Australian Journal of Asian Law, 2018, Vol 19 No 1, Article 4: 1-18 The Right to Privacy in Philippine Jurisprudence Emmanuel Q Fernando This article explores the right to privacy in Philippines jurisprudence, surveying relevant laws and judicial decisions. It pays particular attention to three decisions of the Philippine Supreme Court. The first is the case of White Light v City of Manila, where the Court erroneously considered the right to the pursuit of happiness as a right to privacy. The next is People v Cogaed, a search and seizure case, where the Court mischaracterised the nature of the privacy violated as a right to autonomy. Finally, there is Morfe v Mutuc, in which no mistake was committed by the Court but a superficial reading of the case might lead one to conclude that one had been committed with respect to the standard of review applicable to cases involving the right to privacy. The right to privacy has long been recognised in Philippine law. It is found in several provisions of the Bill of Rights of the Philippine Constitution. It exists also in some statutes and in judicial precedent. The case in which it was first explicitly recognised was Morfe v Mutuc,1 which dealt with the disclosure of statements of assets and liabilities of government officials. This article will discuss the current state of the right to privacy in Philippine jurisprudence. In general, Philippine jurisprudence protects the right to privacy. Oscar Franklin Tan has stated, however, that ‘the Philippine right to privacy taken as a whole is marred by inconsistencies, gaps and self-contradictions’ (Tan, 2008: 79-80). In this paper I hope to show that the right to privacy in the Philippines is not nearly as incoherent and inconsistent as Tan argues. In the first part of this article, the meaning of privacy will be investigated and its two aspects, informational and decisional, will be introduced and explained. This will be followed by an exploration of the ways in which the right may be violated, that is, improper intrusion and unwarranted disclosure. This part will end with a brief discussion of how the right to privacy was first recognised jurisprudentially. In the second part of this article, the jurisprudential basis for distinguishing the two types or aspects of privacy will be shown. The third part then introduces the concept of strict scrutiny, which is the standard of review applicable to determine the constitutionality of a law that that possibly violates the right to privacy. The fourth part deals with informational privacy and cases, giving examples of improper intrusion and unwarranted disclosure. Finally, the article will end with a discussion of decisional privacy. Privacy: Its Meaning and Aspects The right to privacy gained recognition and prominent attention in 1890 when law partners Samuel D Warren and (later) Justice Louis D Brandeis wrote their seminal article, ‘The Right to Privacy’, which they described it as the ‘right to be let alone’, ‘a part of the more general right to the immunity of a person -- the right to one's personality’ (Warren and Brandeis, 1890: 207). Following this definition, I also define privacy as the right to be let alone. This has found jurisprudential recognition. Justice Douglas held: ‘Liberty in the constitutional sense must mean more than freedom from unlawful governmental restraint; it must include privacy as well, if it is to be a repository of freedom. The right to be let alone is indeed the beginning of all freedom’. 2 Justice Brandeis stated that this  1 2 Emmanuel Fernando (D Phil., Oxon.) is a full professor of the Department of Philosophy, College of Social Sciences and Philosophy, University of the Philippines, as well as Professorial Lecturer, UP College of Law and San Beda Graduate School of Law. He is also a Professorial Lecturer of the Philippine Judicial Academy, the institution tasked by the Supreme Court with the continuing education of judges. GR No L-20387, 31 January 1968; 22 SCRA 424. Public Utilities Commission v Pollak, 343 US 451, 467 (1952). Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 right to be let alone is ‘the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men [sic]’.3 The two most important aspects of the right to privacy are its informational and decisional aspects. This is found in Solove's characterisation, which quotes from DeCew (1997: 75). According to DeCew, there are three overlapping ‘clusters of privacy claims’: informational privacy, accessibility privacy, and expressive privacy. Informational privacy involves ‘control over information about oneself’. Accessibility privacy is the limited-access conception: ‘accessibility privacy focuses not merely on information or knowledge but more centrally on observations and physical proximity. Expressive privacy ‘protects a realm for expressing one's self-identity or personhood through speech or activity. Thus, DeCew combines three theories of privacy: (1) control over information; (2) limited access; and (3) personhood. (Solove, 2002: 1125) The first of these clusters corresponds to the informational aspect of privacy and the third, expressive privacy, to the decisional aspect. I categorise the second cluster (accessibility privacy) as simply the ‘manner in which privacy may be accessed and thus violated’ and so I do not treat it as constituting a distinct theory or aspect of privacy. Informational aspect The informational aspect of the right to privacy has been variously defined. Alan Westin (2003: 3) defined it ‘as the claim of an individual to determine what information about himself or herself should be known to others’. Ruebhausen and Brin opined that ‘(t)he right to privacy gives a person the right to determine what, how much, to whom and when information about himself shall be disclosed’ (in Cortez: 1970: 7). Fried (1968: 483) characterised it as ‘control over knowledge about oneself’. Thomson (1975: 304) insisted that ‘it is the right not to be looked at and the right not to be listened to’. Posner (1977: 393) ‘simply not(ed) that one aspect of privacy is the withholding or concealment of information’. Emerson stated: The right of privacy is clearly a vital element in any system of individual rights. Essentially it is designed to support the individual, to protect the core of individuality, in the relations of the individual to the collective society. As such it is designed to mark out a sphere or zone in which the collective may not intrude upon the individual will. (Emerson, 1979: 337). Gavison (1989: 423) commented that the interest in privacy is related to our concern over our accessibility by others which includes the extent to which we are known to them, the extent to which they have physical access to us, and the extent to which we are the subject of their attention. She added, ‘In its most suggestive sense, privacy is a limitation of others' access to an individual. [...] [It] is a complex of these three independent and irreducible elements: secrecy, anonymity, and solitude’ (Gavison, 1989: 423). Allen (1998: 15) characterised ‘personal privacy’ as ‘a condition of inaccessibility of the person, his or her mental states, or information about the person to the senses or surveillance devices of others’. Moore reiterated the control aspect of privacy that Fried stressed: ‘A right to privacy is a right to control access to and uses of—places, bodies, and personal information’ (Moore, 2008: 421). In summary, the informational aspect of privacy is concerned with what and how much an agent is willing to disclose, or let others know, about his or her personal life. Decisional aspect The decisional aspect of privacy stems from respect for a person as an autonomous being with the right to decide for him or herself how to live life and conduct activities. This respect acknowledges that another may be engaged in a kind of creative enterprise that can be disrupted, distorted, or frustrated by intrusion. (Benn, 1971: 26). The value of privacy lies in our respect for persons as autonomous beings with capacity to love, care and the like (Inness, 1993: 95; Solove, 2002: 1145). Hence, decisional privacy is the right to express one's personality and to decide how to live one's 3 Olmstead v United States, 277 US 438, 478 (1928). 2 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 personal life without undue interference from others. It contemplates decisions that are of an intimate or significant nature, expressive of one's lifestyle. The Philippine case of Imbong v Ochoa4 involving reproductive rights, discussed below, is an excellent example of decisional privacy. Violating the Right There are two ways in which the right to privacy may be violated, by improper intrusions or by unwarranted exposure or disclosure. Heyman claims: Invasion of privacy takes two main forms: improper intrusion into an individual's private life (e.g., through obscene or harassing telephone calls), and unwarranted exposure of that private life to the world (through publication of highly personal information). Of course, both forms of invasion of privacy can be committed through speech. (Heyman, 2002: 784; emphasis in original) Improper intrusion Improper intrusion, as previously mentioned, occurs when there is an unwanted access by others to a person’s life. An individual has the right to: control what information about him or herself will be made known to others; and to live his or her life without unwanted intrusion by others (Benn, 1971: 2). An example of the right to intrusion privacy is art 26 of the New Civil Code.5 It provides: Article 26. Every person shall respect the dignity, personality, privacy and peace of mind of his neighbours and other persons. The following and similar acts, though they may not constitute a criminal offense, shall produce a cause of action for damages, prevention and other relief: (1) Prying into the privacy of another's residence; (2) Meddling with or disturbing the private life or family relations of another; (3) Intriguing to cause another to be alienated from his friends; (4) Vexing or humiliating another on account of his religious beliefs, lowly station in life, place of birth, physical defect, or other personal condition. Other examples of offensive intrusions include nude beaches, which spoil the view of a condominium overlooking the ocean, or the unsolicited mailing of sexual material to a person's residence. Many United States cases concern this.6 Further examples of intrusion are unreasonable searches and seizures, also discussed below. Unwarranted disclosure Unwarranted exposure or disclosure occurs when aspects of a person's life is revealed to the public. This may result not only in discomfort or embarrassment experienced by the intrudee due to this exposure but also in decisions that would not normally made were it not for the unwarranted disclosure. Privacy thus prevents interference, pressures to conform, ridicule, punishment, unfavorable decisions, and other forms of hostile reaction. To the extent that privacy does this, it functions to promote liberty of action, removing the unpleasant consequences of certain actions and thus increasing the liberty to perform them. (Gavison, 1989: 448) As an example of this, s 2 of Philippines Republic Act No 1405 (otherwise known as the Bank Secrecy Act) considers bank deposits to be of absolutely confidential nature. They may not be examined, inquired about or investigated. This is intended to protect the deposit owners’ secrecy or privacy and prevent unwarranted disclosure of their bank assets. Of course, there are exceptions, as revealed below. The right against self-incrimination is another example. It also protects against violations of intrusion and disclosure. It prevents questions being asked about a person's life that she 4 5 6 GR No 204819, 08 April 2014; 721 SCRA 146. An Act to Ordain and Institute the Civil Code of the Philippines or Republic Act No. 386; approved on 18 June 1949. See, for example: Rosen v United States, 161 US 29 (1896); Roth v United States, 354 US 476 (1957); and Ginzburg v United States, 383 US 463 (1966), among others. 3 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 or he may not want to reveal lest it provide evidence of a crime she or he may have committed. A selfincrimination case will also be discussed below. Privacy as a constitutional right came to the forefront in United States jurisprudence with the case of Griswold v Connecticut (381 US 479 (1965)), in which the United States Supreme Court affirmed the right of married couples to use contraceptives. This case concerned decisional privacy. A married couple may not be prevented or disallowed from using contraception. It is completely up to them to decide whether to use contraception or not. This decision thus protected their decision privacy. In the Philippines, the seminal case was Morfe v Mutuc,7 in which public officials challenged a statute that required them to file their statements of assets and liabilities, claiming a violation of their right to privacy. This concerned informational privacy. The jurisprudential basis for seeing the right to privacy as divided into two aspects is found in Whalen v Roe:8 The cases sometimes characterized as protecting ‘privacy’ have in fact involved at least two different kinds of interests. One is the individual interest in avoiding disclosure of personal matters, and another is the interest in independence in making certain kinds of important decisions.9 The former corresponds to the informational aspect and the latter to the decisional. The Standard of Strict Scrutiny Just as in United States law, privacy is a value highly treasured in Philippine law, such that it is also considered to be a ‘preferred freedom’. That being the case, a standard of strict scrutiny, and not rationality, is to be applied to determine whether the right to privacy has been violated or not. The rationality standard only requires that the means used to achieve the purpose of the legislation be a reasonable method to achieve it. It need not guarantee the realisation of the purpose; it only requires that it is reasonable to expect that the purpose will be achieved. In strict scrutiny, a higher standard is required: the purpose must be compelling and the means used be the least restrictive. In other words, there may be no other means available that could achieve the result with a lesser burden imposed on the individual. The doctrine of preferred freedoms originated in footnote 4 to the 1938 Carolene Products case,10 which explicitly proposed and articulated a two-tiered or double standard approach to resolving rights cases. This ‘bifurcated review’ (White, 1996: 327) comprised of the deferential standard of rational basis review for economic legislation and the interventionist stance of heightened scrutiny for legislation curtailing fundamental rights.11 Under the former, the validity of legislation was almost invariably upheld. After all, as just explained, rationality review is a deferential standard. On the other hand, the opposite was the case for the strict scrutiny. Indeed, strict scrutiny has been characterised as ‘strict in theory and fatal in fact’ (Gunther, 1972: 8). Preferred freedoms encompassed intellectual liberty as found in the First Amendment to the United States Constitution, which included religious freedom. As noted in the United States case of Braunfield v Brown, ‘For religious freedom—the freedom to believe and to practice strange and, it may be, foreign, creeds—has classically been one of the highest values of our society’.12 Further, Justice O’Connor has pointed out that ‘religious liberty is an independent liberty, that it occupies a preferred position ...’13 That priority, the court held in Thomas v Collins ‘gives these liberties a 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 Morfe, at 424. 429 US 589 (1977). Whalen v Roe, at 599-600. United States v Carolene Products Co, 304 US 144 (1938). Footnote 4 to the judgment states: ‘There may be narrower scope for operation of the presumption of constitutionality when legislation appears on its face to be within a specific prohibition of the Constitution, such as those of the first ten amendments, which are deemed equally specific when held to be embraced within the Fourteenth. See Stromberg v California, 283 US 359, 369-70; Lovell v Griffin, 303 US 444, 452.’ There is another kind of legislation subject to heightened scrutiny, which involves suspect classifications under the equal protection clause. Here, I deal only with legislation affecting fundamental liberties. Braunfield v Brown, 366 US 599, 612 (1961). Employment Division v Smith, 494 US 872, 895 (1990). 4 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 sanctity and a sanction not permitting dubious intrusions’.14 The same status has been accorded to the right to privacy. This was made clear in the case of Ople v Torres, which determined the constitutionality of a computerised, national computerised identification reference system, when the court held that: . . . [the right to privacy] merely requires that the law be narrowly focused and a compelling interest justify such intrusions. Intrusions into the right must be accompanied by proper safeguards and well-defined standards to prevent unconstitutional invasions. We reiterate that any law or order that invades individual privacy will be subjected by this Court to strict scrutiny.15 In the next section, I consider how these principles have been applied by courts in the Philippines. Informational Privacy Improper Intrusion The First Privacy Case: Morfe v Mutuc In this case, the Philippines Anti-Graft and Corrupt Practices Act16 was alleged to have violated the constitutional right to privacy. Section 7 of the Act required every public officer to file a true, detailed, and sworn statement of assets and liabilities every year. This was intended to deter public officials and employees from committing acts of dishonesty and improve the tone of morality in public service. The Supreme Court held that the provisions were valid and did not violate the public officials' rights to privacy. Privacy as a constitutional right was explicitly recognised in this case. […] in view of the fact that there is an express recognition of privacy, specifically that of communication and correspondence which ‘shall be inviolable except upon lawful order of Court or when public safety and order’ may otherwise require, and implicitly in the search and seizure clause, and the liberty of abode, the alleged repugnancy of such statutory requirement of further periodical submission of a sworn statement of assets and liabilities deserves to be further looked into.17 The Court established that the right to privacy was not violated in the following manner. . . . it cannot be said that the challenged statutory provision calls for disclosure of information which infringes on the right of a person to privacy. It cannot be denied that the rational relationship such a requirement possesses with the objective of a valid statute goes very far in precluding assent to an objection of such character. This is not to say that a public officer, by virtue of a position he holds, is bereft of constitutional protection; it is only to emphasize that in subjecting him to such a further compulsory revelation of his assets and liabilities, including the statement of the amounts and sources of income, the amounts of personal and family expenses, and the amount of income taxes paid for the next preceding calendar year, there is no unconstitutional intrusion into what otherwise would be a private sphere.18 The rationality test was used to determine whether the Act violated the right to privacy. This appears to be a mistake. Privacy being a fundamental or preferred freedom, the correct standard to apply is, as explained, strict scrutiny and not rationality. Clearly, the Act satisfies the rationality test but, if strict scrutiny is the standard to be applied, was the ponente (the judge who wrote the judgment) mistaken? He was not, because the public official enjoys no privacy with respect to the amounts and sources of her income. Thus, a private matter became a public matter by virtue of her or him becoming a public official and the rationality test became applicable. The argument, in brief, is this. A public official's assets and liabilities leave the realm of privacy and become a matter of legitimate public concern the moment he or she becomes a public servant. The public has a right to know the amounts and sources of his or her income in order 14 15 16 17 18 Thomas v Collins, 323 US 516, 530 (1945). GR No 127685, 23 July 1998; 293 SCRA 141, 169. Republic Act No 3019 (1960). Morfe, at 443. Morfe, at 447-48. 5 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 to be ensured of his or her honesty, integrity, and lack of corruption. This distinguishes her or him from a private citizen. This has support in judicial scholarship. Irene Cortez, then Dean of the University of the Philippines College of Law and later a Justice of the Philippine Supreme Court, opined that the court showed that there was nothing unreasonable in the requirement that an inquiry made of a person holding public office as to her assets and liabilities, including a statement of the amounts and sources of income, be made a matter of public concern. It is part of a wider policy to stamp out dishonest practices by public officials. Since a public official, unlike the ordinary citizen, is a public figure, information of this sort would not constitute a violation of her privacy. But a similar statute applied to private individuals would infringe on their privacy (Cortez, 1970, 27-28). The Bank Secrecy Law Section 2 of the Bank Secrecy Law provides: All deposits of whatever nature with banks or banking institutions in the Philippines including investments in bonds issued by the Government of the Philippines, its political subdivisions and its instrumentalities, are hereby considered as of an absolutely confidential nature and may not be examined, inquired or looked into by any person, government official, bureau or office, except upon written permission of the depositor, or in cases of impeachment, or upon order of a competent court in cases of bribery or dereliction of duty of public officials, or in cases where the money deposited or invested is the subject matter of the litigation. This Law allows four exceptions to the confidentiality of bank deposits. Presidential Decree No 1792 (1981) later amended the Law by providing for two additional exceptions. In Marquez v Desierto,19 the Supreme Court recognised and enumerated these six exceptions, as follows: (i) in an examination made in the course of a special or general examination of a bank that is specifically authorised by the Monetary Board after being satisfied that there is reasonable ground to believe that a bank fraud or serious irregularity has been or is being committed and it is necessary to look into the deposit to establish such fraud or irregularity; (ii) in an examination made by an independent auditor hired by the bank to conduct its regular audit, provided that the examination is for audit purposes only and the results thereof should be for the exclusive use of the bank; (iii) upon written permission of the depositor; (iv) in cases of impeachment; (v) upon order of the court in cases of bribery or dereliction of duty by public officials; or (vi) in cases where the amount deposited or invested is the subject matter of the litigation (Singson, 2001, 671-72). Ejercito v Sandiganbayan20 In this case, two exceptions to the Bank Secrecy Law were applied. Former President Joseph Estrada, who was being tried for plunder, challenged the validity of two Resolutions denying his Motions to Quash Subpoenas Duces Tecum/Ad Testificandum, a writ issued by the Sandiganbayan Court (a court that criminally tries public officials) summoning a witness to testify orally and bring books, papers or evidence to the court. The Resolutions directed the President of Export and Industry Bank or his or her authorised representative to produce documents pertaining to a trust account and a savings account of the former President. After ruling that a trust account is a deposit for the purposes of the Act, the Supreme Court nonetheless ruled that the exceptions under the Bank Secrecy Law applied. These accounts are no longer protected by the Secrecy of Bank Deposits Law, there being two exceptions to the said law applicable in this case, namely: (1) the examination of bank accounts is upon order of a competent court in cases of bribery or dereliction of duty of public officials, and (2) the money deposited or 19 20 GR No 135882. 27 June 2001; 359 SCRA 772, GR No 157294, 30 November 2006; 509 SCRA 190. 6 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 invested is the subject matter of the litigation. Exception (1) applies since the plunder case pending against former President Estrada is analogous to bribery or dereliction of duty, while exception (2) applies because the money deposited in petitioner’s bank accounts is said to form part of the subject matter of the same plunder case. (Ejercito, 225) National Computerised Identity Reference System: Ople v Torres21 In this case, Senator Blas Ople challenged the validity of Administrative Order No 308 entitled ‘Adoption of a National Computerised Identification Reference System’, in part because it violated the right to privacy. The Court agreed. It pointed out the ‘potential for misuse of the data to be gathered under AO No 308’. Every time an individual deals with a government agency to avail of basic services and security, he or she must present his PRN (Payment Reference Number). His or her transactions with the government will necessarily be recorded. The individual’s file may include his or her transactions for items such as loan availments, income tax returns, statement of assets and liabilities, reimbursements for medication, hospitalisation. The existence of this vast reservoir of personal information constitutes a covert invitation to misuse, a temptation that may be too great for some of our authorities to resist (Ople, 161). The court therefore held a national computerised identity reference system to be unconstitutional, thereby protecting the right to privacy. Right against unreasonable searches and seizures Villanueva v Querubin22 The rationale for the right to privacy was elegantly expressed in Villanueva, where the amount of P10,350.00 and a wooden container was seized by the police by virtue of a search warrant issued by respondent Judge Querubin on the residence of the petitioner, Oscar Villanueva: It is deference to one's personality that lies at the core of this right, a recognition of a constitutionally protected area, primarily one’s home. What is sought to be guarded is a person's prerogative to choose who is allowed entry to his or her residence. In that haven of refuge, his or her individuality can assert itself not only in the choice of who shall be welcome but likewise what kind of objects he or she wants in that place. The state, however powerful, should not have access, for in the traditional formulation, his house, however humble, is his castle. Thus, any unwarranted intrusion by government is outlawed, and the state is called on to refrain from any invasion of a person’s dwelling and to respect the privacies of his or her life (Villanueva, 350). This decision clearly constitutes protection against government intrusion. People v Cogaed23 Unfortunately, search and seizure was misclassified as an autonomy right in the search and seizure case of Cogaed. The Court considered the privacy violated to be that of autonomy, and not simply that of intrusion. There was nothing wrong in the application of the law or the decision of the case. In fact, it was an excellent decision. Nonetheless, the Court misconstrued the type of privacy violated. The defendant was convicted of the crime of illegal possession of marijuana. The defendant’s bag was searched without a warrant and three bricks of marijuana were found. He had not acted suspiciously. A jeepney (jeep taxi) driver had, however, had texted the police and informed them of a possible crime. The defendant was ordered to open his bag and it was searched without his being fully apprised of his rights. This was not a reasonable search within the meaning of the Constitution. Unfortunately, the ponente began his decision with this ill-advised observation. ‘The mantle of protection upon one's person and one's effects conferred by Article III, Section 2 of the Constitution is essential to allow citizens to evolve their autonomy and, hence, to avail themselves of their right to privacy’ (Cogaed, 432). There are two inaccuracies in this quotation. First, search and seizure is 21 22 23 Ople, supra n. 14. GR No L-26177, 27 December 1972; 48 SCRA 345. GR No 200334, 30 July 2014; 731 SCRA 427. 7 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 not essentially connected to autonomy, although it is intimately related to privacy. An individual’s decision-making process is only marginally and indirectly affected by searches and seizures. The case therefore had nothing to do with autonomy. It dealt with privacy. It involved an intrusion on privacy, not autonomy privacy. There was no threat to the defendant’s autonomy, only a physical (and illegal) intrusion into his possessions. There was no indication that he was committing a crime to warrant the search of his personal effects. Second, it misconstrued the relation between autonomy and privacy, when it held that the search and seizure clause ‘is essential to allow citizens to evolve their autonomy and, hence, to avail themselves of their right to privacy’ (Cogaed, 432). The ponente misinterpreted the relationship. Privacy serves autonomy but autonomy does not serve privacy. Autonomy is only an aspect of privacy. To make use of the right to privacy, an individual must have the autonomy to make his or her own decisions, unencumbered by the demands of the state. As Emerson (1973: 340) stated, ‘[…] the right of privacy consists of protection for the three elements which are at the core of individuality. The first is autonomy, which is necessary in order to retain control over one's destiny as an individual’. Autonomy is personal sovereignty combined with self-determination. According to Mill (1990: 135), the ‘only part of the conduct of any one, for which he is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign’. Feinberg, a century later, developed this concept: ‘Personal autonomy […] involves the idea of having a domain or authority in which the self is sovereign’. He adds: ‘to say that I am sovereign over my bodily territory is to say that I, and I alone, decide (so long as I am capable of deciding) what goes on there. My authority is a discretionary competence; an authority to choose and make decisions’ (Feinberg, 1986: 52-53). Raz (1986: 369) also explains autonomy as selfdetermination: ‘The ruling idea behind the ideal of personal autonomy is that people should make their own lives. The autonomous person is a (part) author of his own life. The ideal of personal autonomy is the vision of people controlling to some degree, their own destiny, fashioning it through successive decisions throughout their lives’. In the Roe v Wade case, it was commented that the right to autonomy includes ‘a specific right of personal choice in matters of marriage and family life’.24 The right to privacy protects the individual from interference in the making of personal decisions or life choices. This decisional privacy is a right to autonomy. It is true that privacy and autonomy are intimately related. One must enjoy privacy to act autonomously. Autonomy concerns privacy of decision-making, wherein an individual is allowed complete freedom, without interference from the state, to make up his or her own mind to do as he or she wills. In short, autonomy is an aspect of privacy and privacy serves the value of autonomy. The dilemma experienced by the defendant in this case was not that of a violation of his autonomy. It was a violation of his privacy, an invasion of his physical space. Decision-making was not involved. The court in the Eisenstadt v Baird case25 commented: If the right of privacy means anything, it is the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child (Eisenstadt, 453) In summary, the intrusion was not in the decision-making process but in physical space, that is, in the searching of the bag’s contents. Hence, it was his privacy, and not his autonomy that was violated. Unwarranted Disclosure Income tax returns: Ty v CA (Ty, 836) This is case a case involving the disclosure of information regarding a person's income. A father-inlaw sought to recover certain properties claimed to be part of the estate of his deceased son, which his daughter-in-law intended to sell to raise money to pay the estate taxes. To prove his son's non- 24 25 Roe v Wade, 410 US 113, 168 (1973). 405 US 438 (1972) 8 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 ownership, he attached a number of his son’s income tax returns to his reply to his daughter-in-law's amended answer. The daughter-in-law sought to have these returns struck from the record for violating the rule on confidentiality and the constitutional right to privacy of communication and correspondence. The Court denied the daughter-in-law's motion on the grounds of prematurity. The time for objection was during trial, when these records would be presented for evidence. Hence, the issue of whether the income tax returns were private or not was not settled. Physician-Patient Confidentiality: Krohn v CA26 In proceedings for the declaration of nullity of marriage on the grounds of psychological incapacity, a husband sought to introduce as evidence a psychiatric report about his wife taken early in their marriage. The wife sought have the report struck off the records on the grounds of privilege or physician-patient confidentiality. The Court ruled that the confidentiality provision applies only to the physician, and not to a third party who may have secured a copy of the report. However, the husband’s testimony on the matter was hearsay and his testimony, as well as the report itself, would be inadmissible as evidence for that reason. Unfortunately, the wife did not object to his testimony on this ground and waived her right to object, rendering the report and the husband's testimony admissible. Right against self-incrimination As previously mentioned, the right against self-incrimination both involves improper intrusion and unwarranted disclosure. Pascual v Board of Examiners27 The connection between the right against self-incrimination and the right to privacy was eloquently expressed by then Justice, later Chief Justice, Fernando, in Pascual. The Board filed a case for alleged immorality against Arsenio Pascual Jr, where it would present as its first witness Pascual himself, who objected on the ground of his constitutional right to be exempt from being a witness against himself. The court held that the constitutional guarantee stands for a belief that, while crime should not go unpunished and that the truth must be revealed, such desirable objectives should not be accomplished according to means or methods offensive to the high sense of respect accorded the human personality. While earlier decisions stressed the principle of humanity on which this right is predicated, precluding as it does all resort to force or compulsion, whether physical or mental, current judicial opinion places equal emphasis on its identification with the right to privacy. A zone of privacy which government may not force to surrender to his detriment is created. It comprises a right to a private enclave where he may lead a private life (Pascual, 349-50). Invitations to dialogue or intimidatory interrogations: Babst v National Intelligence Board28 In Babst, journalists critical of martial law were requested to appear before a Special Committee at Philippine Army Officer's Clubhouse, Fort Bonifacio, Metro Manila to shed light on confidential matters. These matters, of course, concerned adverse reporting on military activities during martial law. A dissenting opinion described the invitations: (The journalists) complain that ‘some of them have received summonses, subpoenas or directives from military authorities who have subjected them to sustained interrogation, touching the most delicate aspects of their work, feelings, sentiments, beliefs, associations and even aspects of their private lives’. From August to December of 1982, several such subpoenas were received by some of the petitioners, most of which came in the wake of the mass arrest, indictment and prosecution of the editor and staff of the publication We Forum, which could be read as a threat that petitioners might also be subjected to similar treatment and 26 27 28 GR No 108854, 14 June 1994; 233 SCRA 146. GR No L-25018, 26 May 1969; 28 SCRA 344. GR No L-62992, 28 September 1984; 132 SCRA 316. 9 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 that those ‘who have been subjected to the aforesaid sustained interrogation found it an ordeal creating a “chilling effect” on their work’. (Babst, 333) Clearly, this involved a violation of disclosure privacy of the most egregious kind, as the dissent intimated. The majority decision did not make such a definitive pronouncement, since it decided the case based on mootness (that is, that the action complained of had ceased), since the military chose to discontinue such interrogations. In other words, there no longer remained any controversy since what was objected to had been stopped. Nonetheless strong grounds exist to proclaim such interrogations as anathema and in violation of the Constitution, particularly when done during the period of martial law, which was the situation obtaining at the time of the case. Decisional Privacy Intrusion Marital privacy: Ilusorio v Bildner29 This case involved a wife who filed for a writ of habeas corpus so that she could have custody of her husband. The Court denied the writ on the ground that there was no illegal restraint of liberty. ‘The evidence shows that there was no actual and effective detention or deprivation of lawyer Potenciano Ilusorio's liberty that would justify the issuance of the writ’ (Ilusorio, 2000: 175). Moreover, to subject him to unwanted visitation rights would be a violation of his right to privacy: With his full mental capacity coupled with the right of choice, Potenciano Ilusorio may not be the subject of visitation rights against his free choice. Otherwise, we will deprive him of his right to privacy. Needless to say, this will run against his fundamental constitutional right. (Ilusorio, 2000: 176) Ilusorio v Bildner30 A Motion for Reconsideration was filed after this decision, in which the wife, Erlinda, asked the Court to enforce consortium between her and her husband. In resolving the case, the court chose not to intrude into the privacy of the spouses in terms of the decision of whether to live together or not. They had been living apart and she was fearful that her two children were using their sick and frail father, whom she claimed to be mentally incapacitated, to sign away conjugal property to companies controlled by the children. . . . Erlinda states that Article XII of the 1987 Constitution and Articles 68 and 69 of the Family Code support her position that as spouses, they (Potenciano and Erlinda) are duty bound to live together and care for each other. We agree. The law provides that the husband and the wife are obliged to live together, observe mutual love, respect and fidelity. The sanction therefore is the ‘spontaneous, mutual affection between husband and wife and not any legal mandate or court order’ to enforce consortium. (Ilusorio, 2001: 432) Duncan Association v Glaxo-Wellcome31 The Employee Code of Conduct of Glaxo stipulated that if management perceives a conflict of interest or a potential conflict between, on the one hand, a (present or future) relationship between the employee and co-employees or employees of competing drug companies and, on the other, the employee’s employment with the company, the management and the employee would explore the possibility of a ‘transfer to another department in a non-counterchecking position’ or preparation for employment outside the company after six months. Tecson was aware of such a stipulation and agreed to it as a condition of his employment. Thereafter, he fell in love with Bettsy, an employee of a competing company, and eventually married her. This presented a conflict. After numerous 29 30 31 GR No 139789, 12 May 2000; 332 SCRA 169. GR No 139789, 19 July 2001; 361 SCRA 427. GR No 162994, 17 September 2004; 438 SCRA 343. 10 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 attempts to resolve it, the company decided to assign him to a different province where no such conflict would exist. Tecson claimed that his transfer constituted constructive dismissal and sought to have it nullified. The Court agreed with Glaxo that the transfer a valid exercise of management prerogative. ‘Glaxo has a right to guard its trade secrets, manufacturing formulas, marketing strategies and other confidential programs and information from competitors’ (Duncan, 352). The Court added, ‘Glaxo does not impose an absolute prohibition against relationships between its employees and those of competitor companies. Its employees are free to cultivate relationships with and marry persons of their own choosing. What the company merely seeks to avoid is a conflict of interest between the employee and the company that may arise out of such relationships’ (Duncan, 355). It concluded: . . . the record shows that Glaxo gave Tecson several chances to eliminate the conflict of interest brought about by his relationship with Bettsy. Tecson’s supervisors at Glaxo constantly reminded him about the effects of his relationship on his employment with the company and on the company’s interests. After Tecson married Bettsy, Glaxo gave him time to resolve the conflict by either resigning from the company or asking his wife to resign from Astra. Glaxo likewise acceded to his repeated requests for more time to resolve the conflict of interest. When the problem could not be resolved after several years of waiting, Glaxo was constrained to reassign Tecson to a sales area different from that handled by his wife for Astra. Notably, the Court did not terminate Tecson from employment but only reassigned him to another area. Clearly, the foregoing dispels any suspicion of unfairness and bad faith on the part of Glaxo. (Duncan, 355) This appears to be a case where the right to privacy was not protected, as its value was outweighed by management prerogative or business interests. However, as the Court explained, there was actually no prohibition of relationships. Tecson was still free to marry whomever he wanted. However, something had to be done to ensure that the conflict that arose because of the relationship would be negated, and this was accomplished by Tecson's reassignment. Religious or marital privacy: Estrada v Escritor (Escritor, 1)32 Estrada v Escritor was not decided on the basis of the right to privacy but on religious conscientious objection grounds. Nonetheless, it could have been converted into a privacy case, as indeed one separate opinion did. In the case, the Office of the Court Administrator (OCA) recommended the suspension of a court employee, a member of Jehovah’s Witnesses, from the Civil Service for disgraceful and immoral conduct for six months. The employee who was married under the eyes of the law, but validly divorced from the point of view of her religion, cohabited with another upon remarriage under her religion. From her own perspective and that of her religion, there was nothing immoral about her cohabitation. However, since her acts constituted the crime of concubinage under Philippine law, her conduct was considered grossly immoral under Civil Service Law. The Court treated the case as one of conscientious objection and remanded the case to the OCA to determine whether the defence of religious conscientious objection applied. It could also have been considered a case of privacy. According to the Court, ‘More than religious freedom, I look with partiality to the rights of due process and privacy’ (Escritor, 207, per Davide, CJ, italics in original). If treated in this way, the employee could have argued that the determination of whether she was validly divorced or not, and therefore able to remarry and cohabit with another, was a private or internal matter to be decided in accordance with her own conscience or that of her religion. From that perspective, it could be argued that the choice imposed upon her by the law between family or marriage and her job was an unconstitutional one. Justice Bellosillo, who wrote a separate opinion, was painfully aware of the woman’s situation. He proclaimed: 32 A.M. No P-02-1651, 4 August 2003; 408 SCRA 1. 11 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 Indeed, in light of these facts, what better institution is there to judge her morality than her own church; what business does the government have to judge her conduct that is not criminal in nature nor destructive of her efficiency in the service? (Escritor, 193) He added the observations of Judge Maceda, who was directed by the OCA to investigate the complaint. Judge Maceda formulated the issue in terms of ‘whether the moral standards of the Catholic faith, to which a great majority of us belongs, must be exacted of [the] respondent to determine her administrative responsibility when she is a member of the Jehovah’s Witnesses’ (Escritor, 198) Thereafter, he (Judge Maceda) ‘rendered his Report and Recommendation absolving the respondent of the charge of immorality on the ground that her relationship has been well-accepted by the religious sect to which she and her partner adhered’ (Escritor, 196). Justice Bellosillo further concluded: ‘To be sure, there are matters that are best left to the conscience and the moral beliefs of an individual, and matters of which public law may take cognizance’ (Escritor, 199). Clearly, the judge believed that this was a matter of private concern. Gender privacy: Silverio v Republic33 Silverio had a sex change from male to female and then sought to have her birth certificate amended to reflect her new gender (that of a female), and to change the name on the birth certificate from Rommel to Mela. The Court ruled that neither a person’s first name nor gender on a birth certificate can be changed on the ground of gender reassignment. The change of gender or a change of name in the birth certificate is not a private matter that a person may undertake. It has a public function and importance, and only the legislature can determine as to what comprises allowable or justifiable grounds for such change. In our system of government, it is for the legislature, should it choose to do so, to determine what guidelines should govern the recognition of the effects of sex reassignment. The need for legislative guidelines becomes particularly important in this case where the claims asserted are statute-based. To reiterate, the statutes define who may file petitions for change of first name and for correction or change of entries in the civil registry, where they may be filed, what grounds may be invoked, what proof must be presented and what procedures shall be observed. If the legislature intends to confer on a person who has undergone sex reassignment the privilege to change his name and sex to conform with his reassigned sex, it has to enact legislation laying down the guidelines in turn governing the conferment of that privilege (Silverio, 394-95). Privacy right to abortion: Imbong v Ochoa or the Reproductive Health Law Case34 The issue of a privacy right to abortion did not arise in the Imbong case. This is because the Constitution itself, by means of art II, s12, mandates that ‘the State shall equally protect the life of the mother and the life of the unborn from conception’. However, there were certain observations made by the Supreme Court relevant to the issue. The majority opinion noted that the framers of the 1987 Constitution had the clear and unequivocal intent to protect the life of the unborn from conception. Thus it intended to prevent the legislature from enacting a measure legalising abortion. Clearly, there is no privacy right to abortion under Philippine law. If a statute is enacted creating one, it would almost certainly be declared invalid and unconstitutional. It would require a constitutional amendment for a such a right to be created. Privacy right to the use of contraceptives: Imbong v Ochoa or The Reproductive Health Law Case On the other hand, a privacy right to the use of contraceptives is not outrightly unconstitutional. No provision in the 1987 Philippine Constitution renders it so. Consequently, RA No 10354, the Act Providing for a National Policy on Responsible Parenthood and Reproductive Health of 2012, 33 34 GR No 174689, 19 October 2007; 537 SCRA 373. GR No 204819, 08 April 2014; 721 SCRA 146. 12 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 sought to grant women a reproductive right to the use of contraceptives. The relevant provision on marital consent or spousal privacy in ss 23(a)(2)(i) of this Law states. The following acts are prohibited: (a) Any health care service provider, whether public or private, who shall: ... (2) refuse to perform legal and medically-safe reproductive health procedures on any person of legal age on the ground of lack of consent or authorization of the following persons in the following instances: (i) Spousal consent in case of married persons: provided, that in case of disagreement, the decision of the one undergoing the procedures shall prevail. The Court found this provision unconstitutional for transgressing against ‘family solidarity’, protected by Art XV of the 1987 Constitution: Section 1. The State recognizes the Filipino family as the foundation of the nation. Accordingly, it shall strengthen its solidarity and actively promote its total development. Section 2. Marriage, as an inviolable social institution, is the foundation of the family and shall be protected by the State. Section 3. The State shall defend: The right of spouses to found a family in accordance with their religious convictions and the demands of responsible parenthood; The right of children to assistance, including proper care and nutrition, and special protection from all forms of neglect, abuse, cruelty, exploitation and other conditions prejudicial to their development; The right of the family to a family living wage and income; and The right of families or family associations to participate in the planning and implementation of policies and programs that affect them. The Court concluded that the Responsible Parenthood and Reproductive Health Law cannot be allowed to infringe upon this mutual decision-making. Non-participation in the decision whether to use contraceptives would drive a wedge between the husband and wife, possibly result in bitter animosity, and endanger the marriage and the family. This would be a marked departure from the policy of the State to protect marriage as an inviolable social institution. Decision-making involving a reproductive health procedure is a private matter that belongs to the couple, not just one of them. Any decision they reach will affect their future as a family because the size of the family or the number of their children matters significantly. The decision whether or not to undergo the procedure belongs exclusively to, and is shared by, both spouses as a cohesive unit. It is a constitutionally guaranteed private right (Imbong, 349-50). A concurring opinion added: Clearly, on its face, Section 23 (a)(2)(i) contradicts the unity of direction of the spouses, conflicts with the solidarity or the family, and collides with the fundamental equality before the law of men and women. In particular, it goes against the constitutional right of the spouses to found a family and to jointly decide on the number and spacing of their children. Rather than fostering unity between the spouses, it tends to foment discord and sow division between them. (Imbong, 470) Another opinion, which concurred in part and dissented in part, objected to the solution of the majority opinion as it conferred absolute authority on one spouse, the non-consenting spouse, which is again contrary to family solidarity. ... When the ponencia states that the aforesaid decision–making process must be settled through the spouses' mutual consent and that the State cannot intrude in such, process because of the right to marital privacy, the implicit result is that the other spouse, who refuses to give his or her consent, is given the absolute and final authority to decide this matter. In other words, the result reached by the ponencia is merely the opposite of that under the RH Law. That is, the non–consenting spouse is effectively given the absolute and final authority in the decision–making process. I find this result equally repugnant to the afore–discussed constitutional provisions (Imbong, 616). This opinion suggested state intervention in marital rights and obligations only when there are genuine and serious disagreements between the spouses. This view is consistent with the provisions of the Family Code on dispute resolution between spouses which preserves and adheres to the constitutional precept on the solidarity of the family and the right, belonging to both spouses, to 13 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 found the family. State intervention, which provides the solution to the problem, involves calling upon the courts to ultimately settle the dispute in case of disagreement between the spouses (Imbong, 616-17). This view is contrary to United States jurisprudence. In Eisenstadt,35 it was asserted: [T]he marital couple is not an independent entity with a mind and heart of its own, but an association of two individuals each with a separate intellectual and emotional makeup. If the right of privacy means anything, it is the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child. (Eisenstadt, 453, italics in original) There were dissenting opinions in the Imbong case, which argued for the constitutionality of the provision. The Chief Justice stated: By means of placing importance to the primary decision of the spouse undergoing the reproductive health procedure, the RH Law stresses only the fundamental right of each person to decide for his or herself what to do with one's body.36 Justice Perlas-Bernabe added: In the final analysis, the constitutional right to found a family should not be shallowly premised on the mere decision on the number of children; the right to found a family, more importantly, looks towards the well–being of its members, such as the reproductive health of the spouse undergoing the disputed procedure. To this end, the decision of said family member should be respected and not be overruled by either his/her spouse or by the courts. Respect for individual autonomy, especially in cases involving the individual ’s physical well–being, is a reasonable limitation and, even, a corollary to the spouses' collective right to found a family. (Imbong, 729) The only dissenter agreed: The general rule encourages married persons to discuss and make a conjugal decision on the matter. They are caught in a problem when they disagree. This agreement may fester and cause problems within their family. The disagreement will not be created by the RH Law. It will exist factually regardless of the law. Section 23(a)(2)(i) of the law becomes available to break this deadlock and privilege the decision of the spouse undergoing the procedure. This is logical since the reproductive health procedures involve the body, health and well being of the one undergoing the procedure. (Imbong, 831). The dissenter added: By declaring Section 23(a)(2)(i) as unconstitutional, the majority interprets the privacy and autonomy of the family as also providing insulation of patriarchal or sexist practices from state scrutiny.This is not what the Constitution intends. (Imbong, 834) This was a clear case where privacy rights lost out. This was ultimately due to the pervasive influence of the Catholic Church, which considered the use of contraception to be a sin. Privacy in cybersex: Disini v Secretary of Justice 37 The Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012, or Republic Act No 10175, punishes cybersex, which is the ‘willful engagement, maintenance, control, or operation, directly or indirectly, of any lascivious exhibition of sexual organs or sexual activity, with the aid of a computer system, for favor or consideration,’ with imprisonment of prison mayor (a prison term of 6-12 years) or a fine, or both. This definition allows for innocent trysts between husbands and wives to be criminally punishable. Take, for example, a husband who misses his wife and sends a message to his wife to undress before 35 36 37 Eisenstadt v Baird, mentioned above. ‘Sa pamamagitan ng pagpapahalagasapangunahingpasiya ng asawangsasailalimsa reproductive health procedure, pinaiigtinglamang ng RH Law ang pangangalagasapangunahingkarapatan ng bawattaonamagpasiyaukolsakanyangsarilingkatawan.’ per Sereno, CJ, Concurring and Dissenting. Imbong at 472. GR No 203335, 11 February 2014; 716 SCRA 237. 14 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 him on the Internet with the promise that he will buy her a new refrigerator if she does this. She willingly agrees and does so. This would satisfy the definition of cybersex in the law since the wife engaged in a lascivious exhibition of her sexual organs for favour or consideration – the refrigerator. Innocent trysts are not the only situations punishable by this law. Works of art and medical journals satisfy these elements too. The Petitioners in their Brief informed the Court of this possibility. Petitioners claim that the above violates the freedom of expression clause of the Constitution. They express fear that private communications of sexual character between husband and wife or consenting adults, which are not regarded as crimes under the penal code, would now be regarded as crimes when done ‘for favour’ in cyberspace. In common usage, the term ‘favour’ includes ‘gracious kindness, ’‘a special privilege or right granted or conceded,’ or ‘a token of love (as a ribbon) usually worn conspicuously’. This meaning given to the term ‘favour’ embraces socially tolerated trysts. The law as written would invite law enforcement agencies into the bedrooms of married couples or consenting individuals. (Disini, 309) This is how the Court responded to the matter. But the deliberations of the Bicameral Committee of Congress on the section of the Cybercrime Prevention Act give a proper perspective on these issues. These deliberations show a lack of intent to penalize a ‘private showing . . . between and among two private persons . . . although that may be a form of obscenity to some’. The understanding of those who drew up the cybercrime law is that the element of ‘engaging in a business’ is necessary to constitute the illegal cybersex. The Act actually seeks to punish cyber prostitution, white slave trade, and pornography for favor and consideration. This includes interactive prostitution and pornography, i.e., by webcam. (Disini, 310) The Supreme Court suggests that courts ought to look beyond the words of the statute to the deliberations of Congress to determine its true intent. But that is contrary to the principles of statutory construction. Time and time again, it has been repeatedly declared by this court that where the law speaks in clear and categorical language, there is no room interpretation, there is only room for application.38 For nothing is better settled than that the first and fundamental duty of courts is to apply the law as they find it, not as they like it to be. Fidelity to such a task precludes construction or interpretation, unless application is impossible or inadequate without it.39 Congress failed to express its intent precisely. The Supreme Court failed to reject the act on the grounds that it was too broad, so Congress was spared from making the necessary amendment to s 4(c)(1). As a result, private, innocent acts between consenting adults have been made criminal by this ill-formulated law. It might be argued that privacy rights were lost in this case but the Supreme Court did not think so, arguing that innocent trysts between consenting adults at the Internet would not be criminally punished. This was because it urged the judges to decide the case not in accordance with the letter of the law but instead look at the congressional deliberations to determine the true intent of Congress. This is unlikely to happen, as courts will, in all probability, apply the law as written, there being no ambiguity in its language. Privacy in motel rooms: White Light v City of Manila40 I end this paper with the White Light case, which mistakes the right to privacy for the right to the pursuit of happiness. A Manila city ordinance prohibited motels and inns from offering short-time admissions, as well as pro-rated or ‘wash up’ rates for such abbreviated stays. Some motel operators, as a result, filed a case to declare the city ordinance invalid and unconstitutional as it violated, among others, the right to privacy. The ordinance was enacted with a view of regulating public morals, including illicit activity in transient lodging establishments. Its apparent goal was to minimise, if not 38 39 40 Cebu Portland Cement vs Municipality of Naga, GR Nos 24116-17, 22 August 1968; 24 SCRA 708, 712 (1968). Resins, Inc v Auditor General, GR No L-17888, 29 October 1968; 25 SCRA 754, 757 (1968). GR No 122846, 20 January 2009; 576 SCRA 416. 15 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 eliminate, the use of the establishments covered by the statute for illicit sex, prostitution, drug use and the like. The Supreme Court invalidated the ordinance on the grounds that it violated customers’ right to privacy. The right, being a fundamental liberty, required that it pass the test of strict scrutiny rather than the rationality test to be valid. This it failed to do. Strict scrutiny required that the end of the ordinance be a compelling state interest and the means used be not just rational but the least restrictive. As the Court held, ‘Indeed, the right to privacy as a constitutional right was recognised in Morfe v Mutuc, the invasion of which should be justified by a compelling state interest’ (White Light, 440). It also pointed out that: There are very legitimate uses for a wash rate or renting the room out for more than twice a day. Entire families are known to choose to pass the time in a motel or hotel whilst the power is momentarily out in their homes. In transit passengers who wish to wash up and rest between trips have a legitimate purpose for abbreviated stays in motels or hotels. Indeed, any person or groups of persons in need of comfortable private spaces for a span of a few hours with purposes other than having sex or using illegal drugs can legitimately look to staying in a motel or hotel as a convenient alternative. (White Light, 441) Hence, the least restrictive means was not used. Less intrusive measures such as curbing the proliferation of prostitutes and drug dealers through active police work would be more effective in easing the situation. So would the strict enforcement of existing laws and regulations penalizing prostitution and drug use. These measures would have minimal intrusion on the businesses of the petitioners and other legitimate merchants. (White Light, 443) Moreover, even if the court did not say so, the ordinance was formulated too broadly and was thus guilty of overbreadth. It included prohibitions which were not intended to be prohibited, such as the renting of a room for legitimate purposes, would be disallowed. Customers wishing to stay in motels for purposes other than sex were prohibited from doing so. The rationality test was satisfied by the regulation. It was reasonable to expect that prostitution and sexual vice would be minimised in Manila by the ordinance. Of course, vice in general might not be lessened, as a couple might exercise their prerogative to patronise a motel in a neighbouring city. However, it did not satisfy strict scrutiny. The state’s interest, morality, was not compelling enough; the least restrictive means was not used; and the ordinance was not narrowly tailored. At the onset of the discussion of the case, I intimated that this was not a case of privacy. It is, in fact, a case of the right to the pursuit of happiness. There was no disclosure of private matters. There was no intrusion into the private life of customers. Their rooms were not invaded by unwanted police officers. This was not a case of decisional privacy either, as it did not transgress the free expression of personality, of how to live one's personal life without undue interference from others. The right violated was too trivial, the decision to be made not of an intimate or significant nature. Couples could still pursue sexual activities of their choice, just not within the confines of the motels and inns of the City of Manila. Rather, they were simply prevented from pursuing a leisurely activity in these motels and inns. The Court went overboard in its desire to protect the right to privacy in this case. The Ordinance was valid because it satisfied the rationality test, which was the applicable standard because the liberty involved was not a preferred freedom. Customers would be only inconvenienced by such an ordinance, as they would only be compelled to rent the motel for a longer stay or patronise a motel outside the confines of Manila. Conclusion In this paper, I have explored the meaning of privacy in Philippines law, its aspects, the manner in which the right to privacy may be violated, and the standard of strict scrutiny. I have also discussed informational privacy and decisional privacy, analysing numerous cases that illustrate these aspects of privacy. I have shown that the right to privacy, on the whole, has been protected by Philippine jurisprudence. The only cases where it has not are the Duncan, Disini and Imbong cases. However, 16 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 I have pointed out that the decision in Duncan did not amount to a prohibition of relationships, as Tecson was still free to marry whomever he desired. In Disini, the Court itself was not of the opinion that innocent trysts between consenting adults would be criminally punished by the law. It was only in Imbong that privacy was unprotected. This was due to the pervasive influence of the Catholic Church and its prohibition of the use of contraceptives. References Allen, Anita L (1988) Uneasy Access for Women in a Free Society. New Jersey: Rowman and Littlefield. Benn, Stanley I (1971) ‘Privacy, Freedom, and Respect for Persons’, in J Ronald Pennock and J v Chapman (eds) Nomos XIII, PRIVACY 2. Cortez, Irene (1970) The Constitutional Foundations of the Right to Privacy. Quezon City: UP Law Center. DeCew, Judith WagnerIn Pursuit of Privacy: Law, Ethics, and the Rise of Technology 48 (1997). Emerson, Thomas I (1979) ‘The Right of Privacy and Freedom of the Press’,14 Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Review 329. Feinberg, Joel (1986) Harm to Self: The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, III 1stedn., Oxford: Oxford University Press Fried, Charles (1968) ‘Privacy,’ 77 Yale Law Journal 475. Gavison, Ruth A (1989) ‘Privacy and the Limits of Law’, 89 Yale Law Journal 421. Gunther, Gerald (1972) ‘Foreword: In Search of Evolving Doctrine on a Changing Court: A Model for Newer Equal Protection’, 86 Harvard Law Review 1. Heyman, Steven J (2002) ‘Spheres of Autonomy: Reforming the Content Neutrality Doctrine in First Amendment Jurisprudence’, 10 William and Mary Bill of Rights Journal 647. Inness, Julie C (1992) Privacy, Intimacy, and Isolation (1992). Mill, John Stuart (1990) ‘On Liberty’, in John Gray and GW Smith (eds), JS Mill on Liberty in Focus. New Jersey: Routledge. Moore, Adam (2008) ‘Defining Privacy’,39 Journal of Social Philosophy 411. Posner, Richard A (1977) ‘The Right of Privacy’,12 Georgia Law Review 393. Raz, Joseph (1986) The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Singson, Gabriel C (2001) ‘Law and Jurisprudence on Secrecy of Bank Deposits’, 46 Ateneo Law Journal 670. Solove, Daniel J (2002) ‘Conceptualizing Privacy’,90 California Law Review1087. Tan, Oscar Franklin (2008) ‘The Complete Philippine Right to Privacy’, 82(4) Philippine Law Journal 78. Thomson, Judith J (1975) ‘The Right to Privacy’, 4 Philosophy and Public Affairs 295. Warren, Samuel Dand Brandeis, Louis D (1890) ‘The Right to Privacy’, 4 Harvard Law Review193. Westin, Alan J (2003) ‘Social and Political Dimensions of Privacy’, 59 Journal of Social Issues 2. White, G Edward (1996) ‘The First Amendment Comes of Age: The Emergence of Free Speech in Twentieth-Century America’, 95 Michigan Law Review 299. Legislation Art 26 of the New Civil Code or Republic Act No. 386 (1948). Republic Act No 1405 (1955), the Bank Secrecy Act Republic Act No. 3019 (1960) the Anti-Graft and Corrupt Practices Act. Presidential Decree No 1792 (1981). Manila City Ordinance No 7774 or An Ordinance Prohibiting Short-Time Admission, Short-Time Admission Rates, and WashUp Rate Schemes in Hotels, Motels, Inns, Lodging Houses, Pension Houses, and Similar Establishments in the City of Manila Constitution, 1987, art III and art XV RA No 10354, the Reproductive Health and Responsible Parenthood Act of 2012 Cases Philippine Cases Morfe v Mutuc, GR No L-20387, 31 January 1968; 22 SCRA 424 Cebu Portland Cement v Municipality of Naga, GR Nos. 24116-17, 22 August 1968; 24 SCRA 708 (1968) Resins Inc v Auditor General, GR No L-17888, 29 October 1968; 25 SCRA 754 (1968) Pascual v Board of Examiners, GR No L-25018, 26 May 1969; 28 SCRA 344 Villanueva v Querubin, GR No L-26177, 27 December 1972; 48 SCRA 345 Babst v National Intelligence Board, GR No L-62992, 28 September 1984; 132 SCRA 316 Krohn v CA, GR No 108854, 14 June 1994; 233 SCRA 146 Ty v CA, GR No 122656, 5 September 1997; 278 SCRA 836 Ople v Torres, GR No 127685, 23 July 1998; 293 SCRA 141 Ilusoriov Bildner, GR No 139789, 12 May 2000; 332 SCRA 169 Ilusoriov Bildner, GR No 139789, 19 July 2001; 361 SCRA 427 Estrada v Escritor, A.M. No P-02-1651, 4 August 2003; 408 SCRA 1 Duncan Association v Glaxo-Wellcome, GR No 162994, 17 September 2004; 438 SCRA 343 Ejercito v Sandiganbayan, GR No 157294, 30 November 2006; 509 SCRA 190 Silverio v Republic, GR No 174689, 19 October 2007; 537 SCRA 373 White Light v City of Manila, GR No 122846, 20 January 2009; 576 SCRA 416 17 Australian Journal of Asian Law Vol 19 No 1 Disini v Secretary of Justice, GR No 203335, 11 February 2014; 716 SCRA 237 Imbong v Ochoa, GR No 204819, 08 April 2014; 721 SCRA 146 People v Cogaed, GR No 200334, 30 July 2014; 731 SCRA 427 United States Cases Olmstead v United States, 277 US 438 (1928) United States v Carolene Products Co, 304 US 144 (1938) Thomas v Collins,323 US 516, 530 (1945) Public Utilities Commission v Pollak, 343 US 451 (1952) Braunfieldv Brown, 366 US 599, 612 (1961) Griswold v Connecticut, 381 US 479 (1965) Eisenstadt v Baird, 405 US 438 (1972) Roe v Wade, 410 US113 (1973) Whalen v Roe (429 US 589 (1977) Employment Division v Smith, 494 US 872 (1990) 18