General Section Autonomy for Minorities: Definitions, Types and Status in International Law Athanasios Yupsanis* ABSTRACT: Autonomy for minorities is a recurring issue in legal and political studies. Adherents of the idea argue that it would offer enhanced protection to minorities and ensure State and regional peace and stability. Opponents claim that it could lead to destabilisation and secession, as well as to discrimination against ‘minorities within minorities’. These concerns have resulted in a refusal so far to recognise such a right to minorities. Recent developments, however, like the recognition of a right to autonomy to indigenous peoples in the 2007 UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (UNDRIP), can benefit minorities, notwithstanding the fact that the UN treats these two kinds of groups as distinct categories with different sets of rights, because of the several analogies and similarities found between them. In this context, it is argued that recognising a right to autonomy to minorities in international law upon certain terms, would give them a better bargaining position for negotiating their rights within States’ borders. In such a case, a combination of territorial and non-territorial arrangements would foster minority protection and help prevent ethnic conflict. KEYWORDS: territorial autonomy, non-territorial/cultural autonomy, minority rights 1. Introduction The idea of autonomy, which the Oxford English Dictionary defines as ‘the right of self-government’,1 is ‘a re-emerging topic’2 for minorities in academic and policy makers’ domestic discussions on the management of ethno-cultural diversity and the protection of minority rights both in Europe * LL.M, PhD in International Law, Adjunct Lecturer at the School of Political Sciences of Aristotle University of Thessaloniki; Contact: thayup2@gmail.com. 1. See Glen Anderson, ‘Secession in International Law and Relations: What Are We Talking About?’ (2013) 35 Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review 343–88, 385. 2. Péter Kovács, ‘Autonomy and International Law’ [translated by Endre Orbán] (2012) 3 Délkelet Európa – SouthEast Europe International Relations Quarterly 1–3, 1. 4 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) and elsewhere.3 Its proponents include several scholars and certain political bodies, such as the Parliamentary Assembly (PACE) of the Council of Europe (CoE), and a few individual States (eg Hungary), which argue that minority autonomy can contribute to minority protection and ethnic conflict prevention. The PACE, for example, has recently stated in its Resolution 1985 (2014) that ‘[m]inority protection is … a means of conflict prevention’,4 and that ‘territorial arrangements might play an important role for the effective protection of the rights of national minorities’.5 The PACE also referred to non-territorial arrangements in its Resolution 1866 (2012) on the adoption of an additional protocol to the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR) for national minorities, suggesting that such a protocol could guarantee some minimum standards, ‘including the right to cultural autonomy to preserve national identity’.6 In an analogous context, the Advisory Committee (ACFC) of the Framework Convention for the Protection of National Minorities (FCNM) of CoE examined the functioning and impact of territorial and non-territorial cultural autonomy arrangements in those States Parties where they exist, and commented that the former ‘can foster a more effective participation of persons belonging to national minorities in various areas of life’,7 while the latter can ‘contribute to the preservation and development of minority cultures’.8 3. Günther Rautz, ‘Exploring Territorial and Cultural Autonomy as a Means of Conflict Resolution and Minority Protection’ in Thomas Benedikter (ed), Solving Ethnic Conflict Through Self-Government: A Short Guide to Autonomy in Europe and South Asia (Bozen/Bolzano, EURAC, 2009) 4–5. 4. PACE, Resolution 1985 (2014), The Situation and Rights of National Minorities in Europe, debate on 8 April 2014 (13th Sitting), para 6 www.assembly.coe.int/nw/xml/XRef/XrefXML2HTML-en.asp?fileid=20772&lang=en (last accessed 10 December 2018). All further references to online sources are accurate as of that date. 5. Ibid, para 7. See also PACE, Resolution 1333 (2003), Positive Experiences of Autonomous Regions as a Source of Inspiration for Conflict Resolution in Europe, debate on 24 June 2003 (19th Sitting), para 16 www.assembly.coe.int/nw/xml/XRef/Xref-XML2HTML-en. asp?fileid=17120&lang=en. 6. PACE, Resolution 1866 (2012), An Additional Protocol to the European Convention on Human Rights on National Minorities, text adopted by the Standing Committee, acting on behalf of the Assembly, on 9 March 2012, para 6.3 www.assembly.coe.int/nw/xml/XRef/ Xref-XML2HTML-EN.asp?fileid=18074&lang=en. For a critical view on the PACE’s minority autonomy proposal, see Stephanie E Berry, ‘The Siren’s Call? Exploring the Implications of an Additional Protocol to the European Convention on Human Rights in National Minorities’ (2016) 23 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 1–38, 11. 7. ACFC, Commentary on the Effective Participation of Persons Belonging to National Minorities in Cultural, Social and Economic Life and in Public Affairs, ACFC/31DOC(2008)001, Strasbourg, 5 May 2008, para 134. 8. Ibid, para 135. Autonomy for Minorities 5 The opponents of the idea, on the other hand, include the vast majority of States, which fear that it would lead to destabilisation and even to secession, and scholars, who argue that it will result in discrimination against ‘internal minorities’.9 Due mainly to strong States’ objections to the recognition of a minority right to autonomy, no such right exists, not only in general public international law,10 but also in the stricter context of the regional European legal order, which accords stronger protection to minorities. The FCNM, for example, the only legally binding multilateral instrument devoted to minority rights, does not provide for a right to autonomy of persons belonging to minorities, whether territorial or non-territorial/cultural.11 Also, the aforementioned PACE resolutions and recommendations are merely of a political nature and not legally binding,12 as are the very few, and weakly worded, relevant provisions found in exclusively ‘soft law’ minority texts, which will be examined below. Public international law, however, is not carved in stone, but is constantly evolving and adapting to new situations, needs and demands. Originally it mainly governed relations between States, which were the only subjects that had rights and duties under its norms. Today, however, groups such as indigenous peoples to a larger degree13 and minorities to a lesser are also recognised, albeit reluctantly, as minor actors, having some rights and duties under it.14 Specifically regarding minority rights it should be noted that, until the late 1980s, most States declined to adopt positive measures of minority protection, under the argument that this kind of treatment is detrimental 9. Farimah Daftary, ‘Insular Autonomy: A Framework for Conflict Resolution? A Comparative Study of Corsica and the Aaland Islands’ (2001) 1 The Global Review of Ethnopolitics 19–40, 20. 10. See Doris Wydra, ‘The Crimea Conundrum: The Tug of War Between Russia and Ukraine on the Questions of Autonomy and Self-Determination’ (2004) 10 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 111–30, 123; Thomas D Musgrave, Self-Determination and National Minorities (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1997) 208; Patrick Thornberry, ‘Minorities and Europe: The Architecture of Rights’ (1994) XLII European Yearbook 1–19, 10. 11. György Frunda (Rapporteur), An Additional Protocol to the European Convention on Human Rights on National Minorities, Committee on Legal Affairs and Human Rights, AS/Jur(2011)46, 8 November 2011, para 58. 12. Tudor Tănăsescu, ‘Council of Europe and the Protection of Minorities’ (2013) 2 AGORA International Journal of Juridical Sciences 197–203, 202. 13. See Vassilis Grammatikas, ‘Kossovo v. South Osetia? Modern Politics of Secession and International Law’ (2009) 1 Journal of International Law 26–43, 27. 14. See Prosper Nobirabo Musafiri, ‘Right to Self-Determination in International Law: Towards Theorisation of the Concept of Indigenous Peoples/National Minority?’ (2012) 19 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 481–532, 481. 6 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) to national unity since it creates privileges for minorities.15 This attitude was also in line with the interpretation agreed at the time of the adoption (1966) of Article 27 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), the main universal legally binding minority norm, which provides that minority members shall not be denied their right to use their language, to enjoy their culture and to profess and practice their religion.16 Its negative phrasing was construed to imply a passive State duty of noninterference in the exercising of minority rights, rather than a proactive State role.17 Such an approach, however, has been abandoned since the early 1990s, and the necessity of State sustaining action in order to realise a full equality between majority and minority members, as well as to guarantee the necessary preconditions for the protection and promotion of minorities’ identity, is now widely accepted.18 One might also note that, although minority rights are individual,19 current developments, such as the interpretation given for Article 15 para 1 (a) of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) on the right to take part in cultural life by the Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (CESCR) in its General Comment No 23 (2009), recognise inter alia the minority per se as a bearer of the specific right.20 Under the prism, then, of this evolutional nature of international law, it could be argued that the recent recognition of a right to autonomy to indigenous peoples in the 2007 UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (UNDRIP) can benefit minorities because of the several analogies and similarities found between them.21 Recognising a right to autonomy to minorities in international law under certain guarantees, 15. Patrick Thornberry, ‘Is There a Phoenix in the Ashes? International Law and Minority Rights’ (1980) 15 Texas International Law Journal 421–58, 456. 16. See Athanasios Yupsanis, ‘Article 27 of the ICCPR Revisited: The Right to Culture as a Normative Source for Indigenous/Minority Participatory Claims in the Case Law of the Human Rights Committee’ (2013) 26 Hague Yearbook of International Law 358–409. 17. Jean-Paul Schreuder, ‘Minority Protection Within the Concept of Self-Determination’ (1995) 8 Leiden Journal of International Law 53–80, 70. 18. Linos-Alexandros Sicilianos, ‘The Protection of Minorities in Europe: Collective Aspects of Individual Rights’ in Linos-Alexandros Sicilianos and Antonis Bredimas (eds), The Protection of Minorities: The Framework Convention of the Council of Europe (Athens, Sakkoulas, 1997) 93–129, 116, 128 (in Greek). 19. Johanna Gibson, ‘The UDHR and the Group: Individual and Community Rights to Culture’ (2008–2009) 30 Hamiline Journal of Public Law and Policy 285–317, 295. 20. See Athanasios Yupsanis, ‘The Meaning of ‘Culture’ in Article 15 (1) (a) of the ICESCR – Positive Aspects of CESCR’s General Comment No. 21 for the Safeguarding of Minority Cultures’ (2012) 55 German Yearbook of International Law 345–83. 21. Makau Mutua, ‘The Iraq Paradox: Minority and Group Rights in a Viable Constitution’ (2006) 54 Buffalo Law Review 927–55, 938. Autonomy for Minorities 7 such as a strong commitment on the part of the minority autonomous institutions to the States’ territorial integrity and to the rights of ‘minorities within minorities’, would mean that its existence, its weakening and its abolishment would not depend exclusively on national legislation as has been the case until now. Such a development would give minorities added bargaining strength with which to negotiate their rights within the States’ territory. As the ACFC has commented, territorial and non-territorial instruments can be ‘fully in line with the international law principle of territorial integrity and can be a useful tool to promote the enjoyment of minority rights’.22 In this light, and after analysing the definitions and types of models of autonomy, this article suggests that territorial settlements are best suited to minorities that are geographically compact and highly politically motivated, while nonterritorial schemes can be better adapted to the needs of small and scattered minorities. Also, given that each territorial minority has its own ‘minority diaspora’ within the State, it would be logical to suggest that a combination of territorial and non-territorial arrangements would most effectively foster minority protection and help prevent ethnic conflict. 2. Definitional Issues: Territorial and Non-Territorial Autonomy 2.1. The Concept of Autonomy Assessing the definitions given for the meaning of the word ‘autonomy’ and its main types is a necessary first step towards acquiring a more or less clear picture of its basic elements and the scope of protection it may provide to minority groups. The definitional approaches suggest that territorial settlements are more suitable for the satisfaction of the claims of geographically concentrated minorities, while non-territorial arrangements correspond better to the needs of scattered minorities. Also, given the broader scope of devolved powers enjoyed by territorial regimes, it is fair to argue that they provide stronger protection to minority identities than non-territorial schemes. Beginning, then, with the meaning of the notion, Hannum and Lillich noted in their seminal essay 35 years ago that ‘[a]utonomy is not a term of art or a concept that has a generally accepted definition in international law’.23 22. ACFC, The Framework Convention: A Key Tool to Managing Diversity Through Minority Rights, Thematic Commentary No 4, ACFC/56DOC(2016)001, Strasburg, 27 May 2016, para 78. 23. Hurst Hannum and Richard B Lillich, ‘The Concept of Autonomy in International Law’ (1980) 74 American Journal of International Law 858–89, 858. 8 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) A similar approach is presented by Légaré and Suksi in their introductory note to the 15th volume of the 2008 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights dedicated to the issue.24 In the same vein, Cassese points out that the concept is ‘still vague and imprecise’.25 The first remark to be made on the topic, then, is that there is still no commonly agreed definition of autonomy in international law.26 Etymologically, the notion derives from the Greek words αυτο (self ) and νόμος (law), thus literally meaning the right to make one’s own laws.27 Today, the term is used in various scientific fields, its content differing depending on the context. In philosophy, for example, it signifies an individual’s power to determine alone, through his/her own rational will, a ‘positive liberty’; in the natural sciences, it means organic independence or the condition of a phenomenon conforming only to its own laws and not subject to higher rules;28 in legal-political vocabulary it stands for self-government, a term that is often intermixed or used interchangeably with ‘autonomy’, as synonymous with it.29 Other concepts used in legal and political studies are ‘self-management’, ‘self-rule’, ‘self-administration’, ‘home rule’ and ‘self-legislation’.30 This multiplicity of terms reflects inter alia the variety of the typology of autonomy arrangements. Indeed, there is no uniform model of autonomy, since each case depends on such factors as ‘history, traditions of governance, the size of territory, the size and number of communities, 24. André Légaré and Markku Suksi, ‘Introduction: Rethinking the Forms of Autonomy at the Dawn of the 21st Century’ (2008) 15 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 143–55, 143. 25. Antonio Cassese, Self-Determination of Peoples: A Legal Reappraisal (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995) 355. 26. Samuel De Jaegere, ‘The Belgian Thesis Revisited: United Nations Member States’ Obligation to Develop Autonomy for Indigenous Peoples’ (2003) XIV Finnish Yearbook of International Law 159–204, 198. 27. Matti Wiberg, ‘Ambiguities and Clarifications of the Concept of Autonomy’ in Zelim A Skurbaty (ed), Beyond a One Dimensional State: An Emerging Right to Autonomy? (Leiden/Boston, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2005) 177–90, 181. 28. Ruth Lapidoth, Autonomy: Flexible Solutions to Ethnic Conflicts (Washington, DC, United States Institute of Peace Press, 1996) 29. 29. Lauri Hannikainen, ‘Self-Determination and Autonomy in International Law’ in Markku Suksi (ed), Autonomy: Applications and Implications (The Hague/London/Boston, Kluwer Law International, 1998) 79–95, 79. 30. Natalia Loukacheva, ‘On Autonomy and Law’, Institute on Globalization and the Human Condition, Working Paper Series GHC 05/3 (2005) 2 www.crunch.mcmaster.ca/ institute-on-globalization-and-the-human-condition/documents/IGHC-WPS_05-3_ Loukacheva.pdf. Autonomy for Minorities 9 and internal and external pressures’.31 Broadly speaking, however, autonomy is generally seen in legal and political theory as either territorial or nonterritorial. In the first case, the autonomy is rooted in the principle of territoriality, meaning that the rules to be applied depend mainly on the specific geographical area in question. In the second, it is based on the personality principle, namely that the application of the relevant norms depends on the ethnic affiliation of the persons concerned, irrespective of their place of residence within the state.32 2.2. Basic Elements of Territorial Autonomy A common feature of the several definitions given for the notion of territorial autonomy is that of an institutional arrangement for establishing a legal regime marked by the transfer of certain executive, legislative and judicial powers in one or more specified fields of governmental competence33 from the central authorities to a region of the State without its being detached from the State of which it is a part.34 That region usually possesses some ethnic or cultural distinctiveness,35 which the majority or a large part of its inhabitants want to preserve and develop. Thus, territorial autonomy firstly presupposes a clearly identifiable territory where a minority or an indigenous people lives in a fairly concentrated way, constituting a regional majority, because it then becomes easier to delineate the jurisdiction within which the specific self-government will be exercised.36 It is within this territory that the principle of territoriality, on which territorial autonomy is based, applies; this means ‘that the local autonomous legislative body should be elected and the administrative body selected by the inhabitants of the autonomous area’.37 31. Mark Bennett, ‘Indigenous Autonomy and Justice in North America’ (2004) 2 New Zealand Journal of Public and International Law 203–16, 207. 32. Kenneth D McRae, ‘The Principle of Territoriality and the Principle of Personality in Multilingual States’ (1975) 4 International Journal of the Sociology of Language 33–54, 33, 40. 33. Stefan Wolff, ‘Conflict Management in Divided Societies: The Many Uses of Territorial Self-Governance’ (2013) 20 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 27–50, 32. 34. James Crawford, The Creation of States in International Law, 2nd edn (Oxford, Oxford University Press,2006) 323. 35. Lars Adam Rehof, ‘Human Rights and Self-Government for Indigenous Peoples’ (1994) 61/62 Nordic Journal of International Law 10–41, 19. 36. Markku Suksi, ‘Concluding Remarks’ in Suksi (n 29) 357–63, 359. 37. Kristian Myntti, ‘The Beneficiaries of Autonomy Arrangements – With Special Reference to Indigenous Peoples in General and the Sami in Finland in Particular’ in Suksi (n 29) 277–94, 278. 10 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) The second element, which is inseparable from the first, is the existence of a specific minority group (or indigenous people) which is officially recognised by the government concerned. As Myntti comments, ‘[e]ven if it is true that the exercise of far-reaching autonomous powers requires that the authority and jurisdiction of the autonomous bodies be territorially defined, people, not territories, need and demand autonomy’.38 Finally, a third constituent aspect of territorial autonomy regimes is their subjection to State sovereignty. As Hannum observes, ‘[a]utonomy is not equivalent to independence, and autonomous governments should not expect to be immune from the influence of central governments’.39 Under this perception, the areas in which the territorial self-government may assume primary or significant authority include, according to the ‘Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe’s (OSCE) Lund Recommendations on the Effective Participation of National Minorities in Public Life’, ‘education, culture, use of minority language, environment, local planning, natural resources, economic development, local policing functions, housing, health and other social services’.40 The central government, for its part, retains its exclusive jurisdiction in the fields of defence, foreign affairs, immigration and customs, macroeconomic policies and monetary affairs.41 Further, depending on the range of matters delegated and the scope and depth of the devolved powers, territorial regimes are divided into those entities that i) enjoy legislative powers (often called ‘political autonomies’) like Catalonia, Euskadi, Galicia, Scotland, Gagauzia, Greenland, South Tyrol, the Åland Islands etc, or ii) hold regulatory/administrative powers, like Corsica, Wales, Nunavut, etc.42 From the above description one may conclude that territorial autonomy seems to be a workable means of protection for minorities that are politically conscious of their ethnic distinctiveness and are geographically compact in 38. Ibid (emphasis added). 39. Hurst Hannum, Autonomy, Sovereignty, and Self-Determination: The Accommodation of Conflicting Rights (Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press, 1990) 468. 40. ‘The Lund Recommendations on the Effective Participation of National Minorities in Public Life and Explanatory Note’ (2000) 11 Helsinki Monitor 47–61, 50 (Chap III, para 20). 41. Ibid, 49, 59 (Chap III, para 15); See also Hans-Joachim Heintze, ‘Implementation of Minority Rights Through the Devolution of Powers – The Concept of Autonomy Reconsidered’ (2002) 9 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 325–43, 332. 42. Roger Suso, ‘Territorial Autonomy and Self-Determination Conflicts: Opportunity and Willingness Cases from Bolivia, Niger and Thailand’, Institut Catala International per la Pau, ICIP Working Papers, 2010/01, Barcelona (2010) 12, http://icip.gencat.cat/ web/.content/continguts/publicacions/workingpapers/arxius/wp10_1_ang.pdf. Autonomy for Minorities 11 a way that permits the effective exercise of the delegated powers in their area of inhabitancy. This model gives minority institutions a broad jurisdiction in several fields that are crucial for the protection and promotion of minority identity, while at the same time it does not endanger States’ stability and territorial integrity, since autonomy can by its very nature be exercised only within States’ borders. Thus, it seems to be a practical mode of mutual compromise between minority bodies and State governments. 2.3. Non-Territorial Forms of Autonomy Non-territorial autonomy is usually understood in legal and political studies as ‘personal’, ‘cultural’ and ‘functional’.43 Other terms also in use are ‘national cultural autonomy’, ‘extraterritorial’, ‘corporate’ and ‘segmental’.44 As Henrard notes, a common denominator of all these non-territorial forms of autonomy ‘is that the competences are transferred not in relation to a certain specific territory but in relation to a certain community, irrespective of size and place of residence in the State’.45 Beyond this general observation, one may note that the differences and distinctions between the three main types of non-territorial autonomy are not perfectly clear, but partly overlap and intertwine, which explains why a certain term may have different meanings for different scholars and officials. For example, there are scholars who use the terms ‘personal’ and ‘cultural’ autonomy interchangeably, considering ‘that this type of autonomy applies to all the members of a certain group within the state, regardless of the place of their residence’.46 Others do the same with the terms ‘functional’ and ‘cultural’ autonomy.47 A third view holds that cultural autonomy is confined to cultural matters, such as language, education and so on, while personal autonomy is autonomy granted to a group as a legal person irrespective of the territorial principle. Under this understanding, cultural autonomy is personal autonomy limited to cultural affairs.48 Finally, there are authors for whom personal autonomy refers more 43. Tatiana Rudneva, ‘Non-Territorial Autonomy in Russia: Practical Implications of Theoretical Approaches’ (2012) 7 The Romanian Journal of Society and Politics 27–47, 30. 44. John Coakley, ‘Introduction: Dispersed Minorities and Non-Territorial Autonomy’ (2016) 15 Ethnopolitics 1–23, 11. 45. Kristin Henrard, ‘Participation, Representation and Autonomy in the Lund Recommendations and their Reflections in the Supervision of the FCNM and Several Human Rights Conventions’ (2005) 12 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 133–68, 141. 46. Lapidoth (n 28) 37. 47. Sherrill Stroschein, ‘What Belgium Can Teach Bosnia: The Uses of Autonomy in Divided House States’ (2003) Issue 3 Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe 1–30, 10. 48. Rudneva (n 43) 30. 12 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) to a guarantee of certain basic civil liberties and rights to all individuals, irrespective of their belonging or not to a specific group.49 Regarding functional autonomy, Suksi argues that it is possible to speak about this type of autonomy when private subjects of law are vested with public functions and powers.50 In the same vein, Malloy points out that while non-territorial autonomies are generally agreed to be public law instruments, functional autonomies ‘need not be adopted as public law instruments’ but operate through private establishments regulated by the law on private associations.51 Finally, for Henrard, ‘the only difference between the three types of non-territorial autonomy seems to be the type of body/corporation that exercises the competences transferred’.52 2.4. Concluding Remarks The above analysis leads to the conclusion that there are at least three main differences between the non-territorial/cultural and the territorial autonomy model, namely, that i) the administration is assigned to a culturally rather than territorially defined group, ii) the scope of self-government is limited to cultural aspects, and iii) cultural authority can be exercised only over those individuals who voluntarily opt for the cultural group.53 On this basis, it seems reasonable to argue that the territorial autonomy model provides for stronger minority protection, since it covers a broader range of areas of minority interest than the non-territorial one, which is more focused on specific items, mostly in the cultural sphere. In this regard, it could be claimed that territorial autonomy is more appropriate for the case of minorities that are highly politically motivated, usually in connection with the national identity of another ‘kin’ state, and thus are not probably satisfied with rights of an exclusively cultural nature. 49. Michael Tkacik, ‘Characteristics of Forms of Autonomy’ (2008) 15 International Journal of Minority and Group Rights 369–401, 370–71, 374. 50. Markku Suksi, ‘Functional Autonomy: The Case of Finland with Some Notes on the Basis of International Human Rights Law and Comparisons with Other Cases’ (2008) 15 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 195–225, 197. 51. Tove H Malloy, ‘The Lund Recommendations and Non-Territorial Arrangements: Progressive De-territorialization of Minority Politics’ (2009) 16 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 665–79, 667–68, 672. 52. Henrard (n 45) 141. 53. Yvonne Donders, ‘The UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples – A Victory for Cultural Autonomy?’ in I Boerefijn and J Goldschmidt (eds), Changing Perceptions of Sovereignty and Human Rights: Essays in Honour of Cees Flinterman (Antwerp, Intersentia, 2008) 99–122, 100. Autonomy for Minorities 13 3. The Battle of Autonomies: Non-Territorial Autonomy v Territorial and Vice Versa 3.1. Arguments in Favour of Non-Territorial Arrangements In legal and political theory there is a confrontation between those who argue that territorial settlements can offer enhanced protection to minorities and those who claim that non-territorial forms of autonomy can be of more functional value as regards the safeguarding of minority cultures. Given, however, that each geographically compact minority has its own ‘minority diaspora’, which lives outside the autonomous area and thus does not enjoy the minority protection that the autonomy regime provides, it is logical to suggest that a combination of these two basic forms of autonomy can provide a more holistic protection to all members of the minorities concerned. To begin with the non-territorial autonomy model, its proponents argue that it has additional benefits that allegedly make it a more attractive choice than the territorial one. First, as has been recognised by monitoring bodies (ACFC), intergovernmental committees (Venice Commission) and independent experts (OSCE Lund Recommendations),54 it may prove particularly useful for the maintenance and development of minority identities in situations where the territorial model is, for practical reasons, unable to do so, such as in the case of minorities dispersed over the State territory.55 An analogous argument has for similar reasons been made by some scholars for non-territorial minorities such as the Roma,56 as well as for several indigenous peoples who have been victims of alien and violent invasion that made them scattered minorities in their own ancestral lands.57 Second, it is claimed that it can offer viable compromises in cases of ethnically mixed areas over which more than one ethno-national group have 54. See respectively ACFC/31DOC(2008)001 (n 7), para 135; Venice Commission, A General Legal Reference Framework to Facilitate the Settlement of Ethno-Political Conflicts in Europe, adopted at the 44th Plenary Meeting (13–14 October 2000), CDL-INF(2000)16, Strasbourg, 3 November 2000, 8; ‘The Lund Recommendations … and Explanatory Note’ (n 40) 50, 60 (Chap III, para 17). 55. Henry J Steiner, ‘Ideals and Counter-Ideals in the Struggle Over Autonomy Regimes for Minorities’ (1991) 66 Notre Dame Law Review 1539–60, 1542. 56. See Illona Klimova-Alexander, ‘Transnational Romani and Indigenous Non-Territorial Self-Determination Claims’ in David J Smith and Karl Cordell (eds), Cultural Autonomy in Contemporary Europe (London and New York, Routledge, 2008) 59–80. 57. Ephraim Nimni, ‘Nationalist Multiculturalism in Late Imperial Austria as a Critique of Contemporary Liberalism: The Case of Bauer and Renner’ (1999) 4 Journal of Political Ideologies 289–314, 297. 14 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) ‘inherited’ competing claims, by granting a certain degree of non-territorial self-rule to all the ethno-national groups without assigning exclusive control over the contested common territory to any of them, thus avoiding interethnic frictions.58 Third, it guarantees enjoyment of the minority rights to all members of a minority, irrespective of where they live within the national territory, whereas the territorial model covers only those residing in a given region, leaving those who live dispersed across the rest of the country (‘minority diaspora’) outside its field of protection.59 Moreover, it enjoys stronger individual legitimacy, for it applies only to those members who voluntarily identify with the group for whose benefit it is established, whereas territorial autonomy applies to all inhabitants of a specific region regardless of their will, thus including those who are not members of the group or do not want to identify with it.60 Furthermore, it avoids the creation of ‘minorities within minorities’, since the members of the national majority population and of minorities other than the one which is regionally dominant (‘internal minorities’) will not find themselves in a vulnerable position in a particular region, as in the case of territorial autonomy.61 Lastly, non-territorial autonomy is supposed to pose a lesser danger for States’ territorial integrity – since it can satisfy the cultural needs of the minorities without compromising State sovereignty – than territorial autonomy, which is considered by many governments as a first step to secession,62 thus making the adoption of this model more pragmatic.63 For all 58. Asbjørn Eide, ‘Good Governance, Human Rights, and the Rights of Minorities and Indigenous Peoples’ in Hans-Oto Sano and Gudmundur Alfredsson with the collaboration of Robin Clapp (eds), Human Rights and Good Governance – Building Bridges (The Hague/London/New York, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2002) 47–71, 67. 59. David J Smith, ‘Minority Territorial and Non-Territorial Autonomy in Europe: Theoretical Perspectives and Practical Challenges’ in Zoltán Kántor (ed), Autonomies in Europe: Solutions and Challenges (Budapest, L’ Harmattan, 2009) 15–23, 18. 60. Ruth Lapidoth, ‘Autonomy: Potential and Limitations’ (1994) 1 International Journal on Group Rights 269–90, 282. 61. Athanasios Yupsanis, ‘Cultural Autonomy’ in Andreas Wiesand, Kalliopi Chainoglou, Anna Śledzińska-Simon with Yvonne Donders (eds), Culture and Human Rights: The Wroclaw Commentaries (Berlin/Boston, De Gruyter, Cologne, ARCult Media, 2016) 124–26, 125. 62. See Svante E Cornell, ‘Autonomy as a Source of Conflict: Caucasian Conflicts in Theoretical Perspective’ (2002) 54 World Politics 245–76, 246. 63. See Max van der Stoel, ‘Reflections on the Role of the OSCE High Commissioner on National Minorities as an Instrument of Conflict Prevention’ in Institute for Peace Research and Security Policy at the University of Hamburg and IFSH (eds), OSCE Yearbook 1999 (Baden-Baden, 2000) 381–91, 385–86. Autonomy for Minorities 15 these reasons, non-territorial/cultural autonomy is presented as ‘a promising alternative’64 to territorial autonomy. 3.2. Pro Territorial Autonomy Arguments Adherents of the territorial autonomy version, though agreeing that nonterritorial/cultural autonomy ‘may be the best on offer for dispersed and intermixed populations’65 as well as for the Roma and perhaps for some indigenous peoples,66 strongly doubt its adequacy to address the needs and claims of mobilised, sizeable, and territorially concentrated national minorities. First of all, they point out that confining non-territorial/cultural autonomy to the cultural sphere does not satisfy the demands of the kinds of minorities that, in addition to cultural rights, also want ‘to control local or regional governments, police forces, courts, economic and social welfare policies’.67 Also, they argue that while de-territorialising national minority identities seems more promising at first glance, it is largely unrealistic in the real world, where very often there is a deep link between national minorities and their territory, which is central to their self-understanding, histories and aspirations.68 This emotional attachment is unlikely to be satisfied by the non-territorial cultural approach, since these minorities ‘seek not simply self-government, but selfgovernment in and over their national homeland’.69 In addition, it is said that non-territorial/cultural autonomy regimes cannot guarantee the preservation of the minority language in the long term.70 As Bauböck emphasises, dispersed minority enclaves are not likely to survive 64. Aviel Roshwald, ‘Between Balkanization and Banalization: Dilemmas of Ethnocultural Diversity’ (2007) 3 Ethnopolitics 365–78, 373. 65. John McGarry and Margaret Moore, ‘Karl Renner, Power Sharing and Non-Territorial Autonomy’ in Ephraim Nimni (ed), National Cultural Autonomy and its Contemporary Critics (London and New York, Routledge [Taylor and Francis e-Library], 2005) 64–81, 86. 66. Will Kymlicka, ‘Renner and the Accommodation of Sub-State Nationalisms’ in Nimni, ibid 117–27, 125. 67. Rainer Bauböck, ‘Political Autonomy or Cultural Minority Rights? A Conceptual Critique of Renner’s Model’ in Nimni (n 65) 83–95, 88. 68. Will Kymlicka, ‘National Cultural Autonomy and International Minority Rights Norms’ (2007) 6 Ethnopolitics 379–93, 388. 69. Margaret Moore, ‘Sub-State Nationalism and International Law’ (2004) 25 Michigan Journal of International Law 1319–40, 1335. 70. Rainer Bauböck, ‘Multinational Federalism: Territorial or Cultural Autonomy?’, Willy Brandt Series of Working Papers in International Migration and Ethnic Relations, 2/01 (2001) 33 https://dspace.mah.se/bitstream/handle/2043/690/Workingpaper201.pdf; jsessionid=CDAE45DB7F0100B723B0E0752E9308A1?sequence=1. 16 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) linguistically even when their members have the right to establish and maintain educational institutions, if their language is not a useful resource in the larger environment.71 This is because, ‘a language may prosper best if it has a territorial statutory basis in which it is the primary medium of social and economic exchange and a principal medium for work, business and social interaction’.72 It is mainly for these reasons that most of the geographically compact national minorities opt for territorial autonomy much more than for non-territorial cultural autonomy. Furthermore, proponents of the territorial autonomy model claim that the suggestion inherent in the non-territorial/cultural autonomy scheme, ie that, by inevitably creating internal minorities, territorial settlements may produce ethnic tensions and lead to further oppression and reactionary secessionist demands, thus making the choice of cultural autonomy more attractive, has not been shown to be solid in practice. On the contrary, territorial arrangements have ‘arguably helped reduce the risks of violence, oppression and secession’, as several of the Western States that have adopted it would have faced much greater threats of ethnic mobilisation and destabilisation had they not accommodated the desire for territorial autonomy.73 From such perspectives, then, non-territorial cultural autonomy is best understood not as an alternative to the territorial model, but rather as a potential supplement to it as regards the case of territorially concentrated mobilised national minorities.74 3.3. Concluding Thoughts To conclude, it seems that territorial forms of self-government are more suitable for the needs of those minorities that are sizeable and live compactly in a specific area, while non-territorial settlements appear to serve better the interests of those minorities that are small and dispersed across a country.75 It should be noted, however, that the distinction between the two models 71. Bauböck (n 67) 88. 72. John McGarry and Brendan O’ Leary, ‘Territorial Pluralism: Taxinomizing its Forms, Virtues and Flaws’ in Carlo Basta, John McGarry and Richard Simeon (eds), Territorial Pluralism: Managing Difference in Multinational States (Vancouver/Toronto, UBC Press, 2015) 13–53, 33. 73. Kymlicka (n 66) 119. 74. Bauböck (n 67) 84; Kymlicka (n 66) 118. 75. Ferenc Kalmár (Rapporteur), The Situation and Rights of Traditional National Minorities in Europe, Report of the Committee on Equality and Non-Discrimination, Doc 13445, 24 March 2014, para 64. Autonomy for Minorities 17 does not mean that these are mutually exclusive or contradictory. Territorial autonomy regimes, for example, may recognise personality-based cultural rights to ‘internal minorities’ within their territory, as is the case with the national minority councils in the Autonomous Province of Vojvodina in Serbia.76 There are also settlements where territorial self-government is combined with non-territorial forms of cultural autonomy for members of the minority who live outside the autonomous region, such as the Francophones who live outside Quebec and the members of indigenous peoples who live outside their autonomous territory in Canada.77 These examples show that in practice territorial and non-territorial forms of autonomy can be complementary, providing for a more holistic protection for all members of the minority group or indigenous people concerned.78 4. Territorial and Non-Territorial Autonomy in International Law 4.1. Territorial Autonomy Norms in Non-Legally Binding Minority Instruments In several countries there exist both territorial and non-territorial/cultural autonomy regimes for minorities. Well-known instances of minority territorial autonomy include inter alia those of the German- and Ladin-speaking minorities of the Trentino-Alto Adige (South Tyrol) in Italy, the Swedishspeaking minority of the Åland Islands in Finland, the Gagauzian minority in Moldova, the Hungarian minority of Vojvodina in Serbia, etc.79 Examples of non-territorial/cultural arrangements include, but are not limited to, Estonia, the Russian Federation, Hungary and Slovenia.80 Most often their 76. José-María Arraiza, ‘The Management of Linguistic Diversity Through Territorial and Non-Territorial Autonomy’ (2015) 8 Europäisches Journal für Minderheitenfragen 7–33, 11. 77. Johanne Poirier, ‘Autonomy and Diversity’ in Ronald L Watts and Rupak Chattopadhyay (eds), Building on and Accommodating Diversities (New Delhi, Viva Books, 2008) 37–53, 51; Kymlicka (n 68) 385; Lapidoth (n 60) 281. 78. See José-María Arraiza, Making Home Rules for Mother Tongues – The Legal Implications of Linguistic Diversity in the Design of Autonomy Regimes (Åbo, Åbo Akademi University, 2015) 107. 79. See Thomas Benedikter, The World’s Modern Autonomy Systems: Concepts and Experiences of Regional Territorial Autonomy (Bolzano/Bozen, EURAC, 2009) 66–81 (for South Tyrol), 107–112 (for the Åland Islands), 122–29 (for the Gagauzia), 135 (for Vojvodina). 80. Yash Ghai, ‘Public Participation, Autonomy and Minorities’ in Skurbaty (n 27) 3–45, 41. 18 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) legal basis is domestic, since a right of minorities to autonomy in treaty and customary international law is at best under question.81 A careful reading of the major international and regional minority norms and instruments, such as Article 27 of the ICCPR, the relevant 1992 UN Declaration and the FCNM, clearly show that there is no explicit reference to autonomy, whether territorial, non-territorial/cultural, or in any other form.82 The very few and weakly worded specific references to (mostly territorial) autonomy are found exclusively in the minority texts of so-called ‘soft law’83 and occur in the first half of the 1990s, when the minority issue was at the top of the international (mainly European) community’s agenda. In this context, the first provision to refer expressis verbis to (territorial) autonomy for minorities is found in Chapter IV, paragraph 35.2, of the most far-reaching document of its time, the 1990 Copenhagen Document of the then Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe (CSCE), which states that: The Participating States note the efforts undertaken to protect and create conditions for the promotion of the ethnic, cultural, linguistic and religious identity of certain national minorities by establishing, as one of the possible means, appropriate local or autonomous administrations corresponding to the specific historical and territorial circumstances of such minorities and in accordance with the policies of the State concerned.84 This ‘rather ambiguous and somewhat confused’85 stipulation does not create legal obligations for the States, since the Copenhagen Document is not 81. JA Frowein and Roland Bank, The Participation of Minorities in Decision Making Processes, Expert Study submitted on Request of the Committee of Experts on Issues Relating to the Protection of National Minorities (DH-MIN) of the Council of Europe, DH-MIN(2000)1, November 2000, 18. 82. Regarding the observation that there is no explicit reference to autonomy in Art 27 ICCPR and the relevant UN Declaration, see Yousef T Jabareen, ‘Toward Participatory Equality: Protecting Minority Rights Under International Law’ (2008) 41 Israel Law Review 635–76, 672. Regarding the same observation for the FCNM see Alan Phillips, ‘Participation and the Council of Europe’s Framework Convention for the Protection of National Minorities (FCNM)’ in Skurbaty (n 27) 305–20, 305, 310. 83. See Steven Wheatley, ‘Deliberative Democracy and Minorities’ (2003) 14 European Journal of International Law 507–27, 522 (fn 98); Henrard (n 45) 141 (fn 48). 84. ‘Document of the Copenhagen Meeting of the Conference on the Human Dimension of the CSCE, 29 June 1990’ (1990) 11 Human Rights Law Journal 232–45, 243. See also Malcolm N Shaw, ‘Peoples, Territorialism and Boundaries’ (1997) 3 European Journal of International Law 478–507, 486. 85. Thomas Buergenthal, ‘The Copenhagen OSCE Meeting: A New Public Order for Europe’ (1990) 11 Human Rights Law Journal 217–32, 228. Autonomy for Minorities 19 legally binding.86 It certainly has moral and political force,87 which means that it ‘implies, and should give rise to, an internal legislative or administrative response’.88 Even in this case its ‘extremely feeble wording’,89 in conjunction with the excessive requirements for its fulfilment,90 which leave a wide margin of discretion to the States, make it sound more like a vague general recommendation for the adoption of best practice policies than a right.91 In the words of Pentassuglia, ‘it simply highlights a possibility, not a mandatory outcome’.92 A similar attitude towards (territorial) autonomy was manifested in the few subsequent CSCE/OSCE documents that refer explicitly to the concept. Thus, in the 1991 Geneva Report of experts on national minorities, the participating States just noted with interest (sic) that positive results have been obtained by some of them by inter alia ‘local autonomous administration, as well as autonomy on a territorial basis, including the existence of consultative, legislative and executive bodies chosen through free and periodic elections’.93 Also, in the 1999 Lund Recommendations, it is inter alia simply stated that ‘[a]ppropriate local, regional or autonomous administrations that correspond to the specific historical and territorial circumstances of national minorities may undertake a number of functions in order to respond more effectively to the concerns of these minorities’.94 In this respect, the Explanatory Note to the Recommendations adds that ‘[t]erritorial self-government can help preserve the unity of the States while increasing the level of participation and involvement of minorities by giving them a greater role in a level of government that reflects their geographic concentration’.95 As Packer 86. Janusz Symonides, ‘The Legal Nature of Commitments Relating to the Question of Minorities’ (1996) 3 International Journal on Group Rights 301–23, 322. 87. Arie Bloed, ‘Institutional Aspects of the Helsinki Process After the Follow-Up Meeting of Vienna’ (1989) 36 Netherlands International Law Review 342–63, 345. 88. Oscar Schachter, ‘The Twilight Existence of Nonbinding International Agreements’ (1977) 71 American Journal of International Law 296–304, 303. 89. Aristoteles Constantinides, ‘The Involvement of the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe in Issues of Minority Protection’ (1996) 9 Leiden Journal of International Law 373–95, 383. 90. Yoram Dinstein, ‘Autonomy Regimes and International Law’ (2011) 56 Villanova Law Review 437–53, 442. 91. John Packer, ‘Autonomy and the Effective Participation of Minorities in Public Life: Developments in the OSCE’ in Skurbaty (n 27) 321–35, 325. 92. Gaetano Pentassuglia, ‘The EU and the Protection of Minorities: The Case of Eastern Europe’ (2001) 12 European Journal of International Law 3–38, 5. 93. ‘Report of the CSCE Meeting of Experts on National Minorities, Geneva, 19 July 1991’ (1991) 12 Human Rights Law Journal 332–34, 333 (Chap IV). 94. ‘The Lund Recommendations … and Explanatory Note’ (n 40) 50, para 20. 95. The Lund Recommendations … and Explanatory Note’ (n 40) 60, para 19. 20 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) points out, the Lund Recommendations are just ‘recommendations [emphasis in the original] of independent experts and enjoy so far no official status in international relations’; but since they are the product of a team of internationally recognised experts acting independently and pro bono, they could be seen as an authoritative interpretation of the relevant international minority standards, serving as helpful reference points for policy and law makers.96 However, it should be emphasised, as Palermo indicates, that unlike all other fields covered by the Lund Recommendations, ‘virtually nothing has changed in regard to territorial autonomy in the OSCE region’. This means, he explains, that neither has a new territorial settlement been set up nor has much changed in the legislative framework of the existing autonomy regimes in Europe.97 A stronger statement on (territorial) autonomy came in 1993, in Article 11 of the PACE Recommendation 1201, which provided that: In the regions where they are in majority, the persons belonging to minorities shall have the right to have at their disposal appropriate local or autonomous authorities or to have a special status, matching their specific historical and territorial situation and in accordance with the domestic legislation of the state.98 As Kymlicka comments, this recommendation – which was also not legally binding – recognised territorial autonomy as a right and not merely as a best practice as the Copenhagen Document did; this reflects the high-water mark of support for territorial autonomy within European organisations, as since then there has been a marked movement away from it.99 Thus, while reference was made – albeit in a toothless way – to Article 11 in Hungary’s bilateral treaties with the Slovak Republic (1995) and Romania (1995),100 the 96. John Packer, ‘The Origin and Nature of the Lund Recommendations on the Effective Participation of National Minorities in Public Life’ (2000) 11 Helsinki Monitor 29–45, 41, 44. 97. Francesco Palermo, ‘When the Lund Recommendations Are Ignored. Effective Participation of National Minorities Through Territorial Autonomy’ (2009) 16 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 653–63, 654–55. 98. PACE, ‘Recommendation 1201 (1993) on an Additional Protocol on the Rights of National Minorities to the European Convention on Human Rights’ (1995) 16 Human Rights Law Journal 108–13, 112. 99. Will Kymlicka, ‘The Internationalization of Minority Rights’ (2008) 6 International Journal of Constitutional Law 1–32, 22–23. 100. For the treaty of Hungary with Slovakia, see Nicole VT Lugosi, ‘The Hungarian Minority Question in Slovakia and Romania’ (2011) Issue 2 Review of Applied Socio-Economic Research 111–20, 115; For the treaty with Romania, see Geoff Gilbert, ‘Autonomy and Minority Groups: A Right in International Law?’ (2001–2002) 35 Cornell International Law Journal 307–53, 323. Autonomy for Minorities 21 whole proposal of the Recommendation for an additional protocol to ECHR was finally abandoned by the Heads of State and Government of the CoE.101 Instead, priority was given to the adoption of the FCNM, which does not explicitly contain a right to autonomy, whether territorial or non-territorial. Indeed, the Venice Committee, which was requested by the Committee of Legal Affairs and Human Rights of the PACE to prepare an opinion on the interpretation of the Draft Protocol, with particular reference to Article 11, opined that, given the absence of an explicit reference to a right to autonomy in the FCNM and in the case law of the ECHR, ‘international law cannot in principle impose on States any territorial solutions to the problem of minorities and that States are not in principle required to introduce any forms of decentralization for minorities’.102 As the same Committee observed: States seem in fact to be afraid that the right to have appropriate local or autonomous administrations … may promote secessionist tendencies. Even those States which, while adhering to the principle of unitarity have granted a large degree of regional autonomy, hesitate to accept binding international instruments on the right of minorities to a certain autonomy.103 4.2. Non-Territorial Autonomy Provisions in Minority Texts The aforementioned situation does not differ even as regards the establishment of non-territorial/cultural autonomy arrangements, despite the fact that autonomy of dispersed minorities appears, in theory at least, less threatening to the integrity of the states than autonomy of territorially concentrated minorities.104 As Klebes points out, the State’s sensitivity with regard to autonomy in any form is very strong, and governments see even nonterritorial/cultural autonomy as a first step leading to administrative autonomy and finally to secession.105 Thus, explicit references to ‘non-territorial 101. Stephen Deets, ‘Reimagining the Boundaries of the Nation: Politics and Development of Ideas on Minority Rights’ (2006) 20 East European Politics and Societies 419–46, 435–37. 102. Opinion of the European Commission for Democracy Through Law on the Interpretation of Article 11 of the Draft Protocol to the European Convention on Human Rights Appended to Recommendation 1201 of the Parliamentary Assembly, CDLMIN(1996)004e-rev-restr, Strasbourg, 11 March 1996, para 2 (b). 103. Ibid, para 2 (c); See also Gaetano Pentassuglia, ‘State Sovereignty, Minorities and Self-Determination: A Comprehensive Legal View’ (2002) 9 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 303–24, 321–22. 104. William Safran, ‘Spatial and Functional Dimensions of Autonomy: Cross-National and Theoretical Perspectives’ (1999) 5 Nationalism and Ethnic Politics 11–34, 11. 105. Heinrich Klebes, ‘The Council of Europe’s Framework Convention for the Protection of National Minorities’ (1995) 16 Human Rights Law Journal 92–98, 96. 22 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) arrangements’ (in the wording of the CSCE/OSCE documents)/‘cultural autonomy’ (in the phrasing of the CoE texts) are also rare. Starting, then, chronologically with the 1991 CSCE Geneva Report, the participating States noted with interest that positive results had been obtained by some of them by, inter alia, ‘self-administration by a national minority of aspects concerning its identity in situations where autonomy on a territorial basis does not apply’.106 Further, the Lund Recommendations declare that ‘[n]on-territorial forms of governance are useful for the maintenance and development of the identity and culture of national minorities’.107 In the same spirit the UN’s informative pamphlet on minority rights of the Human Rights Office of the High Commissioner states that ‘[t]he promotion of [minority] rights, identity and culture can be strengthened through the introduction and promotion of certain forms of self-governance, including … cultural autonomy’.108 Finally, in the ACFC’s Commentary on effective minority participation, the Committee simply comments, with regard to the cultural autonomies that exist in some States Parties, that ‘these are granted collectively to members of a particular national minority, regardless of a territory’ aiming inter alia ‘to delegate to national minority organizations important competencies in the area of minority culture, language and education and can, in this regard, contribute to the preservation and development of minority cultures’109 as well as ‘in increased participation of minorities in cultural life’110 and in public affairs.111 As Osipov observes, all the references to non-territorial autonomy in the CSCE/OSCE and the CoE documents [besides not being legally binding] are broad in nature and vague as to their interpretation, creating – instead of answering – questions regarding the beneficiaries and the content of autonomy.112 4.3. Concluding Observations Given, then, the absence of an explicit right for minorities to either territorial or non-territorial/cultural autonomy in the international and 106. ‘Report of the CSCE Meeting’ (n 93) 333 (Chap IV); See Jane Wright, ‘Minority Groups, Autonomy, and Self-Determination’ (1999) 19 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 605–29, 621–22. 107. See ‘The Lund Recommendations … and Explanatory Note’ (n 40) 50, para 17. 108. UN Human Rights Office of the High Commissioner, Minority Rights: International Standards and Guidance for Implementation, HR/PUB/10/3, New York and Geneva, 2010, 41. 109. ACFC/31DOC(2008)001 (n 7), para 135. 110. ACFC/31DOC(2008)001 (n 7), para 67. 111. ACFC/31DOC(2008)001 (n 7), para 72. 112. Alexander Osipov, ‘Non-Territorial Autonomy and International Law’ (2011) 13 International Community Law Review 393–411, 400. Autonomy for Minorities 23 regional minority texts, the dominant position in legal theory is that minorities do not enjoy a positive right of territorial or non-territorial/cultural autonomy in public international law.113 As Thornberry puts it, ‘[a]utonomy is seen as a grant, not a right’.114 In this light the legal basis for the creation of autonomy regimes rests primarily, if not exclusively, on the ad hoc arrangements of the national legislations.115 Establishing a right to autonomy for minorities in international law is, then, necessary, so that its existence, weakening or abolition will not depend exclusively on national legislation, as was the case for example in Kosovo under the Milosevic regime. Such a development would give them a better bargaining position to negotiate their rights within the States’ borders. After all, international law is not static but continually evolves, responding to the times and to peoples’ needs, as the case of indigenous peoples indicates, so that one should not a priori preclude the gradual recognition of such a right to minorities under the argumentation explored below. 5. Possible Modes of Recognition of a Minority Right to Autonomy in International Law 5.1. Preliminary Remarks Although the current reality in public international law regarding the (non-) existence of a right of minorities to autonomy stands as described above, there exist some avenues on which minorities could work in order to reverse this situation, namely a) through the claiming of their peoplehood, b) via invoking an analogical implementation of the relevant provisions of the UNDRIP, and c) by asking for a dynamic interpretation of their participatory rights. Achieving the recognition of a right to autonomy in international law is crucial because it would offer them a permanent and more secure basis 113. Zelim A Skurbaty, ‘Introduction’ in Skurbaty (n 27) xxxi–Iviii, xxxvii, xIiii; Roberta Medda-Windischer, ‘New Minorities, Old Instruments? A Common but Differentiated System of Minority Protection’ (2011) 13 International Community Law Review 361–91 376, 379; Palermo(n 97) 656–57; Dinstein (n 90) 438–42; Shaw (n 84) 488–89; Wheatley (n 83) 522; Packer (n 91) 329; Pentassuglia (n 103) 320–21; Loukacheva (n 30) 5; Heintze (n 41) 329; Henrard (n 45) 141. For a different view, arguing that territorially concentrated minorities may perhaps have a right to autonomy within the existing state structures, see Douglas Sanders, ‘Is Autonomy a Principle of International Law?’ (1986) 55 Nordic Journal of International Law 17–21, 17. 114. Patrick Thornberry, ‘Images of Autonomy and Individual and Collective Rights in International Instruments on the Rights of Minorities’ in Suksi (n 29) 97–124, 123. 115. Zelim A Skurbaty, ‘Is There an Emerging Right to Autonomy? Summary Reflections, Conclusions and Recommendations’ in Skurbaty (n 27) 565–68, 565. 24 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) for deciding on their own issues, fulfilling their rights and promoting their identity.116 The present situation, where such a grant depends exclusively on the goodwill of the States, meaning that it is an entirely internal national matter subject to States’ discretionary power, is unsatisfactory. Even the strongest constitutional stipulations can be altered or repealed and the most progressive governments can change their policies or lose power to more conservative and anti-minorities ones.117 An international law guarantee can certainly provide better protection against the weakening or abolition of an autonomous regime against the will of the minority concerned.118 It is essential, then, to examine how such a development could possibly take place. It should be noted a priori that all three options offered to minorities for seeking recognition of a right to autonomy in international law are hard to realise in the near future due to strong State reluctance to such a development. However, as Hilpold rightly observes, ‘what presently appears as illusionary and utopian can become a hard fact in reality in the next future’.119 5.2. Claiming Autonomy through Peoplehood The first path by which minorities could achieve a right to autonomy is by asserting their peoplehood. Under current international law only ‘peoples’,120 and more specifically ‘peoples under colonial domination’, ‘peoples subject to alien occupation’, and ‘peoples under racist regimes’, have a right to selfdetermination.121 To these categories the recent UNDRIP added ‘indigenous peoples’ as bearers of a right to ‘internal self-determination’ (autonomy).122 116. Frederik Harhoff, ‘Institutions of Autonomy’ (1986) 55 Nordic Journal of International Law 31–40, 39–40. 117. Athanasios Yupsanis, ‘ILO Convention No. 169 Concerning Indigenous and Tribal Peoples in Independent Countries 1989-2009: An Overview’ (2010) 79 Nordic Journal of International Law 433–56, 449. 118. Markku Suksi, ‘Keeping the Lid on the Secession Kettle – A Review of Legal Interpretations Concerning Claims of Self- Determination by Minority Populations’ (2005) 12 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 189–226, 200. 119. Peter Hilpold, ‘Self-Determination and Autonomy: Between Secession and Internal SelfDetermination’ (2017) 24 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 302–35, 334–35. 120. Gudmundur Alfredsson, ‘The Faroese People as a Subject of International Law’ (2001) 1 Faroese Law Review 45–57, 48. 121. Jean Salmon, ‘Internal Aspects of the Right to Self-Determination: Towards A Democratic Legitimacy Principle?’ in Christian Tomuschat (ed), Modern Law of Self-Determination (Dordrecht/Boston/London, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1993) 253–82, 256. 122. Timo Koivurova and Adam Stepien, ‘How International Law Has Influenced the National Policy and Law Related to Indigenous Peoples in the Arctic’ (2011) 19 Waikato Law Review 123–43, 128. Autonomy for Minorities 25 ‘Minorities’ are not considered ‘peoples’123 for the purpose of international law and consequently do not enjoy that right.124 The problem is that there is no generally accepted official definition of the terms ‘peoples’,125 ‘indigenous peoples’126 and ‘minority’127 in international law. The issue is a very important one, since each designation carries different legal consequences. The ‘peoples’ who have a right to self-determination in international law have been defined at different times and according to different interests and needs in significantly different ways. In the Wilsonian era such peoples were identified with the ‘nations’ as ethno-national communities (‘ethnic self-determination’), whereas in the decolonisation era the right to selfdetermination was recognised to colonial peoples defined not in ethnic but in territorial terms (‘territorial self-determination’).128 It was the entire colonial population conceived as a single entity, and not each separate ethnic group living within a colonial territory, that had the right to self-determination (‘one people per colony’).129 The exercise of this right could result, according to the 1541/1960 Resolution of the UN General Assembly, in the following outcomes: a) establishment of a sovereign and independent State, b) free association with an independent State, and c) integration with an independent State.130 To these options the 1970 UN Declaration on Friendly Relations131 123. See Aureliu Critescu, The Right to Self-Determination – Historical and Current Development on the Basis of United Nations Instruments, UN Doc E/CN.4/Sub.2/404/Rev.1 (New York, United Nations Publications, 1981), para 279. 124. Jure Vidmar, ‘International Legal Responses to Kosovo’s Declaration of Independence’ (2009) 42 Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 779–851, 809. 125. See James Crawford, ‘The Rights of Peoples: Some Conclusions’ in James Crawford (ed), The Rights of Peoples (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1988) 159–75, 168–70. 126. See Abdullah Al Faruque and Najnin Begum, ‘Conceptualising Indigenous Peoples’ Rights: An Emerging New Category of Third-Generation Rights’ (2004) 2 Asia-Pacific Journal on Human Rights and the Law 1–29, 3–6. 127. See Abdulrahim P Vijapur, ‘International Protection of Minority Rights’ (2006) 43 International Studies 367–94, 370–72. 128. Susanna Mancini, ‘Rethinking the Boundaries of Democratic Secession: Liberalism, Nationalism, and the Right of Minorities to Self-Determination’ (2008) 6 International Journal of Constitutional Law 553–84, 555–56. 129. Ulrike Barten, ‘What’s In a Name? Peoples, Minorities, Indigenous Peoples, Tribal Peoples and Nations’ (2015) 14 Journal on Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe 1–25, 3. 130. See Principles Which Should Guide Members in Determining Whether or not an Obligation Exists to Transmit the Information Called for under Article 73 c of the Charter, UN Doc A/RES/15/1541 (15 December 1960) Annex, Principle VI. 131. See Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation Among States in Accordance with the Charter of the United Nations, UN Doc A/RES/25/2625 (24 October 1970) Principle 5.4. 26 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) added the choice of any other political status freely decided.132 The fourth alternative could certainly lead, as Suksi notes, to ‘a “middle ground” between independence on the one hand and integration on the other’,133 that is, to various forms of autonomy. However, despite the fact that the relevant texts provided for several modes of implementation of the right, the UN practice largely equated the right of self-determination with independence (the so-called ‘external self-determination’) by showing a preference for the first option for almost all former colonial territories.134 Beyond the decolonisation context, the right to self-determination was recognised first and foremost to the inhabitants of the existing independent states as a whole.135 In essence this perception arbitrarily equated the ‘people’ with the state as spokesman of the entire population.136 This meant that sub-state ethnic groups such as minorities were not recognised separately as holders of the right to their own self-determination.137 With the end of decolonisation and the granting of independence to almost all former colonies, several scholars pointed out that in order for the right to continue to have some substance it should be interpreted as the right of a people to freely choose its form of governance through a democratic process138 ‘within the framework of existing sovereign states and consistently with the maintenance of the territorial integrity of those states’139 (the so-called ‘internal self-determination’). This distinction, which partially echoes the aforementioned fourth choice given for the exercise of self-determination by the 132. Jens Elo Rytter, ‘Self-Determination of Colonial Peoples – The Case of Greenland Revisited’ (2008) 77 Nordic Journal of International Law 365–400, 367. 133. Suksi (n 118) 195–96, 209, 225. 134. Kavus Abushov, ‘Autonomy as a Possible Solution to Self-Determination Disputes: Does it Really Work?’ (2015) 22 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 182–201, 185. 135. Simone F van den Driest, ‘Crimea’s Separation from Ukraine: An Analysis of the Right to Self-Determination and (Remedial) Secession in International Law’ (2015) 62 Netherlands International Law Review 329–63, 338. 136. See David Makinson, ‘Rights of Peoples: Point of View of a Logician’ in Crawford, The Rights of Peoples (n 125) 69–92, 73. 137. Tina Kempin Reuter, ‘The Right to Self-Determination of Ethnic Groups: The Canton of Jura in Switzerland’ (2016) 23 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 250–69, 251. 138. Surendra Bhandari, ‘From External to the Internal Application of the Right to SelfDetermination: The Case of Nepal’ (2014) 21 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 330–70, 350–51. 139. Zoilo A Velasco, ‘Self-Determination and Secession: Human Rights-Based Conflict Resolution’ (2014) 16 International Community Law Review 75–105, 82. Autonomy for Minorities 27 1970 UN Declaration on Friendly Relations, has found great acceptance in legal theory and has been adopted by some human rights bodies.140 For example, in the Katangese Peoples’ Congress v Zaire case, where Mr Gerard Moke, President of the Katangese Peoples’ Congress, speaking as representative of the Katangese, who constitute part of the Zaireoise people, invoked violation of Article 20 para 1 of the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights (ACHPR) on the right of peoples to self-determination, the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights (AComHPR) stated that: self-determination may be exercised in any of the following ways independence, selfgovernment, local government, federalism, confederalism, unitarism or any other form of relations that accords with the wishes of the people but fully cognizant of other recognized principles such as sovereignty and territorial integrity.141 In this context, it has been suggested that minority claims to autonomy might be brought as part of the ‘internal’ right to self-determination.142 In order for such a suggestion to gain a solid legal basis, it would first have to be accepted that the term ‘people’ should not be equated with a States’ population and thus with the State itself, since the majority of States are in reality multinational. As Crawford has emphasised ‘[i]f the phrase “rights of peoples” has any independent meaning, it must confer rights on peoples against their own governments’.143 A meaningful contribution in this direction came in the late 1990s from the Constitutional Court of Canada. In the case of Reference re Secession of Quebec regarding the right of the legislature or the Government of Quebec to effect the secession of Quebec from Canada unilaterally, the Constitutional 140. See Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination, General Recommendation No 21, Right to Self-Determination, 23/08/1996, para 4, contained in Report of the CERD – Fifty First Session, UN Doc A/51/18, Supplement No 18. 141. Katangese Peoples’ Congress v Zaire, Communication No 75/92, African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights (1995), para 4; See Mtendeweka Owen Mhango, ‘Recognizing a Right to Autonomy for Ethnic Groups Under the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights: Katangese Peoples Congress v. Zaire’ (2007) 14 Human Rights Brief 11–15, 12. 142. Miodrag A Jovanović, ‘Territorial Autonomy in Eastern Europe – Legacies of the Past’ (2002) Issue 4 Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe 1–16, 4. 143. James Crawford, ‘The Rights of Peoples: “Peoples” or “Governments”?’ in Crawford, The Rights of Peoples (n 125) 55–67, 56. 28 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) Court of Canada, after noting that the precise meaning of the term ‘people’ remains somewhat uncertain, opined that: It is clear that ‘a people’ may include only a portion of the population of an existing state. The right to self-determination has developed largely as a human right and is generally used in documents that simultaneously contain references to ‘nation’ and ‘state’. The juxtaposition of these terms is indicative that the reference to ‘people’ does not necessarily mean the entirety of a state’s population.144 This judgment is not legally binding in international law but can be used, according to Article 38 para 1 (d) of the International Court of Justice’s Statute, as a subsidiary means for the determination of its rules of law, and has also had great influence on legal theory. It makes perfectly clear that a ‘people’ does not have to coincide with the whole population of an existing State, but there can be several peoples in one State.145 The next step, then, is to see whether minorities can be considered ‘a people’ constituting part of the whole population of a State. Here the semijurisprudence of the AComHPR proves to be particularly helpful. In a series of cases brought before it regarding inter alia violations of Article 20 of the ACHPR on the right to self-determination, the Commission relied explicitly for guidance on the definition of the term ‘people’ given by the international meeting of experts held by the United Nations Economic, Social and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) in 1989. According to them, a ‘people’ is a group of individual human beings who share some or all of the following characteristics: a) a common historical tradition, b) racial or ethnic identity, c) cultural homogeneity, d) linguistic unity, e) religious or ideological affinity, f ) territorial connection, and g) common economic life.146 Adopting this approach the AComHPR has found in the Kevin Mgwanga Gunme v Cameroon case, considering the violation of inter alia Article 20 of the ACHPR concerning the right to self-determination of the anglophone Southern Cameroonians within the francophone Republic of Cameroon, that the Southern Cameroonians constitute a ‘people’ based on their numerous characteristics, ‘which include a common history, linguistic tradition, 144. Reference re Secession of Quebec [1998] 2 SCR 217, para 124; See Peter Radan, ‘Constitutional Law and Secession: The Case of Quebec’ (1998) 2 Macarthur Law Review 69–85, 76. 145. Timo Koivurova, ‘Sovereign States and Self-Determining Peoples: Carving Out a Place for Transnational Indigenous Peoples in a World of Sovereign States’ (2010) 12 International Community Law Review 191–212, 198. 146. International Meeting of Experts on Further Study of the Concept of the Rights of Peoples, UNESCO, Paris, 27–30 November 1989, SHS – 89/CONF.602/7, Paris, 22 February 1990,7–8. Autonomy for Minorities 29 territorial connection and political outlook’ as well as a self-perception as a people with a separate and distinct identity.147 The Commission made its position even clearer in the Sudan Human Rights Organization v Sudan and Center on Housing Rights and Evictions v Sudan cases, opining that: An important aspect of this process of defining ‘a people’ is the characteristics, which a particular people may use to identify themselves, through the principle of self identification, or be used by other people to identify them. These characteristics, include the language, religion, culture, the territory they occupy in a state, common history, ethno-anthropological factors, to mention but a few. In States with mixed racial composition, race becomes a determinant of groups of ‘peoples’, just as ethnic identity can also be a factor. In some cases groups of ‘a people’ might be a majority or a minority in a particular State.148 The Commission has, therefore, embraced a very broad understanding of the term ‘people’, which could certainly cover indigenous and tribal peoples, minorities, descendants of the European colonial settlers, Asian immigrant communities and nomadic societies.149 Although in a more global context there is reluctance to adopt such a broad conception of the term ‘peoples’, the AComHPR’s semi-jurisdiction could gradually contribute to further development of the right to internal self-determination.150 Especially as regards the case of minorities, this reading enhances the position of those scholars who strongly and convincingly argue that minorities undoubtedly fulfill the subjective and objective criteria of peoplehood in its ethnic sense (self-perception, common history, language, culture and historical presence in a specific territory) and should accordingly be recognised as peoples in international law.151 The UN, however, has yet to adopt such an approach. The quasi-judicial body most competent, according to Article 40 of the ICCPR and Article 1 147. Kevin Mgwanga Gunme v Cameroon, Communication No 266/2003, African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights, paras 170, 179; See Simon M Weldehaimanot, ‘The ACHPR in the Case of the Southern Cameroons’ (2012) 9 SUR – International Journal on Human Rights 85–107, 90–91. 148. Sudan Human Rights Organization v Sudan, Communication No 279/2003 and Center on Housing Rights and Evictions v Sudan, Communication No 269/05, African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights, para 220. 149. Dinah Shelton, ‘Self-Determination in Regional Human Rights Law: From Kosovo to Cameroon’ (2011) 105 American Journal of International Law 60–81, 69. 150. Kalana Senaratne, ‘Internal Self-Determination in International Law: A Critical Third World Perspective’ (2013) 3 Asian Journal of International Law 305–39, 321. 151. Felix Ermacora, ‘The Protection of Minorities Before the UN’ (1983, IV) 182 Recueil des Cours 247–370, 327; Nirmala Chandrahasan, ‘Minorities, Autonomy and the Intervention of Third States’ (1993) 23 Israel Yearbook on Human Rights 129–45, 135. 30 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) of its Optional Protocol, to interpret Article 1 of the Covenant on the right to self-determination, the Human Rights Committee (HRC), has so far declined to clearly recognise minorities as peoples with a right to internal self-determination. Specifically, the HRC has carefully avoided, in its semijuridical jurisprudence, determining whether an indigenous people, such as the Lubicon Band of Canada, or a minority, such as the ethnic-German population living in South Tyrol, constitute ‘peoples’ within the meaning of Article 1 of the Covenant.152 Indeed, the Committee initially appeared to sustain the differentiation between peoples and minorities by stating in its 1994 General Comment No 23 that ‘[t]he Covenant draws a distinction between the right to self-determination and the rights protected under Article 27. The former expresses a right belonging to peoples … Article 27, on the other hand, relates to rights conferred on individuals as such’.153 Later, though, the Committee seemed to recognise [albeit in cases concerning indigenous peoples and not sensu stricto minorities] a certain interaction between Articles 1 and 27 of the Covenant,154 by stating that ‘the provisions of article 1 may be relevant in the interpretation of other rights protected by the Covenant, in particular article 27’.155 However, in its latest relevant decision, the Committee omitted to make such a connection, recalling instead its constant adherence to the principle that ‘the Optional Protocol provides a procedure under which individuals can claim that their individual rights have been violated, but that these rights do not include those set out in article 1 of the Covenant’.156 Thus, ‘in the case of minorities, even “internal” self-determination is open to question’.157 152. See respectively Chief Bernard Ominayak and the Lubicon Lake Band v Canada, Communication No 167/1984, Human Rights Committee, UN Doc CCPR/C/38/167/1984 (1990) para 32.1; A.B. et. al. v Italy, Communication No 413/1990, Human Rights Committee, UN Doc CCPR/C/40/413/1990 (1990) para 3.2. 153. Human Rights Committee, General Comment No 23: The Rights of Minorities (Art. 27), UN Doc CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.5 (08/04/1994) para 3.1. See Frances Radey, ‘Self-Determination and Minority Rights’ (2002) 26 Fordham International Law Journal 453–99, 459. 154. See Gaetano Pentassuglia, ‘Indigenous Groups and the Developing Jurisprudence of the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights: Some Reflections’ (2010) 3 UCL Human Rights Review 150–63, 155. 155. Apirana Mahuika et al v New Zealand, Communication No 547/1993, Human Rights Committee, UN Doc CCPR/C/70/547/1993 (2000), para 9.2. 156. Angela Poma Poma v Peru, Communication No 1457/2006, Human Rights Committee, UN Doc CCPR/C/95/D/1457/2006 (2009), para 6.3. 157. Joshua Castellino and Jeremie Gilbert, ‘Self-Determination, Indigenous Peoples and Minorities’ (2003) 3 Macquarie Law Journal 155–78, 161. Autonomy for Minorities 31 While, then, at present it seems highly unlikely that minorities will be recognised as peoples proper in international law, one should not forget that this was also true for indigenous peoples some years ago.158 Due to governments’ resistance, for example, to the designation of indigenous nations as ‘peoples’, it was only possible to employ the term in the legally binding ILO Convention No 169 under the compromised disclaimer of Article 1 para 3, clarifying that ‘its use shall not be construed as having any implications as regards as the rights which may attach to the term under international law’.159 Also, during the drafting process of the UNDRIP, several States were vehemently opposed to the use of the concept ‘peoples’ in the text, proposing instead terms such as ‘indigenous populations’ and ‘persons belonging to indigenous groups’.160 Even well-established democracies with high human rights profiles such as Canada and Sweden refused to accept the Indian and Sami groups on their territories as ‘peoples’ with a right to self-determination under Article 1 of the ICCPR.161 In fact, until the adoption of the 2007 Declaration it was heavily disputed whether indigenous nations could be classified as ‘peoples’ under international law.162 It was the advocacy of indigenous peoples that brought about the desired result, not the goodwill of the States.163 Minorities could press, as indigenous peoples did, for the revision of the arbitrary distinction between ‘peoples’, as the entire population of sovereign States, which possess the right to self-determination, and ‘minorities’, which do not.164 158. Brad R Roth, ‘Secessions, Coups and the International Rule of Law: Assessing the Decline of the Effective Control Doctrine’ (2010) 11 Melbourne Journal of International Law 11–48, 14. 159. Asbjørn Eide, ‘International Cooperation for Group Accommodation Through Minority Protection: A Review of Standard Setting and Institution Building at Regional and Global Levels’ (2006) 13 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 153–70, 162. 160. Linzhu Wang, ‘The Definition of Indigenous Peoples and its Applicability in China’ (2015) 22 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 232–58, 240. 161. Erica-Irene Daes, ‘The UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples: Background and Appraisal’ in Stephen Allen and Alexandra Xanthaki (eds), Reflections of the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (Portland, Hart Publishing, 2011) 11–40, 27. 162. Katja Göcke, ‘The Case of Angela Poma Poma v. Peru before the Human Rights Committee – The Concept of Free Prior and Informed Consent and the Application of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights to the Protection and Promotion of Indigenous Peoples’ Rights’ (2010) 14 Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law 337–70, 350. 163. Julian Burger, ‘The UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples: From Advocacy to Implementation’ in Allen and Xanthaki (n 161) 41–59, 42. 164. Stephen Allen, ‘Recreating ‘One China’: Internal Self-Determination, Autonomy and the Future of Taiwan’ (2003) 1 Asia-Pacific Journal on Human Rights and the Law 21–51, 31. 32 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) In this effort minorities should bear in mind that indigenous peoples gained recognition of their peoplehood by the international community not because they are culturally and physically ‘endangered peoples’ or because they are formerly sovereign ‘first nations’ who have been wrongfully deprived of their sovereignty and were victims of major historical injustices, although such arguments have a certain moral gravity, but because they constitute a non-significant threat for States’ territorial integrity and sovereignty. As Daes has noted, they are vulnerable, are mostly small and with limited resources,165 and most importantly they usually do not have ‘kin states’.166 Many ‘kin states’ to minorities act provocatively, trying to use them in an inappropriate way that violates the rule of non-intervention in the internal affairs of other States.167 This intrusive attitude makes host States suspicious towards their minorities because of fears for their national unity and stability.168 Minorities then have to offer clear and absolute guarantees towards their host States against any improper intervention from their ‘kin states’, on the one hand denying any role that would destabilise the internal order of their host States and on the other acting as a bridge of friendship between the two. This is an essential prerequisite in order for States to positively reconsider their attitude towards the recognition of minorities as peoples entitled to internal self-determination (autonomy). 5.3. Minority Autonomy via an Analogical Use of the UNDRIP After two and a half decades of heated discussions and contested deliberations in the UN, indigenous peoples have succeeded in gaining recognition of their right to autonomy. Specifically, as Article 4 of the relevant 2007 UN Declaration proclaims: ‘[i]ndigenous peoples, in exercising their right to self-determination, have the right to autonomy or self-government in matters relating to their internal and local affairs, as well as ways and means for financing their autonomous functions’.169 Although the Declaration carries 165. Erica-Irene A Daes, ‘An Overview of the History of Indigenous Peoples: SelfDetermination and the United Nations’ (2008) 21 Cambridge Review of International Affairs 7–26, 24. 166. Miriam J Aukerman, ‘Definitions and Justifications: Minority and Indigenous Rights in a Central/East European Context’ (2000) 22 Human Rights Quarterly 1011–50, 1045. 167. See Sia Spiliopoulou Åkermark, ‘Internal Self-Determination and the Role of Territorial Autonomy as a Tool for the Resolution of Ethno-Political Disputes’ (2013) 20 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 5–25, 22. 168. Gillian Triggs, ‘The Rights of “Peoples” and Individual Rights: Conflict or Harmony?’ in Crawford The Rights of Peoples (n 125) 141–57, 146. 169. UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, UN Doc A/RES/61/295, Annex, 13 September 2007. See Fabiana de Oliveira Godinho, ‘The United Nations Declaration Autonomy for Minorities 33 legal significance for the development of customary international law,170 it is not a legally binding instrument and therefore imposes no legal obligations upon States.171 Conversely, it has been argued by Wiessner, based on a widespread study of state practice combined with the necessary opinio juris, that indigenous peoples’ right to autonomy has achieved the status of customary international law.172 Consequently, according to this approach, the Declaration reflects pre-existing customary international law as regards this specific right.173 A more modest position implies that indigenous peoples’ right to autonomy is emerging but is not yet crystallised.174 In this regard, Xanthaki has claimed that to view ‘the Declaration or substantial parts of it [and indeed that of autonomy one may say] as customary international law may be rather premature’.175 This view does not dismiss the specific Declaration or the ‘soft’ law instruments in general as non-law, nor overlooks the growing importance of non-binding instruments in the international legal system,176 but addresses indigenous peoples’ right to autonomy as an issue that clearly requires further debate and clarification.177 on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples and the Protection of Indigenous Rights in Brazil’ (2008) 12 Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law 247–86, 257–58. 170. Timo Koivurova, ‘From High Hopes to Disillusionment: Indigenous Peoples’ Struggle to (re)Gain Their Right to Self- Determination’ (2008) 15 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 1–26, 3. 171. Bradford W Morse, ‘Indigenous Peoples and Water Rights: Does the United Nations’ Adoption of the Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples Help?’ (2010) 20 Journal of Water Law 254–67, 255; Shaw (n 84) 488. 172. See Siegfried Wiessner, ‘Rights and Status of Indigenous Peoples: A Global Comparative and International Legal Analysis’ (1999) 12 Harvard Human Rights Journal 57–128, 127. 173. See Marc Weller, ‘Settling Self-Determination Conflicts: Recent Developments’ (2009) 20 European Journal of International Law 111–65, 116–17, who seems to imply such a position. See also Siegfried Wiessner, ‘The Cultural Rights of Indigenous Peoples: Achievements and Continuing Challenges’ (2011) 22 European Journal of International Law 121–40, 135–136 (fn 85). 174. See Heather A Northcott, ‘Realisation of the Right of Indigenous Peoples to Natural Resources Under International Law Through the Emerging Right to Autonomy’ (2012) 16 The International Journal of Human Rights 73–99. 175. Alexandra Xanthaki, ‘Indigenous Rights in International Law Over the Last 10 Years and Future Developments’ (2009) 10 Melbourne Journal of International Law 27–37, 36. 176. See Mauro Barelli, ‘The Role of Soft Law in the International Legal System: The Case of the United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples’ (2009) 58 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 957–83, 959–60. 177. Steven C Roach, ‘Minority Rights and an Emergent International Right to Autonomy: A Historical and Normative Assessment’ (2004) 11 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 411–32, 429. See also Osipov (n 112) 402; Loukacheva (n 30) 14. 34 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) The recognition of a right to internal self-determination (autonomy) for indigenous peoples in the UNDRIP has been hailed, notwithstanding its vagueness, as ‘the most important advance in the law of self-determination’ since the adoption of the common Article 1 of the ICCPR and ICESCR.178 Indeed, it is the first international legal text, even of a ‘soft law’ nature, to explicitly extend the right to internal self-determination to a sub-national group.179 This development may have major implications for the scope of the right to self-determination, empowering the autonomy claims of other sub-national groups, such as minorities.180 There are certainly good arguments to support this case, since besides their differences several commonalities between the two population categories exist, as analysed below. Starting adversely with the current legal reality, one can note that although in almost all situations indigenous peoples constitute minorities within the States where they live,181 Bolivia and Guatemala being the two best known exceptions to that rule, contemporary international law treats the two groups separately and accords them different sets of legal protection.182 Thus, beyond the recognition of a right to internal self-determination (autonomy) to indigenous peoples only, international law also accords them a series of rights whose nature and content differ considerably from those of minorities, establishing a stronger status for the former.183 Specifically, indigenous instruments are typically worded in the form ‘indigenous peoples have’, meaning that the rights accorded are collective, whereas minority texts recognise rights mainly, if not exclusively, to ‘persons belonging to minorities’, that is they are individual rights.184 This emphasis on collective rights 178. Robert T Coulter, ‘The U.N. Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples: A Historic Change in International Law’ (2008–2009) 45 Idaho Law Review 539–53, 548. 179. Mauro Barelli, ‘Shaping Indigenous Self-Determination: Promising or Unsatisfactory Solutions?’ (2011) 13 International Community Law Review 413–36, 422. 180. Stephen Allen, ‘The Consequences of Modernity for Indigenous Peoples: An International Appraisal’ (2006) 13 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 315–40, 335–36. 181. Alessandro Fodella, ‘International Law and the Diversity of Indigenous Peoples’ (2006) 30 Vermont Law Review 565–94, 572. 182. Yousef T Jabareen, ‘Redefining Minority Rights: Successes and Shortcomings of the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples’ (2011) 18 UC Davis Journal of International Law and Policy 119–61, 125. 183. Dieter Kugelman, ‘The Protection of Minorities and Indigenous Peoples Respecting Cultural Diversity’ (2007) 11 Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law 233–63, 236. 184. Patrick Thornberry, Cultural Rights and Universality of Human Rights, Day of General Discussion, Right to Take Part in Cultural Life (article 15 (1) (a) of the Covenant, UN Doc E/C.12/40/15 (9 May 2008) 9. Autonomy for Minorities 35 corresponds to indigenous societal needs and structures, which are centered on the community rather than the individual. It is the community, for example, that holds rights to the lands,185 traditional knowledge,186 etc. Second, rights to land and natural resources are core elements of the ILO Convention No 169 and the UNDRIP, while minority provisions contain no such rights.187 This differentiation is due to the fact that land rights are crucial for the cultural and physical survival of indigenous societies, because they rely upon their lands to provide them with the natural resources that are necessary for their subsistence and because they are also spiritually tied to their ancestral territories.188 Third, indigenous norms aim at providing an environment in which indigenous peoples shall have the right to preserve their communities outside the dominant society, while minority stipulations aim at ensuring respect for minority rights within the majority society.189 This difference is attributed to the assumption that minorities want to be part of the national society as a whole while preserving their distinct characteristics, whereas indigenous peoples tend to maintain a different way of life.190 In general, the special status of indigenous peoples is justified on the ground that the indigenous societies are the original holders of their traditional lands, retain substantial distinct cultural characteristics,191 and additionally are peoples on the brink of extinction (‘endangered peoples’).192 The implication 185. CG Benedict, ‘The Status and Rights of Indigenous Peoples in Canada’ (1999) 59 Heidelberg Journal of International Law (ZaöRV) 405–42, 428–29. 186. Kerrin Schillhorn, ‘The Status and Rights of Indigenous Peoples in Australia’ (1999) 59 Heidelberg Journal of International Law (ZaöRV) 443–62, 461. 187. Asbjørn Eide, Working Paper on the Relationship and Distinction Between the Rights of Persons Belonging to Minorities and Those of Indigenous Peoples, UN Doc E/CN.4/ Sub.2/2000/10 (19 July 2000), para 9. 188. Rainer Grote, ‘The Status and Rights of Indigenous Peoples in Latin America’ (1999) 59 Heidelberg Journal of International Law (ZaöRV) 497–528, 511. 189. Mattias Åhrén, ‘The Provisions on Lands, Territories and Natural Resources in the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples: An Introduction’ in Claire Chartes and Rodolfo Stavenhagen (eds), Making the Declaration Work: The United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (Copenhagen, International Work Group for Indigenous Affairs, 2009) 200–15, 201–202. 190. Asbjørn Eide and Rianne Letschert, ‘Institutional Developments in the United Nations and at the Regional Level’ (2007) 14 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 299–332, 319. 191. René Kuppe, ‘The Three Dimensions of the Rights of Indigenous Peoples’ (2009) 11 International Community Law Review 103–18, 105, 110–11. 192. Lauri Hannikainen, ‘The Status of Minorities, Indigenous Peoples and Immigrant and Refugee Groups in Four Nordic States’ (1996) 65 Nordic Journal of International Law 1–71, 3. 36 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) is thus that the problems faced by indigenous peoples are in many ways a ‘special category’ deserving special legal status and protection.193 While the case of indigenous peoples is certainly one of tears, blood, horror, exploitation and extermination, some of the aforementioned assumptions justifying their differential treatment in comparison to minorities are partially misleading. Thus, although several characteristics of indigenous peoples’ attachment to their lands, such as the traditional patterns of land usage, collective ownership and spiritual or religious ties to them, are not to be found in the case of minorities, which are mostly adapted to Western notions of economy and private property and practice major world religions,194 it is at the same time true that the latter also have a strong emotional attachment to their historical homelands.195 Also, regarding the argument that indigenous peoples do not just seek measures for their integration, but claim a long term differential status as distinct peoples in order to pursue an autonomous development of their cultures,196 one could note that this is not absolutely true for all of them, since there are indigenous peoples who want to participate fully in the material and cultural life of the societies around them.197 Similarly, there are minorities which give great emphasis to the preservation of their distinctive cultures.198 On this point, Musafiri correctly notes that the difference between indigenous peoples and minorities is a matter of degree, not of kind.199 Indeed, if one compares the two most widely cited UN working definitions for the concepts of ‘minority’ and ‘indigenous peoples’, namely those of Capotorti200 and Cobo201 respectively, one would have to conclude that 193. Marianne Van Den Bosch and Willem Van Genugten, ‘International Legal Protection of Migrant Workers, National Minorities and Indigenous Peoples – Comparing Underlying Concepts’ (2002) 9 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 195–233, 230–31. 194. Aukerman (n 166) 1039. 195. Will Kymlicka, ‘Beyond the Indigenous/Minority Dichotomy’ in Allen and Xanthaki (n 161) 183–208, 200; Aukerman (n 166) 1038–39. 196. Garth Nettheim, ‘“Peoples” and “Populations” – Indigenous Peoples and the Rights of Peoples’ in Crawford, The Rights of Peoples (n 125) 107–26, 126. 197. Anna Meijknecht, ‘The (Re-)emergence of Indigenous Peoples as Actors in International Law’ (2002–2003) 10 Tilburg Foreign Law Review 315–24, 316. 198. Aukerman (n 166) 1014, 1022–23. 199. Musafiri (n 14) 507–508. 200. See Francisco Capotorti, Study on the Rights of Persons Belonging to Ethnic, Religious and Linguistic Minorities, UN Doc E/CN.4/Sub.2/384/Rev.1 (New York, United Nations Publications, 1979), para 568. 201. See José Martinez Cobo, Study of the Problem of Discrimination Against Indigenous Populations, Volume V, Conclusions, Proposals and Recommendations, UN Doc E/CN.4/ Sub.2/1986/7/Add.4 (New York, United Nations Publications, 1987), para 379. Autonomy for Minorities 37 they do not differ by much. The main difference is that only those groups that are connected with a specific territory which their ancestors inhabited prior to its colonisation or invasion can be regarded as indigenous peoples.202 Barring this difference, minorities and indigenous peoples are comparable groups in the sense that both have in the past been victims of gross violations of their human rights,203 and in the present share a common experience of discrimination and lack of access to the whole range of human rights law.204 They belong to non-dominant,205 vulnerable, politically and economically marginalised groups206 that are ethnically distinct from the majority population as regards their language, religion, culture and traditions.207 They are conscious of their different cultures208 and want to preserve and transmit them to their future generations.209 Thus, there is a good deal of overlap between these two kinds of groups and many of their concerns are in practice broadly similar,210 especially those issues concerning non-discrimination and cultural integrity.211 As Daes noted, ‘no definition or list of characteristics can eliminate overlaps between the concepts of minority and indigenous peoples. Cases will continue to arise 202. Malgosia Fitzmaurice, ‘The New Developments Regarding the Saami Peoples of the North’ (2009) 16 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 67–156, 132. 203. Joshua Castellino, ‘The MDGs and International Human Rights Law: A View from the Perspective of Minorities and Vulnerable Groups’ (2009) 13 The International Journal of Human Rights 1–28, 11. 204. Joshua Castellino, ‘Indigenous Rights and the Right to Development: Emerging Synergies or Collusion?’ in Allen and Xanthaki (n 161) 367–86, 368. 205. Budislav Vukas, ‘International Protection of Minorities: Limits of Growth’ (2000) XXIX Thesaurus Acroasium 21–36, 26. 206. Snežana Trifunovska, ‘One Theme in Two Variations – Self-Determination for Minorities and Indigenous Peoples’ (1997) 5 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 175–97, 178. 207. Borhan Uddin Khan and Muhammad Mahbubur Rahman, Protection of Minorities: Regimes, Norms and Issues in South Asia (Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2012) 16. 208. Bent Ole Gram Mortensen, ‘The Greenland Self-Government Act: The Pitfall for the Inuit in Greenland to Remain an Indigenous People?’ (2016) VIII The Yearbook of Polar Law 103–28, 110. 209. Alexandra Xanthaki, ‘Indigenous Rights in the Russian Federation: The Case of Numerically Small Peoples of the Russian North, Siberia, and Far East’ (2004) 26 Human Rights Quarterly 74–105, 77. 210. Tom Hadden, ‘The United Nations Group on Minorities’ (2007) 14 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 285–97, 296. 211. S James Anaya, ‘International Human Rights and Indigenous Peoples: The Move Toward the Multicultural State’ (2004) 21 Arizona Journal of International and Comparative Law 13–61, 21. 38 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) that defy any simple, clear-cut attempt at classification’.212 Brownlie also critically comments on the separate treatment of minorities and indigenous peoples as an impediment to fruitful work, on the grounds that the rights and claims of groups with their own cultural histories and identities are in principle the same.213 In this vein, the UNDRIP could set a precedent that minorities could invoke to strengthen their rights by attaining inter alia a right to autonomy. After all, since whatever arguments exist for recognising a right to self-government to indigenous peoples also apply to a significant degree to minorities, it would be morally inconsistent to deny it to the latter.214 One has, however, to accept that such a transformative potential of the UNDRIP seems unlikely to take place in the near future, as for reasons of security States have adopted the Declaration under an understanding of its sui generis character. Even so, such an approach is short-sighted, since it is conceptually unstable, as Kymlicka warns.215 The present situation, in which it is more advantageous to be labeled an indigenous people than a minority,216 is very likely to lead to tensions over the issue of definitions, making many or even all minorities claim indigenous status.217 Thus, States will sooner or later have to face the reality and give functional responses to minority autonomy claims. 5.4. Minority Autonomy through Effective Participation A third way through which minorities could gradually succeed in gaining a recognition of a right to autonomy without having to argue that they either constitute ‘peoples’ or that they are entitled to the analogical implementation of the UNDRIP as regards its autonomy element, is via the road of participatory rights. The right of every citizen to take part in the conduct of public affairs, to vote and to be elected, stated in Article 25 of the ICCPR, is related to the right of self-determination of peoples, but it is also distinct 212. Erica-Irene Daes, Working Paper on the Relationship and Distinction Between the Rights of Persons Belonging to Minorities and Those of Indigenous Peoples, UN Doc E/CN.4/ Sub.2/2000/10 (19 July 2000), para 41. 213. Ian Brownlie, ‘The Rights of Peoples in Modern International Law’ in Crawford, The Rights of Peoples (n 125) 1–16,16. 214. Kymlicka (n 195) 199–201. 215. Kymlicka (n 195) 203–207. 216. See Russel Lawrence Barsh, ‘Indigenous Peoples in the 1990s: From Object to Subject of International Law?’ (1994) 7 Harvard Human Rights Journal 33–86, 81–82. 217. Aukerman (n 166) 1013, 1020; Kymlicka (n 195) 205–206. Autonomy for Minorities 39 from it.218 It is well established in international law as a freestanding right.219 A progressive approach of the specific provision beyond its individualistic orientation, such as the one suggested below by Scheinin, in combination with a dynamic interpretation220 of Article 2, paras 2 and 3 of the minority UN Declaration and Article 15 of the FCNM, which call for the effective participation of minority members in the cultural, religious, social, economic and public life as well as in the decisions at national and regional level that affect them, could open the door to minority autonomy structures.221 Under this prism, it is critical to question whether simple majority rule can fully secure effective participation of minority members in public affairs.222 Reality proves that, read restrictively, the ‘one man, one vote’ democratic principle can deprive minorities of any real opportunity to improve their situation.223 This happens simply because minorities are outvoted in the ‘winner takes all’ context and are unable to protect their interests.224 Thus, absolute democracy can lead to minority oppression (‘majority tyranny’).225 Another approach, then, is needed, which could make the right of minority members to participation truly effective, in order to generate space for the maintenance and promotion of their identities.226 Such an innovative 218. Human Rights Committee, The Right to Participate in Public Affairs, Voting Rights, and the Right of Equal Access to Public Service, Article 25, General Comment No 25, UN Doc CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.7 (12 July 1996), para 2. 219. Patrick Thornberry, ‘The UN Declaration on the Rights of Persons Belonging to National or Ethnic, Religious and Linguistic Minorities: Background, Analysis, Observations and an Update’ in Alan Phillips and Allan Rosas (eds), Universal Minority Rights (Turku/Abo and London, Abo Akademi University Institute of Human Rights and Minority Rights Group International, 1995) 13–76, 42–43. 220. See Gudmundur Alfredsson, ‘Minority Rights: A Summary of Existing Practice’ in Phillips and Rosas, ibid, 77–86, 81. 221. Anne-Christine Bloch, ‘Minorities and Indigenous Peoples’ in Asbjørn Eide, Catarina Krause and Allan Rosas (eds), Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (Dordrecht/Boston/ London, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1995) 309–21, 316–17. 222. Jungwon Park, ‘Integration of Peoples and Minorities; An Approach to the Conceptual Problem of Peoples and Minorities with Reference to Self-Determination Under International Law’ (2006) 13 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 69–93, 77. 223. Joshua Castellino, ‘The Protection of Minorities and Indigenous Peoples in International Law: A Comparative Temporal Analysis’ (2010) 17 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 393–422, 401–402. 224. Katerina Tsotroudi, ‘Ethnic Minorities and Collective Rights in the New Europe: Some Observations’ (1993) 46 Revue Hellenique de Droit International 225–49, 233–34. 225. Daniel Thürer, ‘National Minorities: A Global, European and Swiss Perspective’ (1995) 19 Fletcher Forum of World Affairs 53–69, 67–68. 226. Marc Weller, ‘Creating the Conditions Necessary for the Effective Participation of Persons Belonging to National Minorities’ (2004) 10 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 265–90, 267. 40 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) approach is found in the concurring individual opinion of Scheinin in the case JGA Diergaardt (late Captain of the Renoboth Bater Community) et al v Namibia. In his view there are situations where the right of participation of Article 25 of the ICCPR calls for special arrangements for members of minorities and indigenous peoples. In such cases, it is not sufficient to give individual members of these communities the individual right to vote in general elections. ‘Some forms of local, regional or cultural autonomy may be called for in order to comply with the requirement of effective rights of participation.’227 This reading of Article 25 of the ICCPR, which goes beyond the individualistic orientation of the right of political participation, in combination with Articles 2, paras 2 and 3 of the relevant UN Declaration and para 15 of the FCNM, could lead to minority autonomy.228 The UN Forum on Minority Issues has taken such a view by suggesting that the right to effective political participation can be ensured through many different means, including ‘forms of territorial or personal autonomy’.229 A similar position has been adopted by the chairperson of the former UN Working Group on Minorities, Asbjørn Eide, in his Commentary on the UN Declaration on the rights of persons belonging to minorities.230 Also, the Explanatory Report of the FCNM encourages governments to consider, for instance, ‘decentralized or local forms of government’ as a means of achieving effective participation.231 It should also be noted that from a practical perspective the separation of the provisions on effective participation from the more politically sensitive right to self-determination, in either its external or its internal dimension, may 227. Individual Opinion by Martin Scheinin, UN Doc CCPR/C/69/D/760/1997 (6 September 2000) 17–18. See Annelies Verstichel, ‘Recent Developments in the UN Human Rights Committee’s Approach to Minorities, with a Focus on Effective Participation’ (2005) 12 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 25–41, 27, 35, 41. 228. See Balázs Vizi, ‘Does European Integration Support the Minority Quest for Autonomy? Minority Claims for Self-Government and Devolution Processes in Europe’ in Zoltán Kántor (ed), Autonomies in Europe: Solutions and Challenges (Budapest, L’HarmattanNPKI, 2014) 25–35, 27; Patrick Thornberry, ‘The Democratic or Internal Aspect of Self-Determination With Some Remarks on Federalism’ in Tomuschat (n 121) 101–38, 134. 229. Human Rights Council, Recommendations of the Second Session of the Forum on Minority Issues on Minorities and Effective Political Participation (12 and 13 November 2009), UN Doc A/HRC/13/25 (2 February 2010), para 9. 230. Asbjørn Eide, Commentary to the Declaration on the Rights of Persons Belonging to National or Ethnic, Religious and Linguistic Minorities, UN Doc E/CN.4/Sub.2/AC.5/2001/2 (2 April 2001), paras 20, 38 and 39. 231. Framework Convention for the Protection of National Minorities and Explanatory Report, H(95)10 (1995), para 80 https://rm.coe.int/CoERMPublicCommonSearch Services/DisplayDCTMContent?documentId=09000016800c10cf. Autonomy for Minorities 41 have some advantages, making them more politically acceptable to States and possibly increasing the prospects of their successful implementation.232 However, the ACFC has so far tacitly declined such an approach in its supervision of Article 15 of the FCNM. Specifically, despite commenting positively on the States that by their own initiative have established autonomous arrangements, the Committee does not go so far as to imply that Article 15 encompasses a right to autonomy for minorities in order to obtain effective participation.233 In this regard, Houten and Wolff note that the autonomy solutions ‘are not part of the official CoE “agenda”’234 at least for now. Still, it is a potential that minorities can explore to the extent possible, using it as a starting point to the way to autonomy. 5.5. Concluding Views Current international law does not entail a right to autonomy for minorities. However, it does offer, as has been analysed, some avenues on which minorities could work on to gain its recognition. While such a development seems unlikely to happen in the near future, due mainly to State anxieties, much will depend on the broadening and deepening of the concept of democracy in society at large. In a living and functional democratic society all issues, even the most ‘sensitive’ such as minority autonomy rights, should freely be put into open dialogue and discussion. Minority representatives should have a real opportunity, meaning available time and space and adequate access to all kinds of media and public fora, to articulate in detail their arguments and make them known to the dominant ethnic majority in order to clarify that autonomy on the one hand does not mean secession and on the other constitutes an inherent element of the democratic principle and a valuable instrument for minority citizens to pursue their cultural development in the same way that citizens of the ethnic majority do. Convincing then the dominant ethnic majority and gaining its neutrality or even its understanding towards the autonomy issue is a necessary prerequisite for State governments to be more receptive to the relative minority demand. In this context, 232. See Helen Quane, ‘The UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples: New Directions for Self-Determination and Participatory Rights?’ in Allen and Xanthaki (n 161) 259–87, 273, 281. 233. Julie Ringelheim, ‘Minority Rights in a Time of Multiculturalism – The Evolving Scope of the Framework Convention on the Protection of National Minorities’ (2010) 10 Human Rights Law Review 99–128, 126 (fn 122). 234. Pieter van Houten and Stefan Wolff, ‘The Dynamics of Ethnopolitical Conflict Management by International and Regional Organizations in Europe’ (2008) 7 Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe 1–31, 12. 42 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) an agenda which would be based not on a nationalistic but on a civic style rhetoric in the spirit of goodwill would have more chances of success. After all, recognising a right to autonomy to minorities could lead to enhancement of the democratic structures of the society, both at international and national level, since autonomy in its original literary meaning in the Greek language, refers, as mentioned, to the right to make ones’ laws and take decisions on matters of direct concern. Minority populations would be more satisfied in the State they reside if they themselves instead of State officials of different ethnic background are in the position to take decisions in areas of minority interest such as education, culture, language, etc. In this way autonomy can contribute to minority satisfaction and State stability at the same time. 6. Anti-Autonomy Critics and Counter-Arguments Critical voices against the recognition of a right to autonomy, territorial or non-territorial/cultural, to minorities, note that the co-existence in a State territory of different laws embodying a diversity of legal traditions may not only create legal antinomies but also political conflicts in terms of values protected by the law.235 In the same context, it has been claimed that these kinds of settlements enhance ethnic separation and reinforce the isolation of minorities, thus undermining on the one hand the common public sphere bridging the different communities and favouring on the other the centrifugal forces that threaten the stability of the State.236 Indeed, most States are very uncomfortable with the idea of minority autonomy as they fear that it will bring destabilisation, which can even escalate to secession. Others argue that granting autonomy to minorities on the one hand ‘may threaten norms of equality and individual rights at the within-group level’237 by sustaining for example traditional practices that violate the rights of women or by legitimising policies that restrict the right of minority members to exit from their group, and on the other, in the case of territorial arrangements, could subject the other minorities that live in the autonomous area to policies 235. Giovanni Matteo Quer and Sara Memo, ‘Releasing Minorities from the “Nationalist Trap”: From Territorial to Personal Autonomy in a “Multiple Demoi Europe”’ (2012) 47 Cuadernos Europeos de Deusto 149–75, 166. 236. Emmanuel Dalle Mulle, ‘Belgium and the Brussels Question: The Role of the NonTerritorial Autonomy’ (2016) 15 Ethnopolitics 105–24, 120–21. 237. Jan Muś and Mirella Korzeniewska-Wiszniewska, ‘Divide et Impera Principle. Minority Oriented State Policy in the Balkans’ (2013) 13 New Balkan Politics 73–89, 79. Autonomy for Minorities 43 of discrimination and assimilation.238 Also, on the level of implementation and especially as regards the non-territorial/cultural autonomy experiments that have taken place almost exclusively in Eastern Europe, it has been pointed out that these are not working properly.239 On the one hand the relative instruments imply only a minimalist action on the part of the States and lack strong requirements for financial support,240 and on the other the cultural councils/self-governments have neither clear status and competences nor decisive powers in their field.241 Replying to the aforementioned concerns, it could be argued, first, that the existence of different cultural values in a society can contribute to its strengthening as a whole than to its fragmentation and disruption.242 To this end, certain educational and social policy programmes promoting integration and cultivating mutual understanding between majority and minority members, as well as a sense of citizen’s common civil identity could help. Considering the States’ fears, Gross accepted in his report that autonomy is certainly a concept that can have negative connotations, since it can be seen as a threat to the State’s territorial integrity and a first step towards secession. However, he added, ‘there is frequently little evidence to sustain this view’.243 Indeed, as Murswiek notes, autonomy could be the best prevention against secession, if only granted in a timely fashion.244 In this light, there is in theory 238. Stephen Deets and Sherrill Stroschein, ‘Dilemmas of Autonomy and Liberal Pluralism: Examples Involving Hungarians in Central Europe’ (2005) 11 Nations and Nationalism 285–305, 293. 239. Kaan Namli, ‘De-Territorializing Minority Rights: The Application of NonTerritorial Autonomy for Dispersed Minority Communities’ (Master’s thesis, İhsan Doğramacı Bilkent University, 2016) 29 http://repository.bilkent.edu.tr/bitstream/ handle/11693/30165/10113480.pdf.pdf?sequence=1. 240. Jala Garibova, ‘Cultural Autonomy: The Perceived vs. Realistic Scope’ (2012) 213 International Journal of the Sociology of Language 105–109, 106. 241. Liliya Aliyeva, ‘Tove H. Malloy, Alexander Osipov, and Balazs Vizi (2015) Managing Diversity Through Non-Territorial Autonomy: Assessing Advantages, Deficiencies, and Risks. Oxford: Oxford University Press (Book Review)’ (2016) 2 Intersections. EastEuropean Journal of Society and Politics 135–37, 137. 242. See Laura Pineschi, ‘Cultural Diversity as a Human Right? General Comment No. 21 of the Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ in Silvia Borelli and Federico Lenzerini (eds), Cultural Heritage, Cultural Rights, Cultural Diversity – New Developments in International Law (Leiden/Boston, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2012) 27–53, 29, 36. 243. Andreas Gross (Rapporteur), Positive Experiences of Autonomous Regions as a Source of Inspiration for Conflict Resolution in Europe, Committee on Political Affairs and Democracy, Doc 9824, 3 June 2003, para 9. 244. Dietrich Murswiek, ‘The Issue of a Right of Secession – Reconsidered’ in Tomuschat (n 121) 21–39, 39. 44 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) strong support for the view that autonomy arrangements carry benefits that overcome the aforementioned anti-autonomy argument, focusing mainly on examples where the autonomy settlements led to a decrease in violence in a series of ethnic conflicts (eg in the Basque Country, Corsica, Northern Ireland).245 In any case, in order to ease a State’s reasonable anxiety it would be wise to have clear and sincere guarantees from the representatives of the minorities concerned that they will not engage in activities contrary to State sovereignty. This requirement does not emanate from an absolute respect for States’ integrity, since human history has repeatedly seen the disintegration of various types of polities that have claimed they would last forever,246 but from acknowledgement of the fact that there is no mono-ethnic territory in the world. Thus, any separation from a State and creation of a new one would inevitably lead to the formation of new minorities subjected to the dominance of their new masters,247 as the case of the marginalised Serbian and Roma minorities in independent Kosovo clearly shows. After all, minority members should not only have rights guaranteeing real and full equality with the members of the ethnically dominant majority but also duties as citizens of the State. Second, any autonomy settlement must respect the principles of equality and non-discrimination.248 The autonomous government authorities should fully guarantee the enjoyment of human rights by all the members of the State’s dominant majority who constitute a numerical minority in the autonomous territory, as well as of the members of other minorities.249 No minority autonomy right can be used as a pretext to suppress or infringe non-minority members’ rights.250 They must also wholly safeguard the rights 245. Daniel Rodrigues, ‘Considerations of the Role of Federalism in Managing Ethnic Plurality in Multinational States in Conflict Prevention’ (2014) 4 Janus.Net e-Journal of International Relations 104–17, 108–109. 246. Christian Tomuschat, ‘Self-Determination in a Post-Colonial World’ in Tomuschat (n 121) 1–20, 6. 247. Sia Spiliopoulou Åkermark and Sarah Stephan, ‘Editorial: Rethinking Territorial Arrangements in Conflict Resolution – Introduction to the Special Issue of the International Journal on Minority and Group Rights’ (2013) 20 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 1–3, 2. 248. Gross (n 243) para 17. See also Layos Arday, ‘Self-determination, Self-government, Regionalization, Autonomy’ (translated by Zsofia Csuti) (2012) 3 Délkelet Európa – SouthEast Europe International Relations Quarterly 1–8, 5–6. 249. Gudmundur Alfredsson, ‘The Rights of Indigenous Peoples with a Focus on the National Performance and Foreign Policies of the Nordic Countries’ (1999) 59 Heidelberg Journal of International Law (ZaöRV) 529–42, 535. 250. See Marco Odello, ‘The Right to Take Part in Cultural Life: General Comment No. 21 of the United Nations Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ (2011) 27 Anuario Espanol de Derecho International 493–521, 505–506. Autonomy for Minorities 45 of the members of their own group who do not wish to identify with it.251 Finally, they have to combat any traditional practices that violate the human rights and fundamental freedoms under the banner of cultural relativism.252 Next, the failures of some autonomy regimes should not necessarily be blamed on them, but on the conditions under which they were applied.253 Majtényi, for example, has argued that Hungary’s cultural autonomy has failed not because of the supposed or real deficiencies of the idea, but because of the inappropriate implementation and malfunctions of the legislation.254 The same conclusion ensues from the poor functioning of the cultural autonomy arrangements in other countries, such as in Estonia and the Russian Federation, where the establishment of the relevant regimes seems primarily to serve hidden political agendas rather than minority protection, resulting in toothless minority cultural self-governments.255 Such cases illustrate that when goodwill on the part of State authorities is lacking, there can be no substantive autonomy. Thus, a true spirit of meaningful collaboration between the State authorities, the ethnic majority and the minority/minorities living in a State is a prerequisite for the different models of autonomy to become an effective instrument of minority protection and conflict prevention. 7. Final Thoughts Autonomy for minorities is not and cannot be a panacea, since there is a wide variety of minority situations around the world that are in need of different treatment.256 In general, however, it can be one of the best vehicles for minority protection,257 and for the prevention of ethnic conflicts.258 251. See Timor Varady, ‘Minorities, Majorities, Law and Ethnicity: Reflections of the Yugoslav Case’ (1997) 19 Human Rights Quarterly 9–54, 46. 252. See the relevant discussion in Federico Lenzerini, The Culturalization of Human Rights Law (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2014) 127–28. 253. Gross (n 243) para 15. See also Csaba Máté Sarnyai and Pap Tibor, ‘Individual, Community, Identity’ (2015) 1 West Bohemian Historical Review 167–76, 173–74. 254. Balázs Majtényi, ‘What has Happened to our Model Child? The Creation and Evolution of the Hungarian Minority Act’ (2005–2006) 5 European Yearbook of Minority Issues 397–443, 419. 255. See Athanasios Yupsanis, ‘Cultural Autonomy for Minorities in the Baltic States, Ukraine, and the Russian Federation; A Dead Letter’ (2016) XXXVI Polish Yearbook of International Law 109–35. 256. Hurst Hannum, ‘Contemporary Developments in the International Protection of the Rights of Minorities’ (1991) 66 Notre Dame Law Review 1431–48, 1442. 257. Kay Hailbronner, ‘The Legal Status of Population Groups in a Multinational State Under Public International Law’ (1990) 20 Israel Yearbook on Human Rights 127–54, 140. 258. Mtendeweka Mhango, ‘Governance, Peace and Human Rights Violations in Africa: Addressing the Application of the Right to Self-Determination in Post-Independence Africa’ (2012) 5 African Journal of Legal Studies 199–214, 213. 46 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (Vol. 25, 2014–2015) It can accommodate population diversity and enhance integration without assimilation,259 as well as provide minorities with the necessary space and control over the development of their culture, language and religion, without jeopardising State integrity, as it is exclusively oriented towards internal structures and arrangements.260 Given its positive potentials it is sad that such a right exists only for indigenous peoples in contemporary international law. Developments like the ACHPR’s broad conception of the term ‘people’, in a way that certainly includes ‘minorities’, in combination with the application to them of the legal doctrine of internal self-determination, which includes forms of autonomy/self-government, could lead to the recognition of such a right to minorities in international law. Also, given the several commonalities between minorities and indigenous peoples, an analogical implementation of the relevant UNDRIP provisions on autonomy could have the same result. Indeed such a development is morally and practically justified. A dynamic interpretation of the minority participatory rights found in the relevant UN Declaration and the FCNM could additionally contribute in this direction. In order for such a right not to become a tool of oppression of internal minorities, its recognition should be conditional on the absolute respect of their human rights. Moreover, in order to avoid any attempt by ‘kin states’, where these exist, to manipulate autonomous minority institutions with the aim of serving their own political agenda, any recognition should be made dependent on the full respect of the States’ territorial integrity, and the minorities should give strong commitments in this direction. An unreasonable disloyalty should incur the penalty of the unilateral repeal by the State government of the autonomy regime. Autonomy can work only if there is a spirit of goodwill on all sides concerned. In such a context, a combination of territorial and non-territorial schemes could offer stronger minority protection and ensure peace and stability. 259. Kristin Henrard, ‘The Interrelationship Between Individual Human Rights, Minority Rights and the Right to Self-Determination and its Importance for the Adequate Protection of Linguistic Minorities’ (2001) 1 The Global Review of Ethnopolitics 41–61, 57. 260. Kelley Loper, ‘Substantive Equality in International Human Rights Law and its Relevance for the Resolution of Tibetan Autonomy Claims’ (2011) 37 North Carolina Journal of International Law and Commercial Regulation 1–46, 31.