Uploaded by Annie Ma

ECON1401 Lecture Scripts

advertisement
ECON1401
Marginal Analysis
What is value? In the classical school of economic thought embodied by thinkers like Adam
Smith, Karl Marx and David Ricardo, the worth of a good or service was seen to derive from
the labour value of that good. How much was the value of the labour that had gone into
producing it? Some distinctions were drawn between value in use and value in exchange,
where value in use could be calculated as the amount of labour saved by the user when using
the good. While exchange value brought in the connection of a good's value to its worth to
another person, apart from the initial user, there was no full reckoning by classical
economists of value in relation only to the entire marketplace on which the good traded.
Alfred Marshall, together with other economists who collectively contributed to what we now
call the marginalist revolution, turned in his search for an alternative measure of the
economic value of a good to its price. The price of a good is a signal of its value on the
market as a whole rather than being specific and personalised like value to the individual
user, or reflective of the amount of resources used to produce it, or that would be saved by its
use. Price is ruthlessly and narrowly a judgment upon the worth of the good to the market
right now - regardless of how costly it was to produce, or how much any individual person or
even society collectively might value it now or at another time.
Marshall applied marginal analysis to both sides of the market - supply and demand. On the
demand side, consumers buy according to a rule that compares the price of a good to the
marginal utility they obtain from it. On the supply side, producers are willing to sell a good in
the short run as long as they can recoup their marginal cost of producing that one additional
good (i.e., as long as price is at least as great as marginal cost). The supply and demand
curves that are generated by these decision processes, occurring on both sides of the market
across consumers and firms that are heterogeneous in their preferences and their production
costs, give rise to the familiar equilibrium price for a good - also, according to Marshall and
all of the ensuing neoclassical economists, the value of that good - where those two curves
intersect.
The idea of decision making on the margin has given rise to the indifference curve, to the
notion of firms deciding on input mix by considering the marginal rate of technical
substitution between those inputs, and to the notion of diminishing returns.
Marshall also pioneered the analysis of consumer and producer surplus (arguably another
form of value) and the impacts of taxation on surplus on both sides of the market. He also
was the first great economist to draw many of the graphs that we see today as standard in
neoclassical economics. A picture of the economy is worth a thousand words, and the
graphical expository techniques that Marshall popularised likely saved the economists who
came after him hundreds of thousands of words.
Opportunity Cost
Students often struggle to understand the concept of opportunity cost, and this is partly
because the way we calculate opportunity cost is not by figuring out how much something
costs, but rather by figuring out how much we benefit from something. Opportunity cost is
the value - the benefit - of the next best alternative action foregone by the decision maker
when he takes a particular action. It is in fact a cost, but an unseen one, of taking the chosen
action.
Frédéric Bastiat's parable of the broken window published in 1850 in "Ce qu'on voit et ce
qu'on ne voit pas" is a striking illustration of opportunity cost. Essentially he tells the parable
of a boy who breaks a window through throwing a ball through it and then people, the
onlookers, say, "oh, you know, it's not so bad because the whole economy will benefit since
the glazier will be employed to fix that window. There is a benefit from this destruction." But
in fact, Bastiat argues that's not the best way to use the money. That money could have been
spent on something else.
Let's take a modern and more personal example. Suppose you make an impulse purchase
while waiting in the checkout queue at the grocery store. Say you buy five dollars' worth of
lollies. By making that purchase, you are foregoing the value that you would obtain by
spending that five dollars on another good or service. If across all possible alternative uses of
the five dollars, you would most value the lollies, then an economist would not quibble with
the optimality of your choice, but your choice would still carry an opportunity cost, equal to
the value of the next-best most favoured thing you could have bought - for example, the value
to you of five dollars worth of beer, or chips, or cherries. If in fact you get more value from
buying something other than lollies with your five dollars, then an economist, using the
Homo Economicus model to predict your behaviour, would be very confused by your choice
to buy the lollies.
In the broken window parable, Bastiat alleges that even though repairing the broken window
does give work to a glazier, breaking windows on purpose in order to ensure that glaziers
don't go unemployed would be a sub-optimal decision for the economy. To support this
claim, he compares the benefit of the repair work to glaziers - one segment of the economy to the benefit of using the resources spent in repairing windows on other things instead, that
support the economy in other ways, providing employment to other workers in different
sectors, or even funding investment into innovation and hence further future growth of the
economy.
A big part of thinking like an economist is thinking about what is given up when a choice is
made in a world where resources are scarce. Trade-offs are implicit in every resource
allocation decision, and the concept of opportunity cost embodies that pillar of economic
thought better than any other concept.
Externalities
My son is studying to play piano at Boston University and when he used to live in the home,
and be playing and practicing all the time, I would come home from work and have a lovely
evening with my husband, cooking dinner while we heard piano music in the background.
This was an example of a positive externality: Neil's playing, which was beneficial for him,
was also beneficial for us because it gave a nice ambiance to the environment in the home.
However, his playing often continued after dinner and up until the point when we wanted to
go to bed, and then even after that point. At that stage in the evening, his piano playing was
then generating negative externalities: although he was enjoying it, it was impacting
negatively on other people in the household.
Ronald Coase, who won the Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences in 1991, famously analysed
the situation of externalities and put forward a proposition that if there are no transaction
costs, then allocating the right to some property that's relevant in the creation of externalities
to one party or the other will enable those parties to come to a traded solution which
optimises the level of production of the good that generates the externalities.
In the example of the piano playing, if you imagine that the property right being allocated is
the right to create noise in the home, then that allocated right could be given first to our son,
for example, and then we, the parents, could bargain with him and say, "Look, if we pay you
a bit of money, would you be willing to not play as much in the late evening?" Alternatively,
that property could be allocated to us, in which case he would then come to us, offering us
money to be able to play a bit more than nothing in the late evening. Either way that the
initial property right is allocated would generate, according to the Coase theorem, the same
solution in terms of the amount of piano playing done.
The problem, of course, in the real world is that there are transaction costs associated with
this sort of bargaining. Also, of course, the individuals involved really do care about the
initial allocation of property rights, because that impacts their ultimate wealth level.
In the example of the piano playing, the transaction cost might be that I don't really feel
comfortable taking money or giving money to my son in relation to his piano playing. I
actually, as a mother, just want him to do lots of that and I'm willing to sacrifice and take the
cost of the fact that he's playing. Maybe that could be a barrier in real life. In families, often
times it's not money that's exchanged but other sorts of in-kind favours. So, for example, he
might say, "Well, if I play a little bit tonight, how about I walk the dog tomorrow or do the
dishes?", and then we might agree to that. That's still a form of bargaining, and that kind of
bargaining happens in families all the time.
Comparative Advantage
So the concept of comparative advantage is often attributed to David Ricardo, and he spoke
in terms of comparative advantage between countries. But let's work through an example that
considers production in the home.
So let's assume that you have a set of inputs that we'll call time (like maybe one hour of
time), flour, sugar, fruit, and water. With that set of inputs, you might be able to make a
number of different things. And there are often two householders in a given household, so
let's imagine that we want to look at the productivity of each of those two householders in
producing two different things that you could make with that same input set.
So let's imagine we have Mom and we have Dad. We have two things we could make. We
could make kids' snacks, and we could make pies. So typically when we look at comparative
advantage, we make a table. And often times the classical depiction of opportunity cost and
comparative advantage uses a different formula than what I'm doing here. This is a more
general way of describing it, which hopefully you'll find illuminating.
So, you take this set of inputs... If you're Mom, you can, with those inputs, make eight kiddie
snacks. And you can also, alternatively, make two pies. If you're Dad, let's say you can make
six kiddie snacks or one pie. Now when you look at that, first off, you think "Well, obviously
Mom should be doing everything because she has an absolute advantage over Dad in the
production of both of these things." But as we'll see, actually there is a difference between the
two of these people in their relative productivities across the two different possible uses of
the inputs. And that gives rise to comparative advantage of one person in one production and
the other person in the other production. And then it's optimal for the household to have that
sort of specialisation according to their comparative advantage.
So let's look at that over here. So, for Mom, what is the opportunity cost of making the eight
snacks? Well, the opportunity cost is what she could have made with the same inputs, if she
didn't make the snacks. And that's two pies. So the opportunity cost for Mom of making the
eight snacks is equal to two pies. Now for Dad, the opportunity cost of making the six snacks
that he makes with those inputs is one pie. And we can do the same thing in reverse: we can
say the opportunity cost of making these two pies, for mom, is eight snacks And for Dad, the
opportunity cost of making one pie is six snacks.
Now what we can do to figure out who has a comparative advantage in what is take the ratio
of the opportunity costs. So, for Mom, the ratio of the opportunity cost of making the pies
over the opportunity cost of making snacks is equal to eight snacks over two pies, or four. For
Dad, on the other hand, the opportunity cost of making pies over the opportunity cost of
making snacks is equal to six snacks over one pie, or six. So who has the lower ratio of
opportunity costs? This person. So what that means is that Mom should specialise in making
pies. The relative opportunity cost for her of making pies, relative to making snacks, when
compared with Dad, is lower. Dad, alternatively, as the opposite, should be specialising in
making snacks. And you can think about that as simply reversing these ratios, so his
opportunity cost of making snacks, relative to the opportunity cost of making pies, is onesixth, whereas Mom's is two-eighths, or one-fourth. And one-sixth is smaller than one-fourth,
so again, smaller relative opportunity cost for Dad of making snacks relative to pies.
So, we end up that Mom specialises in making pies, dad specialises in making snacks, and so
the whole household gets six snacks and two pies from each parent spending one hour of
their time and all of these other inputs making something.
Now, you might argue, "How about Mom just does both of those things." Again, because if
she spends two hours she gets more stuff than what we get if each parent spends the one hour.
And often times, households will specialise more broadly in terms of household labour versus
labour at work, and sometimes that's because of these kinds of comparative advantage
arguments.
I will also say that of course, like any other example of comparative advantage, such as
David Ricardo's example of Portugal and England making wine and cloth, respectively, there
is an assumption built in that the market is going to value each of these goods.
So the analysis here is all predicated upon the notion that the household really wants snacks
and also really wants pies, and it sort of wants them both all the time. There's no
consideration of changes and market scenarios. Remember, comparative advantage is a
classical sort of concept that came up before the Marginalist Revolution. It was inspired by,
and reflects very much, the labour theory of value of goods.
Behavioural Economics
When I was a child growing up in Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania, my mother worked at Carnegie
Mellon University and that happened to be where Herbert Simon also worked, and we went
to a church where he also attended, and I remember after the sermons, we'd have coffee hour
and my mother and Herb Simon would spend an hour talking about ideas in relation to
human decision making and motivation and psychology. My mom was herself a cognitive
therapist and so it was the most wonderful look on her face that I would see, every Sunday,
when she was able to have a conversation with Herb Simon.
Herb Simon was an economist and a cognitive scientist and a pioneer of the notion that
cognitive limitations - what he called bounded rationality - fundamentally impacts human
decision making. We might like to think that decision makers always select the best outcome
via a comprehensive consideration of all the alternative actions available at any given
decision point, and that's what the standard Homo Economicus model asserts. But Simon
bluntly rejected this as impossible. His work on decision making in administrative
organizations and rational decision making in general earned him a Nobel Prize in 1978.
Since that time, a raft of economists have joined the chorus of voices claiming that some, if
not all, of the core assumptions about economic decision making maintained by mainstream
economic theory are simply not valid. These critiques, which often come together with toy
models and empirical evidence from the experimental laboratory or the field, claim to
illustrate the inaccuracy of traditional assumptions and are seen by the profession to be part
of the relatively new sub-field of behavioral economics. In the academic literature, we've
seen models in empirical work and behavioral economics focusing on cognitive constraints of
many flavours, as well as attempts to build into models of human decision making notions
like identity, altruism and social norms that are entirely omitted from the Homo Economicus
model.
Some economists have made lots of money on popular science books arguing for their
particular favourite wrong assumption. Two famous examples are Thinking Fast and Slow by
Daniel Kahneman and Nudge by Cass Sunstein and Richard Thaler. (Note that Kahneman
and Thaler are both winners of the Nobel Prize in economic sciences.)
Far deeper work is required before economists will be in a position to deliver a renovated
theory of individual decision making that retains the simplicity and tractability of the Homo
Economicus model yet captures more realistically the constraints and objectives, both seen
and unseen, faced by human decision makers.
Download