the original makers or present traditional owners of such sites.20 Moreover, as sites with marks on rocks are progressively being opened up to the public for its appreciation, cultural appropriation through tourism may bring about problematic effects because of the widespread commercialization of rock art images. In the process, whole industries specializing in T-shirts, jewelry, and other assorted products displaying images borrowed from rock art sites have sprung up.21 As of late, such derivative activities have become the focus of critique by indigenous peoples who decry the exploitation of their cultural heritage by outsiders, all the while without being recipients of compensation for this use of their cultural resources.22 The perception of panels of marks on rocks as valuable art objects sadly may, moreover, lead to the literal removal of rock art panels from their original locations. Aesthetic appreciation itself, however, cannot fairly be blamed for cultural appropriation through uninvited visitation of restricted sites; tourism and the ensuing commercialization of rock art images; or the removal of rock art panels. These are, rather, problems that call for attention to proper cross-cultural etiquette and reflection on the larger implications of one’s perhaps innocent-seeming actions. Furthermore, even if the European cultural perspective on aesthetics is idiosyncratic, this does not mean that to engage in aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks necessarily is the imposition of an alien point of view. As has been shown by various authors, people around the globe may lavish great care on the appearance of both special and common utilitarian objects in their environment. When asked about the point of their care, they direct us to the importance of appearance for the effectiveness of the item, to the pleasure that the appearance may generate, or the rightness of the appearance 41 42 those who were initially expected to view the images. This is evident with regard to the arts in the European tradition as well. Sophisticated aesthetic appreciators of Renaissance paintings, for example, will seek to become aware of the specific training and intentions of their makers, attempt to use the images only in such a way that they are recognized for the value they have, seek to determine the standards that their makers expected as appropriate for their evaluation, and, in general, try to accord the works and their makers the respect they deserve on the basis of the value present in the art. Insofar as aesthetic appreciation of rock art or other artworks from remote times and places requires intercultural knowledge and sensibility it should contribute to, rather than hinder, the development of intercultural perceptiveness and goodwill. iii. Discussion. Aesthetic appreciation of images on rock does not necessarily entail a problematic form of cultural appropriation. It is, of course, very difficult to become fully aware of the imprint of one’s own culture on one’s mode of aesthetic appreciation. Moreover, it may be difficult to adequately supplement that cultural outlook, especially in the case of rock art manifestations, since very little information may be available about the original makers’ standards for aesthetic appreciation or the functions of their works. For instance, the long-time association in European peoples’ thinking of prehistoric and non-European people with warlike behaviors can have confusing effects in the appreciation of rock art panels that display what appear to be representations of battle scenes. Only by studying contemporary Aboriginal societies were researchers able to show that, in most cases, certain Northern Australian panels, which at first seem to be battle scenes, actually are representations of dancers in full ceremonial attire holding their weapons upraised. This fact, however, has an important impact on aesthetic appreciation of the marks, since it changes their meaning and, just as in the appreciation of artworks in the European traditions, the meaning intended is as relevant as the formal aspects exhibited. Moreover, if it were suggested that we limit ourselves to the scientific analysis (in narrow Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 makes better aesthetic sense if seen as intended to highlight the relative religious importance of the various figures represented than if we were to suppose that this phenomenon were the result of arbitrary choice. Similarly, one can come to a better aesthetic appreciation of the expressive power of certain Australian rock art panels, and of the custom of periodically repainting them (“freshening them up”), if one is cognizant of the fact that, according to Aboriginal people, these panels show Ancestral Beings who “painted themselves on the rock,” than if one ignored it.27 Third, does the aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks suppose an ontological problem by threatening the identity of the members of the artists’ originary group? As noted, the appropriation of cultural goods by outsiders may threaten the identity of a people if there is serious misrepresentation; if their images, motifs, and art styles become associated with problematic ideologies; if their representations are judged by extraneous standards, alien to those according to which they were fashioned, thereby subverting their voice; and, in cases in which cultural goods, such as images, function as insignia definitory of the makers’ group, cultural appropriation may be equivalent to the literal theft of the group’s identity. The threat to a group’s identity becomes a moral issue, on the assumption that members of groups only function as such if they can find ways of substantiating their identity through cultural markers. The possibilities of misrepresentation, misuse, misjudgment, and unauthorized use of rock art images are real enough. For instance, problems may arise through the development of the tourism industry, which quickly turns into logos images that were never meant for mechanical reproduction. Such problems, however, are not a direct function of aesthetic appreciation. They arise if aesthetic appreciation is accompanied by lack of intercultural knowledge and lack of willingness to follow standards of intercultural etiquette and respect. There is no reason, though, to suppose that such threats to the identity of the makers of rock art are inevitable. Satisfactory aesthetic appreciation itself, as already noted, is highly dependent on attentiveness to the cultural context of images, the intentions of their makers, the standards of aesthetic judgment within the community of origin, and their significance for The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Heyd Rock Art Aesthetics and Cultural Appropriation III. THE CASE FOR ROCK ART AESTHETICS AND CONCLUSION i. Cross-cultural aesthetics. A number of grounds offered in the literature for engaging in crosscultural aesthetics apply equally well in the case of rock art aesthetics. Notably, it has been proposed that attending to the products of peoples from other cultures from the aesthetic point of view will enrich our understanding of those peoples, while honoring their achievements.29 Such appreciation may also more generally enrich our own capacity to aesthetically appreciate, as has been well illustrated by the path-breaking new aesthetic and artistic perspectives acquired by Pablo Picasso, Paul Gauguin, and others, which, at least partially, were due to such crosscultural appropriations.30 It has also been proposed that cross-cultural aesthetic appreciation may contribute to a critique of our own narrow conceptions of art and aesthetics, and of the mostly exclusionary practice of art galleries, focused on European models of art.31 In addition to these reasons for engaging in aesthetic appreciation we may take note of some that have to do with the unique character of marks on rocks among the diversity of existing cultural manifestations. ii. The uniqueness of rock art. Rock art is integrated into the natural world in a way that few other humanly made objects are. Rock art panels usually are located in remote locations, relatively unimpacted by contemporary industrial, urbanizing, or “recreational” activities. In contrast to most other art, rock art sites are not dependent on extraction of materials from nature for the creation of new artefacts somewhere else.32 Instead, pictographs and petroglyphs are made on location and generally are intended to remain on site. Marks on rocks, that is, become integrated into the natural site. As such, rock art panels also offer us a special opportunity for learning about their makers’ aesthetic appreciation of nature, insofar as it is reflected in the content of the images, the choice of surfaces, and the choice of locations in the land.33 Marks on rocks are also valuable counterimages to the growing aesthetization of the everyday as found in the societies of industrialized countries. While in contemporary, consumptionoriented societies all aesthetic appreciation is increasingly being trained onto objects intended to tie us ever more into the reproduction of exploitative relationships with other human beings, nature, or even ourselves, the aesthetic appreciation of rock art offers a paradigm of resistance.34 Marks on rocks, exposed to the environment, generally are subject to (humanly uncontrolled) decay, mostly do not fit mainstream aesthetic tastes, often deal with our connection to other parts of the natural (and supernatural) world, are arduous to find and reach, and usually are difficult to make sense of without careful preparation. Nonetheless, such marks on rocks can be a source of great aesthetic pleasure. The aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks, in other words, offers us an alternative model for the enjoyment of human creativity, little tied to the ever more emaciated values of the “entertainment” industries, highly dependent on respect for crosscultural values, and attentive to a notion of cultural productivity governed by natural context and spiritual concerns. iii. Conclusion. At first blush, the aesthetic appreciation by people of European cultural descent of marks on rocks may appear necessarily to lead to a problematic form of cultural appropriation, given that the aesthetic perspectives Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 archaeological or anthropological terms) of marks on rocks, we may note that this is not a sure way to avoid problematic appropriation, since it is unlikely that the rock art makers would have shared our particular scientific outlook and interests. That is, to take a scientific perspective on rock art may be as culturally appropriative as to take the aesthetic perspective. Nonetheless, despite the difficulties in properly appreciating rock art, and despite the possibilities of problematic aesthetic appropriation, there are strong, independent reasons for aesthetically attending to marks on rock. Not to consider marks on rocks from the aesthetic point of view, when they are offered as such, constitutes a kind of neglect.28 As potential appreciators, we may miss out on valuable aesthetic experiences, and, given the high value accorded to the aesthetic point of view in most (or perhaps all) societies, it may indicate an unjustified (ethnocentric) discrimination of the rock art makers’ cultures. 43 44 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism THOMAS HEYD Department of Philosophy University of Victoria Victoria, British Columbia V8W 3P4, Canada INTERNET: heydt@uvic.ca 1. One result of such appreciation is that these marks generally are known under the rubric “rock art,” even when there is some debate regarding the question whether they properly should be called “art.” Here, I will follow convention by making reference to these marks as “rock art,” but see Thomas Heyd, “Rock Art Aesthetics: Trace on Rock, Mark of Spirit, Window on Land,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (1999): 451–458, for an argument that supports it. 2. See Tim Ingold, The Appropriation of Nature: Essays on Human Ecology and Social Relations (University of Iowa Press, 1987). The exclusive attribution of the capacity for appropriation to human beings is not quite correct, though, since we know of diverse other species (certain birds and apes) that also appropriate nature, even with the use of tools. 3. See John Locke, Two Treatises on Government (1689). 4. On cultural appropriation, see Bruce Ziff and Pratima V. Rao, eds., Borrowed Power: Essays on Cultural Appropriation (Rutgers University Press, 1997); Richard Fung, “Working Through Cultural Appropriation,” Fuse 16 (1993): 16–24; James O. Young, “Should White Men Play the Blues?” Journal of Value Inquiry 28 (1994): 415–424; Joel Rudinow, “Race, Ethnicity, Expressive Authenticity: Can White People Play the Blues?” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1994): 127–137. 5. We may add here the physical appropriation of culturally significant items, such as the Parthenon frieze (the so-called Elgin Marbles) or, more recently, the acquisition of masks and pottery from looted sites by collectors and museums. These concerns have been discussed in the context of the repatriation of cultural property. See, for example, J. H. Merryman, “The Retention of Cultural Property,” U.C. Davis Law Review 21 (1988): 477–513; and John Moustakas, “Group Rights in Cultural Property: Justifying Strict Inalienability,” Cornell Law Review 74 (1989): 1179–1227. 6. For a careful, introductory discussion of various forms of authenticity and inauthenticity, see Elizabeth Burns Coleman, “Aboriginal Painting: Identity and Authenticity,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59 (2001): 385–402. For a critique of authenticity as a form of ideology, see Larry Shiner, “‘Primitive Fakes,’ ‘Tourist Art,’ and the Ideology of Authenticity,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1994): 228–230. For a critique of the way in which the concept of authenticity has been applied to constitute the art of small-scale non-European societies as “traditional” or “primitive,” see James Clifford, The Predicament of Culture: Twentieth Century Ethnography, Literature, and Art (Harvard University Press, 1988), esp. pp. 196–200. 7. “Cultural appropriation” is sometimes equated with “voice appropriation,” tout court, but it seems more apropos to specifically reserve the latter expression for those cases in which legitimate forms of self-assertion or -expression are thwarted. 8. This is Coleman’s argument with regard to the unauthorized use of Aboriginal art designs by non-Aboriginal people. (See p. 396 for the quoted words.) 9. For objections such as those listed, especially see Young, “Should White Men Play the Blues?”; Rudinow, “Race, Ethnicity, Expressive Authenticity: Can White People Play the Blues?” and James O. Young, “Against Aesthetic Apartheid,” Rendezvous: Idaho State University Journal of Arts and Letters 30 (1995): 67–77. 10. It is relevant to note here that, with regard to the morality of cultural appropriation, it is not simply a matter of toting up local harms and lining them up with global benefits in a consequentialist manner, since, at least in some cases, there also are issues of cultural property rights and cross-cultural etiquette involved. 11. This is a point argued implicitly by Kendall Walton, “Categories of Art,” Philosophical Review 79 (1979): 334–367; and explicitly, in different contexts, by Paul Ziff, “Reasons in Art Criticism,” Philosophical Turnings, Essays in Conceptual Appreciation (Cornell University Press, 1966); and Allen Carlson, “Appreciating Art and Appreciating Nature,” and passim, in his Aesthetics and Environment (New York: Routledge, 2000). 12. Stephen Davies, “Non-Western Art and Art’s Definition,” in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 199–216. 13. Howard Morphy, “From Dull to Brilliant: The Aesthetics of Spiritual Power among the Yolngu,” in Anthropology, Art and Aesthetics, ed. Jeremy Coote and Anthony Shelton (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 182–208. 14. There are also marks on rocks, some of which are appreciated for their aesthetic values and some of which are considered graffiti, made by European peoples in the historical period. Even though, to my knowledge, such marks are seldom made the subject of serious study, they fall into the category “rock art,” and their study might generate valuable Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 developed among European peoples likely are specific to those people. In other words, it may seem that aesthetic appreciation would bring with it the imposition of an alien perspective, lead to distortion in the understanding of rock art, and cause the subversion of the identity of its makers. I grant that cross-cultural aesthetics, as is required by the appreciation of rock art, constitutes a significant challenge. Nonetheless, given proper care to respect and consider the cultures of origin, aesthetic appreciation of marks on rocks need not be problematic in the senses just noted. Since there also are prima facie strong, independent reasons for engaging in aesthetic appreciation of this cultural phenomenon, I conclude that the aesthetic approach to marks on rocks is both eminently appropriate and generally desirable.35 Heyd Rock Art Aesthetics and Cultural Appropriation the universality versus the particularity of aesthetic values. F. D. McCarthy, “Theoretical Considerations of Australian Aboriginal Art,” Journal of the Proceedings of the Royal Society of New South Wales 91 (1957): 3–22, moreover, comments on the aesthetic values in Australian Aboriginal art. 24. See Davies, who argues for a transcultural aesthetic based on a universal human interest in certain properties of things. See also Denis Dutton, “But They Don’t Have Our Concept of Art,” also in Theories of Art Today, pp. 217–238, who furthermore argues that the differences between the aesthetic manifestations of European and other peoples generally have been exaggerated. Also relevant in this context is Denis Dutton, “Tribal Art and Artifact,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1993): 13–22, where he argues against Arthur Danto, “Artifact and Art,” in the catalogue ART/artifact (New York: Center for African Art, 1988), pp. 19–32, by claiming that, outside of the twentiethcentury artworld of European peoples, items considered “art” do show perceptible differences from those not so considered. 25. See, for example, Overing; also see Silvia Tomásková, “Places of Art: Art and Archaeology in Context,” in Beyond Art: Pleistocene Image and Symbol, ed. Margaret W. Conkey et al. (California Academy of Sciences/University of California Press, 1997), pp. 265–287, who rejects the aesthetic point of view on rock art. 26. On this point, also see Morphy, “Aesthetics.” 27. Christopher Chippindale, The Archaeology of Rock-Art (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), emphasizes the importance of combining “informed” and “formal” methods in rock art interpretation, when possible. Informed methods rely on information gathered ethnographically, whereas formal methods rely on what is given in the representations themselves. 28. I want to emphasize that rock art, insofar as art made by particular people for their own purposes, in principle, is not a free good like the light of the sun. There may be good reasons from the perspective of intellectual and cultural property rights, and for reasons of cross-cultural etiquette, not to visit or photograph or describe certain sites if they are not offered as such by their makers or guardians. 29. Especially see Morphy, “Anthropology of Art.” 30. Diverse authors in the rock art and cultural appropriation literatures comment on the significance of crosscultural aesthetic influences for the enrichment of aesthetic perspectives. See, for example, Skotnes, and also Ronald DeWitt Mills, “Acculturated Art Forms of Three Central American Indigenous Groups and Observations Concerning Research Methodology in the Study of Contemporary Art,” Rendezvous: Idaho State University Journal of Arts and Letters 30 (1995): 35–49. 31. See Morphy, “Aesthetics”; S. Price, Primitive Art in Civilized Places (University of Chicago Press, 1989). 32. Although, as Sven Ouzman (personal communication, 2000), notes, rock paintings often depend on paint materials that may have been mined at locations distant from the painted sites: “In southern Africa, the majority of San rockpaintings are made from exotic ferric oxide that was mined 20km–400km from where the rock-painting occurs.” 33. For further details on the uniqueness of and perspectives offered by rock art, see Heyd, “Rock Art Aesthetics”; also see Thomas Heyd, “Aesthetics and Rock Art: Art, Mobile Peoples, and Aesthetic Appreciation in Australia,” Arqueologia 25 (2000): 9–18; “Rock Art and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 understanding of the phenomenon in question. See Sven Ouzman, “‘Koeka kakie, hents op bokkor of ik schiet!’ Introducing the Rock Art of the South African Anglo-Boer War, 1899–1902,” The Digging Stick 16 (1999): 1–5. Throughout the paper, I use terms such as “the cultures of people of European descent” to make reference to the mainstream cultures commonly called “Western,” which ultimately have their roots in Europe but are now expressed on diverse continents. I choose not to use the term “Western,” since it is geographically ambiguous. (Notably, Europe is West of Jerusalem and Mecca, but so is all of Africa, whereas Australia more properly is east of both Europe and Jerusalem and Mecca.) 15. But see Heyd, “Rock Art Aesthetics,” for discussion. 16. This is not to say that art is the prerogative of contemporary people of European cultural descent; for discussion see, for example, Howard Morphy, “Aesthetics in a CrossCultural Perspective: Some Reflections on Native American Basketry,” Journal of the Anthropological Society of Oxford 23 (1992): 1–15. Also see John Halverson, “Art for Art’s Sake in the Paleolithic,” Current Anthropology 28 (1987): 63–89, for an account of the origins of art that precisely appeals to Paleolithic rock art as its first instance. See also the references to the discussion in the philosophical context, below. 17. Pippa Skotnes, “The Visual as a Site of Meaning: San Parietal Painting and the Experience of Modern Art,” in Contested Images: Diversity in Southern African Rock Art Research, ed. Thomas A. Dowson and David LewisWilliams (Witwatersrand University Press, 1994). 18. See Joanna Overing, “Aesthetics as a Cross-Cultural Category: Against the Motion” in Key Debates in Anthropology, ed. Tim Ingold (New York: Routledge, 1996), pp. 260–266; see also Alfred Gell, “The Technology of Enchantment and the Enchantment of Technology,” Anthropology, Art and Aesthetics, pp. 40–63. 19. Shiner, “‘Primitive Fakes.’” 20. Notably, some sites were meant to be seen only by initiated individuals, or by members of one particular gender, for example. 21. See, for example, Thomas Dowson, “Off the Rocks, Onto T-Shirts, Canvasses, etc.,” and Peter Welsh, “Commodification of Rock Art: An Inalienable Paradox,” both in Rock Art Ethics: A Dialogue, ed. William D. Hyder (Tucson: American Rock Art Research Association, 2000). 22. See, for example, Adrienne Tanner, “B.C. Natives Put Stop to Commercial Use of Ancient Artwork: Trademark Petroglyphs,” The National Post (Canada) February 14, 2000. 23. See, for example, Jeremy Coote, “Aesthetics as a Cross-Cultural Category: For the Motion,” in Key Debates in Anthropology, pp. 266–271; Morphy, “Aesthetics”; Howard Morphy, “Anthropology of Art,” in Companion Encyclopedia of Anthropology, ed. Tim Ingold (New York: Routledge, 1994), 648–685; Morphy, “From Dull to Brilliant”; Anthony Shelton, “Predicates of Aesthetic Judgment: Ontology and Value in Huichol Material Presentations”; and Jeremy Coote, “‘Marvels of Everyday Vision’: The Anthropology of Aesthetics and the Cattle-Keeping Nilotes,” in Anthropology, Art and Aesthetics, respectively, pp. 181–208, 209–244, and 245–273. Evelyn Payne Hatcher, Art as Culture: An Introduction to the Anthropology of Art (Westport, CT: Bergin & Garvey, 1999), pp. 197–207, provides a useful discussion on the issue of 45 46 Debates in Anthropology, pp. 251–254. On general strategies of resistance to commodification in contemporary society, see, for example, Hal Foster, “Readings in Cultural Resistance,” in his Recodings: Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics (Seattle: Bay Press, 1985), pp. 157–179. 35. I am indebted to Sven Ouzman and John Clegg for careful comments on an earlier draft of this paper, as well as to an anonymous referee of the JAAC. Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/61/1/37/5956854 by Universiteit van Amsterdam user on 10 December 2021 Natural Landscapes,” News95 International Rock Art (Pinerolo, It.: Centro Studi e Museo d’Arte Preistorica, 1999); and “Northern Plains Boulder Structures: Art and Foucauldian Heterotopias,” in Foucault and the Environment, ed. Éric Darier (New York: Routledge, 1998), pp. 152–162. 34. Concerning the importance of cross-cultural aesthetics in potentially countering the aesthetization of the everyday, see James F. Weiner, “Introduction,” in Key The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism