This article was downloaded by: [University of Birmingham] On: 15 November 2014, At: 21:23 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Theory Into Practice Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/htip20 The practical uses of curriculum theory Elizabeth Vallance a a Director of academic outreach , Assistant professor in Kansas State University's, Division of Continuing Education Published online: 05 Nov 2009. To cite this article: Elizabeth Vallance (1982) The practical uses of curriculum theory, Theory Into Practice, 21:1, 4-10, DOI: 10.1080/00405848209542973 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00405848209542973 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions Elizabeth Vallance Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 The Practical Uses of Curriculum Theory It is hard not to feel a certain envy for those profes­ sions whose labels are self-explanatory. People seem to have a rough idea of what an architect, a bricklayer, a teacher, a jeweler, a cabaret singer, or a lawyer (for example) does, and can imagine the skills required and the kinds of settings in which these people work. The vividness of these images seems somehow to legitimize the activity; the prac­ tical uses of bricklaying (or indeed of cabaret sing­ ing) are rarely questioned. It is much less clear, to people both within and outside the education professions, just what "cur­ riculum theorists" are or what purpose their prod­ ucts serve. One gets accustomed to polite confusion and requests for explanation, two popular re­ sponses to describing oneself as a curriculum theorist; one gets accustomed also to encountering curriculists with advanced degrees who have never dealt with curriculum theory (since the course was not required) and who seem mystified - if not slightly intimidated - by it. Theory seems to have a less than enthusiastic reputation, especially among practitioners; various forms of the word have been used synonymously with "abstract," "unresolva­ ble," "ideal," or - maybe even worse! "academic." It is almost always divorced from prac­ tice in our discourse about education; the two terms have become standard fixtures on a frequently used dichotomy. Theory would seem to be thoroughly impractical, of questionable direct usefulness ex­ cept perhaps to those erudite people who dabble in it for various inexplicable reasons of their own. Elizabeth Vallance is director of academic outreach and assistant professor in Kansas State University's Division of Continuing Education. This situation is unfortunate, though it is under­ standable and certainly not peculiar to the cur­ riculum discipline. But curriculum, to the extent that it is a discipline, seems to have gotten at least its share of the confusion resulting from education's persistent efforts to declare itself a science. For var­ ious reasons, relating both to the complexity of the curricular enterprise and to the various perspectives from which its practitioners come, curriculum dis­ course tends to slide easily in various directions away from the subject at hand, which is the cur­ riculum itself; Schwab observed this over a decade ago (1969). The flight upward into theory is among the most tantalizing of the options, and is one to which many curriculists regularly succumb. This tendency to move into the realm of the abstract, and to analyze curricular problems from points of view which seek conceptual consistency - be they ideological, political, quantitatively or qualitatively research-based, historical, or other -seems to be a regular pursuit of curriculists not embroiled in day­ to-day working with real curricula. Teachers seem to have little time for it. As a result, most curriculum theorizing published as such in journals is not done by practicing teachers or curriculum supervisors; it is done largely by college professors. We may argue, however, that this split between theory and practice is more illusory than real, that theorizing about the curriculum occurs at many levels -only a few of them revealed in the journals - and that curriculum theory is indeed useful in practical situations. I will argue especially that the process of theorizing, rather than any particular theory, is one of the most valuable activities avail­ able to us in understanding the practical, and that training in the practical is incomplete without train­ ing in the theoretical as well. Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 The Several Faces of Theory in Curriculum Bypassing Aristotle only in an effort to under­ stand more current usage, I refer to the following five definitions of theory, offered by the Random House College Dictionary in its last several editions: 1) a coherent group of general propositions used as principles of explanation for a class of phenomena; 2) a proposed explanation whose status is still con­ jectural; 3) a body of principles, theorems, etc., about a subject; 4) that branch of a science or art that deals with principles and methods; 5) guess or conjecture.1 Some would argue that we already have plenty of the fifth definition; indeed some of the most passionate arguments about schooling are based on "theories" which seem to take the form of conjecture (e.g., the assumption that reading "dirty books" ruins children's morals, an allegation that has never been proven). We can also argue that we have a branch of curriculum study that looks for and worries about principles and methods, thus meeting the criteria implied by the fourth definition. We have some proposed explanations still being tested by research and observation (the second definition). But do we have a coherent group of general proposi­ tions, principles, or theorems which explain the class of phenomena known as the curriculum? I think not. Consider that a theory, according to the definition cited above and our collective experi­ ence in the area of curriculum theory, includes at least the following: an identification of the major varfables or aspects of the class of phenomena in question, a proposition as to which of these aspects are common to all phenomena in this class, a set of principles and rules which describe the relation­ ships among these elements in explanatory and predictive ways, and some assurance that the theory can be applied in a variety of related situations with equal success. A theory seeks an answer, it seeks closure, and it attempts to remain stable in the face of frequent tests against real situations. Because it seeks to explain, a theory contains "if-then" as­ sumptions and rules; the application of a theory to any situation is always a dynamic enterprise describ­ ing predictable changes. Thus, "if a child commits himself to a task which is within his capability, he will have a successful experience with learning and will progress better than if he experiences failure" is a paraphrase of the kind of "if-then" rule inherent in Glasser's (1969) approach to schooling. In the defin­ ition used here, it is a theoretical statement; it de­ scribes predictable change. But despite all the self-described theoretical ac­ tivity of the past decade or two, we have no body of theory which attempts to explain the kinds of varia­ tions we see in the practical phenomena of cur­ riculum - curriculum development, implementa­ tion, teaching, evaluation. There have been a number of lucid studies of the curriculum from his­ torical and other points of view, plenty of prescrip­ tions and shoulds, many intelligent analyses, a number of provocative collections of writing dealing with the full range of curriculum activity, and some excellent essays treating the relationship of theory to practice. The field has been active, and it has been extraordinarily productive. Its ·adherents have wor­ ried a lot about the role of theory. But I don't believe we have really produced one. There are probably several reasons for this. Among the likeliest is that, unlike gravity or genetic structure, the curriculum is never sufficiently regu­ lar in its practical form to be susceptible to explana­ tion by coherent and regularized principles. Some aspects of it are, of course, for much of teaching and learning is regularizable and controllable­ were this not true, schools would not have survived as long as they have. But not all of it is. Evidence increasingly argues that the effectiveness of any curriculum is colored significantly by subtle influ­ ences such as teacher warmth, social class, nutri­ tion, television, and the like, not subject to our con­ trol. Furthermore, we acknowledge that "behind the classroom door" is an environment which is special, unique to that teacher and to those kids, and not completely explainable by principles derived from research. Education is, of course, both a science and an art, which is problematic for theory-builders; it is difficult to develop rules and principles which apply equally to both aspects. Consider, by way of illustra­ tion, an analogy to photography: there are princi­ ples of chemistry and physics which explain what happens to film and photographic paper when ex­ posed to light, chemicals, and time; there is a sci­ ence to photography, its rules are generalizable, and its rules work. They are useful; any photographer is well advised to master them. But there is an art to photography as well, principles of design and intui­ tions about color and composition which are gener­ alizable only to a limited extent; each photographer uses them differently, discovers new ones, uses some and not others. The uniqueness and value of any photographer's vision is ultimately explained by these rather than by generalizable principles. The two are rarely if ever combined into a single theory of photography; indeed, the phrase sounds absurd. Volume XX/, Number 1 5 Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 Our attempts at theory in curriculum or educa­ tion generally tend, however, to be phrased in the technical terms of a science which seeks regularity and certainty. So constrained, we tend to focus on those characteristics which are most susceptible to replicability, seeking lowest common denominators to give our discourse some consistency. The result sometimes is a language relying on terms such as learner, behavior, interaction, outcome, materials, and the like -terms which claim neutrality and can be applied to any situation. But even this attempt at clarity is deceptive, since the real meanings of the terms are nearly infinite: depending on the context, a/earner can be construed either as a "respondent" (in strict S-R theory) or as a "whole child"; the term cur riculum materials can refer to either pro­ grammed learning exercises or the great books of the western world, and so on. To use any of these terms to refer concurrently to very different settings reduces their meaningfulness to nearly zero; any theory which attempts to explain curricular phenomena in such neutral terms risks oversimplifi­ cation. The result is the stilted jargon many of us have come to dread in our experimentally oriented colleagues; it seems utterly remote from the living fabric of classrooms. Perhaps we ask too much of the curriculum field by expecting theory to explain variations in curricu­ lar situations. We know its limitations, of course, in our acceptance of the concepts of the hidden cur­ riculum and the behind-the-classroom-door phenomenon; both of these function as a kind of "black box" which allows us to acknowledge that much goes on which we cannot control, and to ac­ knowledge it while retaining some dignity as profes­ sionals. Confronted with the incompleteness of theory in our field, we have at least two choices, not mutually exclusive: we can seek something besides a "theory" in its generalizable sense, and we can shift our focus from the end product (the theory itself) to the process by which a theory is sought (the process of theorizing). For it may be that the most valuable contributions of curriculum theorists are the lessons learned in the process of attempting to identify the common and generalizable facets of the curriculum. It is my contention that practitioners engage in this process at least as much as theorists do. It is important to note that theorizing results in more than theories. A related outcome of the proc­ ess of theorizing is the generation not of theoriesper se but of models. Models, often cast in graphic terms which attempt to portray situations visually, are quite common to curriculum discourse, and are far 6 Theory Into Practice more numerous than theories. Goodlad and Richter (1966), Duncan and Frymier (1967), the systems­ analysis models of the instructional design ap­ proach, Walker's naturalistic model (1971), McCutcheon's metaphor of patchwork quilts (1978) - all are familiar attempts to characterize what is involved in the curriculum enterprise. They are ar­ guably different from theories, for they lack state­ ments of rules and principles which claim to de­ scribe the relationships between the parts. They more simply portray a situation (or a class of situa­ tions) by identifying its major elements and locating them in relation to one another. A model is, in this view, more static than a theory, for it describes rela­ tive states rather than a change process. It seems to function more to help us to see what the practical reality includes than to try to explain why or what to expect from it. Thus, for example, in Walker's (1971) and McCutcheon's (1978) cases, models are clearly presented, though in quite different levels of detail. The curriculum development process is charac­ terized - as a political process starting from a shared "platform" (Walker) and as a quilt which may be more or less systematically constructed (Mccutcheon). Neither of these two models pur­ ports to predict how the curriculum development process would be changed by the introduction of specific conditions (say, a more experienced teacher) into a given curricular situation (such as a science curriculum for gifted eighth graders). A theory would. These models seek rather to describe, clarify, order our perceptions about, and help us to see more clearly the forces and conditions affecting curriculum decisions. The difference between a model and a theory, in this view, is not unlike the diff�rence between a Miro painting and a Calder mobile.2 The one is static, presenting to the viewer a set of relative positions of its elements, while the other is dynamic, constantly testing the change that is possible between the ele­ ments given certain constraints such as length of wire, balance, weight, and color. Both are delightful. Both enable us to see the world differently. But they operate quite differently on our perceptions. I can think of no particularly better word than theoiizing (save perhaps modeling) to describe the process by which both models and theories are developed, and so will retain it for the sake of consis­ tency. The process of theorizing requires, at a minimum, a being sensitive to emerging patterns in the phenomena in question, a seeking of com­ monalities, a willingness to attempt and test several different constructions of the situation, and most of all, a close attunement to one's own context. The Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 process of theorizing is an effortful one, ultimately practical in the sense that it is rooted in the im­ mediate data available. It seems hardly necessary to mention that these data need not take the form of "research data" nor of anything more esoteric than the characteristics of the problem at hand. Thus, a student of linguistics may tentatively theorize about the process of language acquisition in order to make sense of a number of articles on language develop­ ment, a photographer may theorize about the rela­ tionship of subject to background in a particular composition, and a teacher may wonder why the implementation of a new curriculum package in her classroom is so much more difficult than she had expected. Whether any of these individuals eventu­ ally produces a theory or model is less important than that they become intimately involved in trying to identify and understand the factors affecting their work. The linguistics student may not finish the day in the library with a new theory of language de­ velopment, but she will have had an effortful in­ volvement in working out some parts of what may later become a theory; the photographer may not develop a complete theory of portraiture, but she will have attempted some variations and learned some basic principles about what not to do; the teacher may never publish a treatise describing a model of curriculum implementation, but will have learned something about the constraints her own classroom imposes on a pre-packaged set of cur­ riculum materials. All, however, will have ap­ proached a problem from a "theoretical" perspec­ tive, seeking not only answers to an immediate ques­ tion but more general rules that may apply next time. The effortful involvement in finding common ele­ ments in situations which will surely be repeated (certainly the teacher must face another day) has a value which can properly be described as a "theoret­ ical" one. Theorizing of this kind clearly has a practical, indeed a survival, value. In the examples cited here it is not very abstract, though any of the three situa­ tions could well be carried into more abstract levels; the linguistics graduate student probably stands the best chance of this. For the teacher especially, it is a question of grappling with a significant number of complex classroom and content variables and of seeing some order in them. The pattern perceived may well shift, and indeed it can be rewarding when it does. Just as a photographer may create several quite different compositions from a single subject, a teacher may see several different constructions of a given problem and learn something from consider­ ing them. The sensitivity to these possibilities is cru- cial. The sense of and ability to order one's experi­ ence so as to make sense of it is critical to any art; it is equally critical to understanding the problems posed by curriculum development and use. It is perhaps more critical in education and curricular situations than it is in less varying settings, for if scientifically-construed educational theory cannot explain and predict every nuance to which we must be sensitive, then it is the job of the practitioner to fill in those gaps with individual an'd perhaps incom­ plete "theories" of his or her own. To return now to an earlier point: curriculum theory and its practical uses seem to be mis­ construed by many educators for at least two rea­ sons: 1) it tends to be done at universities, by academics who call it theory3 and who speak mainly to each other, and 2) because the tradition of re­ search in education has borrowed heavily from the natural sciences, its results - both research appli­ cations and theoretical formulations - tend to be freighted with greater expectations than they can always meet. Our purpose, in working in the area of curriculum theory, might better be to recognize the value of theorizing even when it does not result in complete and coherent theories. We may thereby find a different kind of value in formulations which now pass for "curriculum theory" work but whlch may also be read as political or ideological interpre­ tations of schooling (which the reconceptualists so lucidly offer), alternative approaches to understand­ ing the workings of the curriculum (including argu­ ments for qualitative evaluation, aesthetic criticism, "new journalism," or other re-interpretations of the central problems of curriculum research), or rules for curriculum development itself (the Tyler [1950] rationale being preeminent among these). While not all curriculists engaged in these formulations claim that they are "doing theory," discourse among cur­ riculists tends generally to group these analytical and conceptual studies of the curriculum in a cate­ gory loosely configured as theory. Its adherents be­ come theorists by definition; the list of contributors to this issue of TIP illustrates the point. Nor is theorizing solely the domain of academic curriculists. Indeed, it is engaged in by practitioners at all levels, though few would call it theorizing and almost none of them publish words about it. The need to identify commonalities, to unearth underly­ ing assumptions, to propose tentative hypotheses and test them and revise them, to build informal "models" describing situations-all are common to practitioners involved in work which requires problem-solving. We know from classroom observa­ tions and interviews with teachers that they are Volume XX/, Number 1 7 Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 doing these things more or less constantly; it is generally viewed, however, as an aspect of practice. For example, a number of studies, including the Beginning Teacher Evaluation Study at the Far West Laboratory (Morine and Vallance, 1976) and some research being carried out at Michigan State's Insti­ tute for Research on Teaching, are succeeding in identifying teachers' perceptions of their own teach­ ing and especially of the regularities and patterns in it. This work, done largely by people who describe it as "research on teaching," is rarely if ever charac­ terized as curriculum theory. Such studies are gen­ erally considered to be analyses of practice, re­ search on teaching, evaluation studies, and various other things besides curriculum theorizing. They do not explicitly address curriculum theory problems as we typically understand them. It has been to academic curriculists to take these studies and later reassess them in curriculum theory terms, demonstrating their value to our un­ derstanding of how the curriculum-in-use (cur­ riculists' occasional term for "teaching") works or to other problems. A few curriculists identified as curriculum theorists - notably Anyon (1980), Simon (1980), Walker (1980), Mccutcheon (1980) - con­ duct classroom-based research themselves, and use these data as the basis of cogent analyses of various aspects of the curriculum. Yet even the re­ search of curriculum theorists rarely results in ac­ tual theories, by the strict definition. What we have in the writing of curriculum theorists include interpre­ tations of curricular phenomena in certain methodological or ideological lights, and some­ times models or portraits of curriculum develop­ ment or use. All such studies contribute to our un­ derstanding of schooling and to our own ability to "theorize" about it. The Practical Uses of Curriculum Theory The uses of curriculum theory, then, are several, varying with the specific meaning of the word. Most appropriate to our task is "curriculum theory" loosely construed, which involves careful scholarly thought leading to many different formulations, and describes a body of activity whose purpose is gener­ ally to illuminate the workings of the curriculum. Much of what we conveniently call theory might more accurately be described as "thoughtful study," "analysis and synthesis," "carefully de­ veloped interpretation," or other phrases relating to the gradual and rather painstaking development of new knowledge about the curriculum. This loose version of the rubric admits studies of the history of 8 Theory Into Practice curriculum change, socio-political studies of cur­ riculum context, explorations of standard and alter­ native research methodologies, interpretations of classroom research, interpretations of analyses of curriculum materials, and other work which at­ tempts to shed light on the curriculum as a generic concept. It would also admit curriculum models, principles, formulations of how-to-do-it rules, and other attempts to describe these qualities of curriculum-making and curriculum use which are recurring. The practical uses of this version of cur­ riculum theory are for the most part not immediate, for they depend on accumulation, testing, and gradual integration. But they do finally contribute to our collective knowledge, shaping the ways in which we view classrooms, textbooks, specific curriculum reforms, and the like. Some may argue that this aggregate body of analyses and conceptual studies is not curriculum theory; it is more interesting, how­ ever, to consider that it is. The practical uses of curriculum theory when defined as a coherent body of principles would be quite immediate if such theory existed in the disci­ pline. That it doesn't is the major contributor to its bad reputation, for many of us talk as though it did. We certainly seem to wish it did. This most powerful conception of theory accords it an explanatory and predictive power which would allow us to manipu­ late situations. The principles of physics and chemistry allow the photographer to create a spe­ cific desired photograph from a given subject by manipulating time and exposure settings. They are immediately applicable. They are also accepted as true, for if the result is not as expected, it is assumed that the photographer erred in applying the princi­ ples, not that the rules themselves were at fault. A similarly predictive set of rules in curriculum would yield similarly clear interpretations of error. Few if any such rules have been demonstrated in cur­ riculum, however, and they would likely be as tem­ pered by the ineffable qualities of artistry as they are in photography. If theory is conceived of as a search for coherent and stable principles, and if such a theory existed, its practical uses would be welcome; it is reasonable to argue that they would also be limited. If "curriculum theory" is confused with "cur­ riculum models" (or the making thereof), as I believe it frequently is, then its practical uses are at least two. 1) The application of existing models to specific real situations can help the practitioner to more clearly see the patterns operating within his/her classroom or curriculum-development setting. I have watched practicing teachers study the basic / Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 model implied i n Conflicting Conceptions of Cur­ riculum (Eisner and Vallance, 1 974) as in Huebner's (1 966) argu ment for different modes of "valuing" cu rricular activity. In both cases, the frameworks suggested by those "existing" studies illuminated heretofore subtle distinctions within the teachers' own situations and helped them to o rganize their own perceptions more clearly (this by their own ad­ mission). 2) But models are not only to be applied from without; p ractitioners regularly sort through their own p ractical experiences so as to perceive them i n i nformal categories, h i e rarchies, flow charts, or other forms of models. While they rarely call these perceptions "models," the order created in them serves the same function : it simplifies and it makes possible tentative descriptions of the rela­ tionships among the various categories. The gener­ ation of models by practitioners has a fairly im­ mediate use; it identifies variables that may be ma­ nipulable, and it warns of constants that may be immutable. It invites a testi ng of the limits of change and interpretation in one's own practical setti ng. A model suggests (implicitly) what actions may be possi ble; it colors our understanding of what has al ready happened. Fi nally, though, the practical use of curriculum theory is simply that it requires us to un dertake an analysis of real situations. Th e "theorizing" in cur­ ricu l u m theory occurs at every l evel and in every meaning of "theory." In this sense, theorizi ng is not the flight upward i nto the abstract which Schwab noted and decried (1 969), but rather the attempt to su rvey, analyze, synthesize, and test the knowledge avai lable about curriculum p roblems. It requ i res that we look at the data available and make sense of it. The data may be the parts of a new cu rricu lum package, the textbooks mandated by the state or district, students' performance so far, the pol itical cli mate of the school, research data available on a particular kind of problem, competing conceptuali­ zations of what the curriculum includes, and a nearly infinite list of others. The data available to a classroom teacher may be different from the data available to a g raduate student working on a litera­ ture review. The process of theorizing, in the two cases, is simi lar nonetheless. It is this process, and the wi llingness and eagerness to approach it, which seems i ntegral to all cu rriculum work. In this view of the uses of "theory," the disti nc­ tion between theoretical work and p ractical work all but vanishes; the work and effort i nvolved in theoriz­ ing in either setti ng is the same. More, the pu rpose in both is to understand what the curriculum includes and how it operates. U nder this conception of "theory," it is reasonable to argue that all students of education, both g raduate and underg raduate, should syste mat i cally study c u rri c u l u m theory through a study of p ractical situations; for various reasons it wou ld seem that this work should come near the end of their formal training so that it can serve the proper function of synthesis and orderi ng. Ulti mately, the p ractical uses of cu rriculum theory depend on the i ndivi dual using the term and on his or her interp retation of its possibilities. The narrower conception of theory serves us relatively little; the broader version allows us many more av­ en ues legitimately called "theory." Perhaps we don't need the term at all ; but since we seem to hold some allegiance to it, perhaps the best we can do is to shake up our own conceptions as to what it is and allow it to include some of the very p ractical reason­ i ng that goes on regularly among all curri culists. I wonder if any of this solves the p roblem of the blank stares from colleagues. Perhaps not; it is sti ll hard to imagine most of them g reeting the label "curriculum theorist" with shouts of recognition and delight. Perhaps we need a closet to retreat into, camouflaging our activities with other nomencla­ tu res which have more recogn izable legiti macy among edu cators and others. We should perhaps determine which version of curricu lum theory we mean when we lay it on an unsuspecti ng educa­ tional psychologist colleague, and demonstrate an understandi n g of the confusions and li mitations of the term - all of which may be more than our col­ league wanted to know about it. In any event, hon­ esty still seems to be the best poli cy. A curricu lum theorist who is also a p hotographer might d o well si mply to describe herself as a photographer. Notes 1 . The same di ctionary provided several definitions of practice, all having to do with performance, action, and process. 2. The comparison really happened. A well docu mented story has it that Alexander Calder, visiting the studio of his colleague, the painter Joan Miro, looked at Mire's paint­ ings and their arrangements of color and said, "Wouldn't it be fun if they could move?" 3. Hence, we have had journals called Curriculum Theory Network and Journal of Curriculum Theorizing. References Anyon, Jean. Social class and the hidden curriculum of work. Journal of Education, 162 (1), Winter 1 980, 67-92. Duncan, J.K. and Frymier, J.R. Explorations in the systema­ tic study of curriculum. Theory Into Practice, 6, Oc­ tober 1 967, 1 80-199. Volume XX/, Number 1 9 Downloaded by [University of Birmingham] at 21:23 15 November 2014 Eisner, Elliot and Vallance, Elizabeth. Conflicting concep­ tions of curriculum. Berkeley: Mccutchan, 1 974. Glasser, William. Schools without failure. New York: Harper & Row, 1 969. Goodlad, J. and Richter, M. The development of a concep­ tual system for dealing with problems of curriculum and i nstruction. Los Angeles: UCLA, Project No. 454, HEW No. SAE-8024, 1 966. Huebner, Dwayne. Curricular language and classroom meaning. In Macdonald, J.B. and Leeper, R.R. (Eds.) Language and meaning. Washington: ASCD, 1 966. Mccutcheon, Gail. The curriculum: Patchwork or crazy q u i lt? Educational Leaders hip, 36 (2), November 1 978, 1 1 4-1 1 6. Mccutcheon, Gail. How do elementary teachers plan ? The Elementary School Journal, 8 1 ( 1 ) , September 1 980, 4-23. Morine, G reta, and Vallance, Elizabeth. The beginning teacher evaluation study, special study B: A study of teacher and pupil perceptions of classroom interac­ tion. San Francisco: Far West Laboratory for Educa­ tional Research and Development, 1 976. Schwab, Joseph. The P ractical : A language for curriculum. · School Review, 78, November 1 969, 1 -23. Simon, Roger. Programme portrayal and reflexive inquiry. Paper presented at the annual meeting of American Educational Research Association, Boston, Apri l 1 980. Tyler, Ralph. Basic principles of curriculum and instruc­ tion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 950. Walker, Decker. A naturalistic model for curriculum de­ velopment. School Review, BO, 1 971, 51 -65. Walker, Decker. Textbooks and textbook use (Research in progress, described i n Fall 1 980 Stanford Educator, p.2). tip 10 Theory Into Practice