1 There are three points that I would like to discuss. Firstly, I will point out the ambiguity in the conceptualization of development in developmental systems theories (DST). Secondly, I will pose a question if it is necessary to abandon developmental theories in foundational periods given the existence of DST. Finally, I would like to note some of my thoughts on the DST's ability to change our perception of human beings' relationship with the natural environment. The first point is that DST lacks a clear conception of development. As Lerner, LewinBizan, and Warren (2011, p. 3) warned, "development is not an empirical concept." The understanding of researchers on human development determines how they collect, organize, and interpret observable data. Different perspectives lead to different formulations while describing and explaining phenomena (Lerner et al., 2011; Miller, 2011). In the evaluation of developmental theory, uncovering the author's assumptions on development helps us consider its limitations in capturing human development's nature. Scientists have reached a consensus on several features of development including systematic, organized, and successive changes (Lerner et al., 2011). The nature of human development, as DST has asserted, reflects these characteristics. Specifically, they assume that "basic developmental process as involving relations – or 'fusions' – among variables from multiple levels of organization that comprise the ecology of human development" (Lerner et al., 2011, p. 3). However, the question is whether these properties are adequate to identify when development occurs. For example, how to distinguish between development and its opposite – or regression in Freud's term? Is every change in the interaction between a person and his or her ecological context development? There was no explicit declaration in Lener et al. 's description of DST. However, these authors claimed that the practical purpose of DST is to promote "positive individual-context relations." Baltes' life-span developmental theory and Brandtstädter's action theories of human development concluded that development is the changes stemming from the mutually interactive relationships between people and their contexts, and aiming towards the adaptation (Lerner et al., 2011). These arguments imply that what distinguishes development from systematic, organized, and successive changes, and regression, is the positivity and adaptation. Yet, what are positivity and adaptation? For instance, are mental disorders positive and adaptive changes that inform problems existing in the individual-context relation? Or they are maladaptive and harmful adjustments? Answering these questions continues requiring DST's scientists to rely on an ideology which may include bias in their research studies in the same way reductionist and individualistic worldviews did. 2 The second point that I would like to consider is the possibility of leaving out developmental theories in prior historical periods of this field. Although these theories, which were biased by their author's worldviews (Cairns & Cairns, 2006; Dixon & Lerner, 1988; Lerner et al. 2011; Miller, 2011), did not fully explain human development, they did reveal fragments of it, and we have benefited from those findings. Take Piaget's theory of cognitive development as an example. It overlooked the influences of sociocultural context on the emergence of children's intellectual functions. However, its detailed description of that process has guided our decisions on what we teach, how we teach, and when we teach children. Do we need to discard these reductionist and individualist theories? Or we can still exploit them as guidelines for research and intervention practices while being alert of their limitations? These theories may be alternative choices for scientists while considering DST's complicated and rigorous research methodology, measurement, design, and analysis (Lerner et al., 2011). Given limited resources and time, we need the most parsimonious solution to predict and intervene in developmental phenomena (Miller, 2011). DST sometimes may not be an optimal choice. Finally, DST's conceptualization of human beings as part of the whole ecological context removes the inequality between human beings and other natural environment entities. While Bronfenbrenner's ecological systems theory may illustrate its stance by putting an individual in the central of the whole ecological context, we may expand our perspective by looking at these systems and its components as equally coexistent entities. Admitting the implicitly inherent plasticity or historical potentials to change in the organizations of the ecological context of which we are a part means that we may be affected by their changes. Any changes in one of them may impact or even transform the whole context and ourselves. This implication may encourage research studies on the influence of large-scale environmental change (e.g., climate change and the extinction of species) on human development. References Cairns, R. B., & Cairns, B. D. (2006). The making of developmental psychology. In R. M. Lerner (Ed.). Handbook of Child Psychology: Vol. 1. Theoretical models of human development (pp. 89–164). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Dixon, R. A., & Lerner, R. M. (1992). A history of systems in developmental psychology. In M. H. Bornstein & M. E. Lamb (Eds.), Developmental psychology: An advanced textbook (4th ed., p. 3–58). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc. Lerner, R. M., Lewin-Bizan, S., & Warren, A. E. A. (2011). Concepts and theories of human development. In M. H. Bornstein, & M. E. Lamb, M. E. (Eds.) Developmental Science: 3 An advanced textbook (6th ed., pp.3–43). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers. Miller, P. H. (2016). Theories of developmental psychology (6th edition). New York, NY: Publishers.