This article was downloaded by: [University of Tennessee At Martin] On: 02 October 2014, At: 23:41 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Ethics, Policy & Environment Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cepe21 What Will it Mean to be Green? Envisioning Positive Possibilities Without Dismissing Loss Cheryl Hall a a University of South Florida , Tampa , USA Published online: 03 Jul 2013. To cite this article: Cheryl Hall (2013) What Will it Mean to be Green? Envisioning Positive Possibilities Without Dismissing Loss, Ethics, Policy & Environment, 16:2, 125-141, DOI: 10.1080/21550085.2013.801182 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2013.801182 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/termsand-conditions Ethics, Policy & Environment, 2013 Vol. 16, No. 2, 125–141, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2013.801182 Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 Target Article What Will it Mean to be Green? Envisioning Positive Possibilities Without Dismissing Loss CHERYL HALL University of South Florida, Tampa, USA ABSTRACT Convinced of the importance of framing, many environmentalists have begun emphasizing positive visions of a happy and healthy green future rather than gloomy pictures of deprivation and sacrifice. ‘Gloom and doom’ discourses foster despair and resistance, they worry, instead of hope and motivation to change. While positive visions are crucial, though, it is ineffective to deny that living more sustainably will involve any loss. Since people value many incompatible things, living more sustainably will inevitably entail both sacrifice and reward. Environmentalists must help articulate new possibilities of a greener future without dismissing the value of what must be given up. What story should we tell ourselves and each other about the state of the physical world we live in, how it got to be that way, and what should be done about it? Should it be a depressing, scary story of humanity’s violations of nature and our impending punishment for these violations? Or should it be an optimistic narrative of the ongoing quest for sustainability, a quest we’re bound to succeed at? Should the story emphasize necessary sacrifices or the benefits of living green? What story should we tell ourselves and each other about how we should feel in this situation? Should the story try to elicit concern, fear, guilt, responsibility, resolve, hope, pride, joy, or what? What difference might different kinds of stories make in motivating action to change the way we live? As concern deepens that we are failing to avert potentially devastating consequences from climate change and biodiversity loss, in addition to many other environmental problems, environmentalists both within and without academia have been rethinking how to approach these problems. The worry is that a negative discourse of ‘gloom and doom’ is counter-productive, fostering resistance, apathy, or despair instead of hope and motivation to change. Convinced of the importance of framing, many people are now aiming to present positive visions of a happy and healthy green future rather than gloomy pictures of deprivation and sacrifice. Activists are using social marketing techniques to cast green issues in a more appealing light while scholars are proposing that sustainable low-carbon modes of life could bring greater freedom, happiness, and well-being than existing highconsumption modes do. This paper traces the contours of this recent trend, examines its assumptions, and evaluates its prospects. I argue that while it is indeed crucial to stress the potential benefits of living more sustainably, it is, nevertheless, ineffective to deny that Correspondence Address: Cheryl Hall, Department of Government and International Affairs, University of South Florida, 4202 E Fowler Ave/SOC107, Tampa, FL, 33620, USA. Email: chall@usf.edu q 2013 Taylor & Francis 126 C. Hall Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 transforming existing ways of life will involve any genuine loss. People value many things, not all of which are compatible. As a result, living more sustainably will inevitably entail both sacrifice and reward—just as living unsustainably inevitably entails both sacrifice and reward. Denying this reality is either wishful thinking or patronizing and consequently unpersuasive. The argument over whether to depict positive visions or necessary sacrifices is thus based on a false choice: it will have to be both. For environmental thinkers, then, the challenge is to help reshape imagination of what a greener future could mean in ways that articulate new possibilities without dismissing the value of what must be given up. The New Focus on Framing and Narrative Frames and narratives have become a frequent topic of concern in environmental discourse (Alexander, 2008; Broder, 2009; de Boer, Wardekker, & Van der Sluijs, 2010; Ereaut & Segnit, 2006; Fletcher, 2009; Maibach et al., 2010; Mann et al., 2009; Miller, 2000; Moser & Dilling, 2007; Nisbet, 2009; Spence & Pidgeon, 2010). This focus indicates a strong sense that ‘information’ about the state of the environment is not the only thing that matters. More than anything, what matters is how information is interpreted, what meaning it holds for people. The argument for the significance of frames and stories depends on at least four propositions. First, current ecological dangers are serious enough that addressing them will likely require making some major changes in the institutions, systems, and infrastructure of many societies. Second, in any society that is at least nominally democratic (and arguably even in societies that are not), making major changes in the institutions, systems, and infrastructure of that society requires at least some level of support from significant numbers of people. Third, such popular support requires changes in how people think and feel about existing ways of life and the possible alternatives to those ways of life. And finally, changes in how people think and feel about a situation depend in turn on changes in the frameworks they use to interpret that situation and the stories they tell each other about it—that is, in the elements of the situation they choose to focus on and the way they put those elements together into a coherent whole. There is reasonable support for each of these claims. The need for humans—and especially those humans who live in advanced industrialized/industrializing countries—to make some major changes in how we interact with the rest of nature is, or should be, clear. The situation may be usefully summarized by comparing humanity’s ecological footprint to the available biological capacity of the planet.1 By this measure, the footprint of the entire human population already exceeds sustainable biological capacity by approximately 50%, and it is continuing to expand rapidly. Focusing more specifically on advanced industrialized countries, the ecological footprint of the United States is about five times too big, for it would take about five planets’ worth of resources and waste sinks for everyone in the world today (let alone larger populations in the future) to live the way that the average person in the United States does (Kitzes et al., 2008, p. 468). In order to achieve a world that is both sustainable and just, then, the population of the United States needs to reduce its ecological footprint by approximately 80%. While the ecological footprints of most European countries are certainly smaller, the required reductions still fall within the 40– 50% range. Meanwhile, in the case of carbon emissions, the situation is much starker. To be sure, there is uncertainty and continued debate over how much carbon dioxide humanity can discharge into the atmosphere without risking ‘unacceptably dangerous’ Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 What will it mean to be green? 127 increases in global temperature. Nevertheless, climate scientists are increasingly arguing for a target of no more than 350 ppm (parts per million) by 2050 in order to keep the increase in global temperature below 28C (Hansen et al., 2008).2 We have already overshot that target: by the end of 2012, the level of carbon in the atmosphere stood at 394 ppm. Getting back down to 350 ppm by 2050 would require global emission cuts of 90% or more (Leahy, Bowden, & Threadgold, 2010, p. 854). And if projected population growth is taken into account, a goal of no more than 350 ppm translates into a global carbon budget of 0.1 tons per person, a whopping 98.5% less than the 6.6 tons emitted per person in the U.S. back in 2002 (Huesemann, 2006, pp. 541 –542). So the populations of advanced industrialized countries need to reduce their ecological and carbon footprints by percentages between 40– 99%. Accomplishing such massive cutbacks will likely require changes in energy use, land use, methods of transportation, residential patterns, agricultural systems, production processes, and levels of consumption, among other things. Indeed, it will likely require fundamental changes to an economic system that is currently predicated on unlimited growth. The hypothesis of a socalled ‘Environmental Kuznets curve,’ in which economic development brings an initial increase in environmental impact followed by an eventual decrease, is not supported by the evidence, especially once global impact is taken into account (York, Rosa, & Dietz, 2003, p. 294). On the contrary, increasing affluence, along with population growth, is one of the main drivers of environmental problems (Brulle, 2010, p. 88; Rosa, York, & Dietz, 2004). Studies show that ‘an increase in per capita GDP consistently leads to an increase in the ecological footprint’ (York et al., 2003, p. 294). Insofar as the existing global economy depends upon permanent economic growth, then, serious reductions in ecological and carbon footprints cannot occur without significant modifications to that economic system.3 Moreover, the popular belief that technological invention will single-handedly provide the key solutions to the most fundamental environmental problems, enabling many other aspects of existing society and culture to remain essentially unchanged, is also misplaced. While technology will undoubtedly be part of the solution, it cannot solve these problems on its own, both because of inherent physical limitations and because technology cannot counteract the effects of unlimited growth in population and consumption—in fact, historically it feeds such growth (Huesemann, 2006; Huesemann & Huesemann, 2008; York et al., 2003, p. 287). As a result, achieving both environmental sustainability and global equity will require significant departures from current ways of life, particularly in industrialized countries—and soon. How can such changes come about? In ‘Reorienting climate change communication for effective mitigation,’ David Ockwell, Lorraine Whitmarsh, and Saffron O’Neill (2009) offer a helpful framework. They describe three main options for effecting change on carbon emissions: top-down, where governments ‘force people to be green’; bottomup, where citizens voluntarily take action to be green; and a bridge between the two, where citizens voluntarily insist that the government regulate everyone’s high carbon behavior (Ockwell et al., 2009, p. 317). Ockwell et al. persuasively argue that the third approach is the most promising—and, therefore, the best target for climate change communication. A purely top-down approach is limited in the depth and sustainability of the changes it can inspire, particularly insofar as citizens resent the regulations the government enacts. Indeed, governments are usually reluctant to pursue such strategies because they fear public backlash come election time (Ockwell et al., 2009, p. 313).4 A purely bottom-up approach is limited in the scope of the changes it can accomplish, 128 C. Hall particularly insofar as individual actions cannot address the systemic, structural influences on levels of carbon emissions (Ockwell et al., 2009, p. 317). It also fails to address the problem of free-riders. So: Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 voluntary action may not work fast enough because of the entrenched social and structural barriers to individuals adopting low carbon lifestyles, while forcing people to be green is politically unpopular, undemocratic, and ultimately unlikely to change values and lifestyles in the long term. (Ockwell et al., 2009, p. 319) The advantage of the third approach is that it combines the strengths of the first two while avoiding some of their weaknesses. Encouraging popular support for governmental action addresses the need for structural changes at the level of the entire society; for rules that require everyone to do their part, thereby guaranteeing both equity and better results; for democratic process; and for positive citizen response to regulation and shifts in priorities, which reduces the political risk involved for elected officials. When big changes are needed, neither governments nor citizens can make them happen on their own. The necessary transformations can only be achieved if the community takes action as a community and if enough people in the community are personally and politically willing to abide by and even demand such action. Of course, the problem is that broad and especially deep popular support for community-wide action on environmental issues such as climate change currently does not exist. In the United States, research suggests that people are generally in favor of addressing environmental problems but not at the cost of other problems they consider to be more important. According to January 2013 data from the Pew Research Center for The People & The Press, only 28% of citizens surveyed ranked ‘dealing with global warming’ a ‘top priority’ for the President and Congress. Out of a total of 21 possible priorities, the goal is ranked dead last. ‘Protecting environment’ fares somewhat better, with 52% considering it a top priority. Still, it ranks twelfth out of 21, far behind the top priorities of ‘strengthening economy,’ ‘improving job situation,’ and ‘reducing budget deficit,’ with the support of 86%, 79% and 72% of those surveyed, respectively (Pew Research Center for the People & The Press, 2013). Hence the need to find ways to encourage citizens in the United States to reconsider our thoughts, feelings, and views about the significance of our current relationship to the rest of nature, the consequences of this relationship, and the necessity to change our ways of life. However, to reconsider thoughts, feelings, and views about complex issues usually means to tell a different story about them. We might use a number of different words here: story, narrative, frame, even— perhaps—theory, if we return to its original sense of ‘vision.’ Frames are concise, stories more extensive, and theories (ideally) fully developed and supported visions. Since there has been a good deal of talk about frames recently, I shall focus on that word for now. What is a ‘frame’? According to Joop de Boer, Arjan Wardekker, and Jeroen P. van der Sluijs, ‘frames are generally conceived as organizing principles that enable a particular interpretation of a phenomenon’ (De Boer et al., 2010, p. 502). Clark Miller emphasizes the shared nature of these principles. As he puts it, ‘writers invoke the concept of “framing” in reference to the perceptual lenses, worldviews or underlying assumptions that guide communal interpretation and definition of particular issues’ (Miller, 2000, p. 211, my emphasis). As Alexa Spence and Nick Pidgeon (among many others) point out, the key to organizing the interpretation of information is selectivity: What will it mean to be green? 129 Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 A frame allows complex issues to be pared down and for some aspects of that issue to be given greater emphasis than others in order that particular audiences can rapidly identify why an issue may be relevant to them. (Spence & Pidgeon, 2010, p. 657, citing Nisbet & Mooney, 2007) Finally, Matthew Nisbet connects frames to narratives: ‘Frames are interpretive storylines that set a specific train of thought in motion, communicating why an issue might be a problem, who or what might be responsible for it, and what should be done about it’ (Nisbet, 2009, p. 4). In other words, by highlighting certain aspects of a situation and leaving other elements out of the storyline, frames convey an analysis of a problem and its solution in a condensed format. Miller and Nisbet both provide useful examples of the concept of framing in their discussions of the various ways that climate change has been (or could be) framed. Miller analyzes how climate change was interpreted within the United States’ scientific policy community in the 1970s. He identifies several different frames of ‘the CO2 problem’ that emerged during this time, each of which corresponded to a different societal narrative and invoked a different response strategy. For example, the ‘global warming’ frame saw carbon emissions in terms of pollution or environmental degradation and led to a call for ‘end-of-pipe’ technology to curb that pollution, while the ‘climatic change’ or ‘weather extremes’ frame focused on the narrative of natural disasters and led to efforts at adaptation and the reduction of vulnerability to disasters (Miller, 2000, p. 216). In similar fashion, Nisbet provides a typology of different ways that any science-related policy may be viewed (Nisbet, 2009, p. 5). Applying this typology to the case of climate change, he considers three frames to be particularly promising for encouraging broad-based support for mitigation efforts: the ‘economic development’ frame, the ‘morality and ethics’ frame (especially as linked to a faith-based notion of responsible stewardship), and the newly emerging ‘public health’ frame (Nisbet, 2009; Maibach et al., 2010). Each of these perspectives on climate change emphasizes a different facet of how to understand the problem and, accordingly, what is to be done about it. Several points about frames are important to stress. First, they are necessarily partial. If one could include everything within a frame, it would no longer be framing anything. While frames are necessarily incomplete, though, they are not thereby necessarily untrue, or at least any more so than language in general, which also inevitably condenses, interprets, organizes, and otherwise shapes reality. To be sure, it is possible to frame an issue in a way that violates essential realities of the situation (for example, to call a law that lowers standards for reducing pollution a ‘Clear Skies Act’)—but this does not mean that all frames of that issue violate essential realities. Finally, frames are unavoidable, particularly in communication. As Nisbet puts it, ‘there is no such thing as unframed information’ (2009, p. 4). The question, then, is not whether to frame, but how. To recap, frames and stories matter because they are important in shaping how people understand the world around them and what needs to be done about it. In order to change how they understand the world, people need to change the frames or stories through which they view the world. Since addressing environmental problems such as climate change and species loss will likely require major changes in social organization and life, and such changes will require popular support, environmentalists need to pay attention to what kinds of frames and stories will facilitate that support and what kinds will not. 130 C. Hall What’s Wrong with ‘Gloom and Doom’? Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 The recent flood of criticism about environmentalism’s ‘gloom and doom’ message can be understood in this context. The contention, whether explicit or implicit, is that gloom and doom is an ineffective frame. Michael Shellenberger and Ted Nordhaus are perhaps the most well-known critics, consistently taking ‘environmentalism’ itself to task for what they consider to be its narrow and overly negative approach.5 The two authors bemoan the lack of a ‘compelling vision for the future’ offered by environmental advocates (Shellenberger & Nordhaus, 2004, p. 30). As they put it, Martin Luther King, Jr.’s ‘I have a dream’ speech is famous because it put forward an inspiring, positive vision that carried a critique of the current moment within it. Imagine how history would have turned out had King given an ‘I have a nightmare’ speech instead. (Shellenberger & Nordhaus, 2004, p. 31)6 Yet, they argue, this is precisely what environmental leaders are doing. The reason leaders should not be painting pictures of apocalypse and cultivating fear is because negativity and fear do not work: ‘Cautionary tales and narratives of eco-apocalypse tend to provoke fatalism, conservatism, and survivalism among voters—not the rational embrace of environmental policies’ (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007b, p. 33). Nordhaus and Shellenberger are hardly alone in arguing that fear is counter-productive. In a New York Times blog post asking, ‘Are words worthless in the climate fight?’ Andrew Revkin cites Tom Lowe of the Center for Risk and Community Safety on the obstacles involved in communicating concerns about climate change. Lowe writes, In the absence of physical evidence that something bad is going to happen, people tend to ‘wait and see’ . . . . A common reaction to this stand-off is for risk communicators to shout louder, to try and shake some sense into people. This is what I see happening with the climate change message. The public are on the receiving end of an increasingly distraught alarm call. The methods used to grab attention are so striking that people are reaching a state of denial. This is partly because the problem is perceived as being so big that people feel unable to do anything about it, partly because the changes associated with impact reduction are unacceptable and/or unviable to many people, and partly because this ‘overselling’ of climate change attracts strong criticism from a vocal and disproportionately publicized few. (Revkin, 2007, p. 6) Lowe’s assessment of the ineffectiveness of the ‘increasingly distraught alarm call’ is repeated in a report by the British Institute for Public Policy Research entitled ‘Warm words: How are we telling the climate story and can we tell it better?’ In the report, Gil Ereaut and Nat Segnit analyze the ‘linguistic repertoires’ used in British popular media coverage and government communications about climate change. They find that the two most common repertoires are what they call the ‘alarmist’ repertoire and the ‘small changes’ repertoire. The ‘alarmist’ repertoire is characterized by an urgent tone, extreme words, and ‘cinematic codes.’ It speaks of acceleration and irreversibility, and employs a ‘quasi-religious register of death and doom’ (Ereaut & Segnit, 2006, p. 7). Unfortunately, they argue, this discourse’s emphasis on the catastrophic danger entailed in climate change Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 What will it mean to be green? 131 tends to overwhelm and distance people: ‘the scale of the problem as it is shown excludes the possibility of real action or agency by the reader or viewer. It contains an implicit counsel of despair—“the problem is just too big for us to take on”’ (Ereaut & Segnit, 2006, p. 7). The ‘small changes’ repertoire attempts to head off such paralysis by encouraging relatively easy actions that ordinary citizens can take to reduce carbon emissions. Its language conveys ‘ease, convenience and effortless agency’ (Ereaut & Segnit, 2006, p. 8). However, when used in conjunction with the alarmist discourse (as it frequently is), this discourse raises the ‘unspoken but obvious question: how can small actions really make a difference to things happening on this epic scale?’ (Ereaut & Segnit, 2006, p. 8). While the criticism of ‘gloom and doom’ is usually offered as a unified reproach, the phrase nevertheless signals two distinct (albeit connected) worries. The first concern is that the picture that environmentalists paint of what needs to be done is too gloomy: we (especially we Northerners) need to sacrifice our comforts and conveniences, to consume far less than we do, in order to save the planet, the global South, and future generations. From now on our lives must be considerably more restrained than they have been, our quality of life seriously reduced. Moreover, we Northerners have no right to protest such deprivation because we have brought this upon ourselves and the rest of the world through our careless, profligate ways. We are the guilty ones. This account, the critics claim, is deeply unappealing. It promises a future devoid of both freedom and happiness. As such, it is virtually guaranteed to be met with serious resistance. The second concern is the picture that environmentalists paint of the present and especially future state of the world is too frightening and overwhelming: the problems are monumental, the hour late, and the resources few—consequently we are all doomed, because there is little most of us can do to solve these problems. This account, the critics contend, is extremely daunting. It elicits both fear and a sense of powerlessness. Building on arguments that fear-based appeals may be ineffective in motivating action (Feinberg & Willer, 2011; Feygina, 2010; Moser & Dilling, 2004; Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2009; O’Neill & Nicholson-Cole, 2009; Revkin, 2006), critics maintain that a discourse of doom is ill-advised.7 Finally, adding doom to gloom only makes matters worse. For in emphasizing the magnitude and intractability of environmental problems, the narrative only further undermines any personal willingness people may have to live within limits. Why sacrifice if it will not make any real difference? What is the point? Thus, the argument declares, a doom and gloom approach backfires, inspiring resistance, despair, withdrawal, and fatalism rather than personal/political action for change. Alternatives to Gloom and Doom: Hope and Possibility If the concern is that the frame of gloom and doom is ineffective, then clearly the solution is to tell a more positive, inspiring story. As with the critique of gloom and doom, the proposed alternative has two distinct facets: to replace gloomy images of deprivation and restriction, authors offer a hopeful vision of a happy and free green life, while to replace doom-filled warnings of impending disaster, they provide an empowering description of what we can achieve if we work together (whoever ‘we’ are). Needless to say, although each narrative emphasizes a different corrective, the two are often deeply intertwined. Let us begin with the hopeful visions of a happy and free green life, focusing first on the argument about happiness. Frames that focus on the fulfillment that could come from living more sustainably are becoming increasingly common. A few examples can serve to Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 132 C. Hall illustrate the trend. Juliet Schor has been arguing for at least 20 years that the ecologically unsustainable levels of production and consumption that Americans, in particular, engage in do not lead to happier lives, as many people assume, but rather to alienation, exhaustion and dissatisfaction. In her most recent book, Plenitude (Schor, 2010), she emphasizes that the model she is advocating—working and spending less, creating and connecting more— is ‘not a paradigm of sacrifice. To the contrary, it involves a way of life that will yield more well-being than sticking to business as usual . . . ’ (Schor, 2010, p. 2). In ‘A shallow route to environmentally friendly happiness,’ Chrisoula Andreou also argues that, beyond a certain minimum level, increases in wealth are not associated with increases in happiness. However, Andreou departs from the familiar lofty argument that the reason we are not happier when we have more material goods is because genuine happiness only comes from non-material goods. Instead, she emphasizes recent empirical evidence that the reason we are not happier when we have more material goods is, in great part, because we are comparative animals: the pleasure we get from material goods depends on how much everyone else has (Andreou, 2010, p. 12). When other people have more as well, our happiness is not increased. Andreou finds hope for the environment in this phenomenon, because it suggests that we could be ‘as happy with much less, so long as others, particularly [our] peers, also have much less’ (Andreou, 2010, p. 15). In ‘Living green and living well: Climate change and the low-carbon imaginary,’ Steve Vanderheiden worries that calling on people to sacrifice in order to mitigate climate change will not work, particularly because in this case (unlike in wartime) the sacrifices involved must be permanent. Since ‘it stands as a truism that we all want to live well’ (Vanderheiden, 2010, p. 2), the better course is to challenge the norms that presume a connection between consumption and welfare, and thus a conflict between ‘living green’ and ‘living well.’ Drawing on Schor’s defense of downshifting, John de Graaf, David Wann, and Thomas Naylor’s critique of ‘affluenza,’ and Michael Pollan’s defense of the slow food movement, Vanderheiden contends that reducing competitive consumption and eating sustainable food can increase leisure time, the quality of our personal relationships, and the pleasure we find in food (Vanderheiden, 2010, pp. 14– 17). These sorts of revisions to existing norms can help to construct a new ‘low-carbon imaginary’ that presents the necessary changes as attractive rather than sacrificial. Frames that focus on the freedom that could come from living more sustainably are somewhat less common but still significant. Jonathan Porritt points out that the accusation that environmentalists want to take away people’s freedom rests on an understanding of ‘freedom’ as consumer choice within an exponentially expanding economy. But the freedom offered by infinite growth is only an illusion. Meanwhile, the environmental movement has not said enough about the complexities of defending real freedom of choice within a sustainable society. It is not articulating as it should the proposition that people would in fact lead richer, healthier, better lives in a sustainable (or ‘stationery’) society, and would, therefore, in so many different ways be more free. (Porritt, 1995, pp. 18– 19) They would, for example, be free not to have to consume and ‘not to be subsumed into an inherently irrational and destructive economy’ (Porritt, 1995, p. 19). Jason Lambacher echoes Porritt’s point that freedom has often been defined in opposition to limits. As a result, respecting ecological limits has seemed to require restraining freedom (Lambacher, Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 What will it mean to be green? 133 2009, p. 2). However, this exclusive definition of freedom can and should be challenged. Lambacher distinguishes between ecologically irresponsible forms of freedom, which ignore limits, promote ‘context-less individualism,’ and deny obligations to non-human others, and ecologically responsible forms of freedom, which do not. For Lambacher, being free means, among other things, being able to restrain ourselves (Lambacher, 2009, p. 41). If freedom is ‘the law we give to ourselves,’ then to live more responsibly means to live more freely (Lambacher, 2009, p. 38). Understanding freedom in this way allows us to ‘[harness] the aspiration toward freedom, rather than assuming it can only be part of the problem’ (Lambacher, 2009, p. 28). Finally, Richard Dagger also emphasizes freedom as autonomy and self-government. Drawing on Philip Pettit’s distinction between optionfreedom and agency-freedom, he argues that having more options (for example, more choices of things to buy) does not always lead to greater autonomy. What matters is that we have options that promote the ability to be self-governing. This means that we must be able to enjoy a reasonably secure sense of the self as something that is not simply the plaything of external forces or the creature of ungovernable impulses. (Dagger, 2006, p. 212) In the case of our relationship to the environment, this in turn means learning to curb selfdestructive tendencies that threaten the natural systems that support us. Again, if we can learn to do this, we will actually be freer than we are now. Let us now turn to frames that emphasize human power and agency rather than the inescapable doom of a looming catastrophe. Here Nordhaus and Shellenberger offer such an unparalleled example that I confine myself to discussing them. Over and over, the two counsel against apocalyptic narratives that, they argue, engender fear and fatalism. At the foundation of Nordhaus and Shellenberger’s argument is the claim that people are more productive and more generous when they feel strong and in control of their lives (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, pp. 187, 222). If this is the case, then motivating action on issues such as climate change requires focusing on people’s strengths and abilities, not their weaknesses. Responding to the tragic stories that bemoan human arrogance and ecological failure, they write: There is a very different story that can be told about human history, one that embraces our agency, and that is the story of constant human overcoming. Whereas the tragic story imagines that humans have fallen, the narrative of overcoming imagines that we have risen . . . . Not only have we survived, we’ve thrived . . . . The narrative of overcoming helps us to imagine and thus create a brighter future. Human societies will continue to stumble. Many will fall. But we have overcome starvation, disease, deprivation, oppression, and war. We can overcome ecological crises. (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, pp. 150 –151, their emphasis) The implication is clear: without a narrative of how human beings have successfully overcome obstacles and can continue to do so, we will be unable to imagine or create a brighter future. This is why stories must strive to inspire feelings of joy, gratitude and pride: because stories that inspire feelings of regret, guilt, sadness, and fear will not foster the optimistic attitude necessary to solve the problems we face (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, p. 153). Notably, Nordhaus and Shellenberger explicitly identify Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 134 C. Hall this approach as a form of cognitive therapy. Cognitive therapy encourages depressed patients to reorganize the narratives they tell themselves, focusing on different experiences and reinterpreting the meaning of their lives in more positive ways, in order to ‘become the person [they want] to be’ (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, p. 217). Thus, environmentalists (and other progressives) need to switch from a negative frame that emphasizes all the things people must stop doing to a positive frame that focuses attention on our potential to be creative—to invent new solutions (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, p. 120). Instead of thinking of climate change as a pollution problem that requires more regulation and restriction, we should think of it as a clean energy problem that requires ‘unleashing human power’ (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, p. 113). In this light, Nordhaus and Shellenberger have been strong supporters of the Apollo Alliance, a coalition working to promote investment in the development of clean energy technology and green jobs. Of course, in referencing the Apollo Project to send an American to the moon, the Apollo Alliance means to call to mind American technological leadership and ‘can-do spirit’ (Anon, n.d.). The approach is a perfect example of the frame that Nordhaus and Shellenberger advocate. What Could be Wrong with Hope and Possibility? It is important to tell a story about humanity’s relationship to the rest of nature that is not just gloom and doom—now more so than ever. As argued above, better technology, while no doubt part of the answer, will not single-handedly solve the most pressing environmental problems. To solve these problems, people in advanced industrialized countries will need to forego current high-carbon, high-consumption ways of life, while people in lesser-developed countries will need to forego whatever aspirations they may have to emulate those ways of life. The necessary transformations can only be achieved democratically if enough people are personally and politically willing to support them. Yet people usually are not willing to change their lives and dreams unless they have a clear idea of how doing so will make a significant and beneficial difference. Hence the need for alternative stories. Since the dominant narrative emphasizes the freedom, power, and happiness entailed in a high-carbon, high-consumption lifestyle, environmentalists need to challenge the assumptions of that narrative. That is to say, we need to help people reimagine what it might mean to be free, powerful, and happy. At the same time, telling a story that is all hope and possibility has some limitations. To explain how and why, let me begin by pointing out that, while the authors discussed above all agree on the importance of replacing a gloom and doom frame with a more positive one, they do not agree on the specific individual, social, economic, and political changes necessary to solve problems such as climate change and biodiversity loss. The question is not just how to ‘communicate’ about these problems; the question is what needs to be done about them. And the answers range from reformist to radical. In spite of their rousing, revolutionary-sounding rhetoric, Nordhaus and Shellenberger are decidedly reformist in their recommendations. They do not endorse any significant alterations in the economic system, political structure, or culture of consumption in advanced industrialized countries. They explicitly disavow any need for people in these countries to change their everyday behavior (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2011, sec. Fourth Thesis). They see no need, for example, for humans to eat lower on the food chain or return to smaller-scale organic forms of agriculture. They do not advocate either political decentralization or Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 What will it mean to be green? 135 more effective global governance. Nor do they call for a rejection of the imperative of economic growth; on the contrary, they see continued economic growth as crucial. For Nordhaus and Shellenberger, the fundamental solution to the problem is massive public investment in the development of clean energy technology. In their own words, ‘the solution to the ecological crises wrought by modernity, technology, and progress will be more modernity, technology, and progress’ (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2011, sec. Twelfth Thesis). In contrast, many of the other authors discussed above recommend more profound changes in current patterns of consumption, energy use, reliance on high-risk forms of technology, land use, methods of transportation, agricultural practices, political institutions, and economic systems. The problem with a narrative that is overly focused on hope and possibility depends on the solution being advocated. In the case where the story points to a reformist solution, as Nordhaus and Shellenberger’s does, the problem lies with the solution itself. This frame is cheery, confident, and reassuring, downplaying difficulties and any need for sacrifice. The reason it can do this is because the proposed solution maintains much of the status quo, including existing institutions, practices, standards of living, and values. Since the status quo in advanced industrialized countries supports a relatively privileged way of life, particularly in comparison to life elsewhere, little sacrifice is indeed called for here. (Or perhaps better put: little sacrifice of the comforts and conveniences of current forms of advanced industrialized life is called for, while the less obvious sacrifices already entailed in this way of life are ignored.8) Given the scope of the problem, though, a solution such as the one offered by Nordhaus and Shellenberger is not sufficient. In putting their faith almost entirely in economic growth and the expectation of technological progress, they underestimate the changes needed. Once again, technology cannot do the job on its own, and economic growth intensifies ecological destruction more than it reduces it. If everything Nordhaus and Shellenberger advocate were done, the biggest problems would remain, and might even be worse. In the case of the reformist story, then, the optimism of the frame reflects the optimism of the solution, but it does not get us where we need to go. The hope that this story provides is false, because the proposed solution is too shallow to solve the problem.9 In the case where the story of hope and possibility points to a more radical solution, the problem is different. Unlike the first story, the second story means to point to changes big enough to address the depth of the problem. In emphasizing what will be gained, though, it does not adequately account for what must be given up. Instead, the tendency is to argue that people in advanced industrialized countries are not actually benefiting from current ways of life; therefore, it’s no great sacrifice (indeed, maybe not even a small sacrifice) to change how they’re living. Whereas in the reformist story no sacrifice is involved because no real change is involved, in this story, no (real) sacrifice is involved because the change, while real, is supposed to be entirely for the better. However it is not effective to maintain that no real sacrifice will be involved in the transition from high-carbon, high-consumption ways of life. For even if the change will be for the better overall—that is to say, even if most people stand to gain a good deal more than they lose by living more sustainably—it does not follow that no loss is entailed. A low-carbon lifestyle may indeed offer some genuinely valuable goods, such as better tasting food, more leisure time, or stronger neighborhood communities. Yet a high-carbon lifestyle also offers some genuinely valuable goods: to mention only one, the ability to travel long distances quickly and easily, and thus to more easily visit far-flung family and Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 136 C. Hall friends, take advantage of work opportunities in distant places, and experience a wide variety of different cultures first-hand. It is quite possible that frequent, widespread travel by jet plane is not a sustainable practice. If plane travel must be seriously reduced in order to prevent dangerous levels of climate change, is this not a significant sacrifice—albeit for a crucial cause? The point is that people value many different things. Inevitably, some of the things we care about will conflict with other things we care about. As a result, the reality is that living more sustainably will unavoidably entail both sacrifice and reward— just as living unsustainably unavoidably entails both sacrifice and reward. Ignoring this reality is either inaccurate in missing what it is that people value in existing ways of life, or patronizing in implying that people are essentially suffering from false consciousness about what is truly valuable in life. Yet a frame that is inaccurate or patronizing will not be persuasive. People in overdeveloped countries can see that some loss of what they currently value will be involved in the transition to a low-carbon, low-consumption way of life. Although they may not realize what they are currently sacrificing in order to have what they have now, they do realize what they are going to need to sacrifice to live more sustainably. Even if they reevaluate what matters to them, not everything they will have to give up is worthless. Refusing to acknowledge this fact risks a serious loss of credibility with the audience one is hoping to reach. So the reformist story is optimistic and inspiring in great part because the solution is too shallow, while the more radical story is optimistic and inspiring, at least in part, because it overlooks or dismisses the losses entailed in living differently. Its solution is deep but the story about it is too shallow. As a result, neither frame is sufficient. In the first case, the story is too good to be true; in the second case, it will be seen to be too good to be true. To get past this dilemma, environmental thinkers and activists must embrace the need for a more profound transformation of life in industrialized and industrializing countries and rewrite the story about this transformation in a way that allows for complexity in people’s values and appreciation of the inevitability of sacrifice in any way of life. Currently, many environmentalists advise against any discussion of sacrifice because they perceive it to be inherently opposed to a positive vision. Recall Juliet Schor’s claim that the model of plenitude is ‘not a paradigm of sacrifice. To the contrary, it involves a way of life that will yield more well-being than sticking to business as usual’ (2010, p. 2, my emphasis). Here, sacrifice and well-being are entirely opposed. Steve Vanderheiden echoes this opposition. We need, he says, to reconcile the goal of ‘living well’ with the goal of ‘living green,’ but a frame of sacrifice ‘treats these as incompatible aims that require the former to give way to the latter.’ Moreover, ‘By casting voluntary reductions in personal consumption as a kind of sacrifice, critics of unsustainable consumption forfeit the ability to question the alleged incompatibility between living green and living well’ (Vanderheiden, 2010, p. 6). These arguments rely on a common interpretation of sacrifice as essentially synonymous with deprivation or self-denial. A closer look at the concept, however, reveals a far more complex picture. As defined in the New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, sacrifice is ‘the surrender of something valued or desired, especially one’s life, for the sake of something regarded as more important or worthy, or in order to avoid a greater loss, reduce expenditure, etc.’ To be sure, then, sacrifice involves foregoing or giving up something one cares about—but only for the sake of something else one cares about even more. In this way, sacrifice is decidedly not the same as simple deprivation or self-denial (Meyer, 2010, pp. 14– 17). It entails loss but it also entails gain. Indeed, the point of the concept is that the gain is considered more important than the loss, else the sacrifice would not be undertaken. Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 What will it mean to be green? 137 Thus, articulating the need for some level of sacrifice in moving toward more sustainable forms of life in no way precludes presenting a vision of how people’s lives would be improved by doing so. Quite the reverse: it actually requires a vision of improvement, because there must be something of greater value to inspire the sacrifice in the first place. I suspect that the fundamental obstacle in the quarrel about the frame of sacrifice is the presumption that this greater value can only benefit others, not oneself. The sacrifice involved in ‘living green’ (if it is a sacrifice) must be undertaken to save the whales or the polar bears, or to protect ‘the environment’ as a whole, or at best to preserve it for the sake of future human generations—not to live well oneself. However, this need not be the case. One can sacrifice something that benefits oneself personally (say, the greater convenience of packaged food) for the sake of something else that also benefits oneself personally (say, the better nutrition and taste of food one prepares at home). Furthermore, even if one is sacrificing at least in part for the sake of others, to assume that there is no personal benefit in doing so relies on an overly individualistic view of what counts as a person’s well-being. Living well is not just about one’s own individual material well-being. It is, or at least certainly can be, about one’s physical, emotional and spiritual well-being and the well-being of anyone or anything else one cares about. A sacrifice made for the sake of a child, a friend, even a stranger or nonhuman animal can be and often is experienced as part of a ‘good life’ for oneself. For this reason, recognizing that ‘voluntary reductions in personal consumption’ may involve some sacrifice in no way requires that one ‘forfeit the ability to question the alleged incompatibility between living green and living well’ (Vanderheiden, 2010, p. 6). It merely acknowledges the reality that there are some incompatibilities between some forms of living green and some forms of living well, just as there are some incompatibilities between many, if not most, other choices we make about how to live. It is not possible for any of us, individually or collectively, to have everything we want. As a result, any way of life necessarily entails some sacrifice and—because this is the whole point of sacrifice—some reward for that sacrifice. In the case of living green, that reward may well include both an increase in personal material well-being and an increase in other facets of one’s well-being or the well-being of others. The fear that any discussion of sacrifice must inevitably lead to an entirely gloomy picture is unwarranted, and stands in the way of a realistic account of the choices we face in life. Conclusion Positive visions about what it might mean to be green are badly needed. There is no doubt that a story of gloom and doom on its own is not sufficient. However, a purely optimistic message is not sufficient, either. A story that focuses only on what will be gained in living more sustainably necessarily dismisses either the seriousness of how much needs to be changed or the seriousness of people’s perceptions about the many different, even conflicting, things one might value in life. A stronger frame would give both of these issues their due. In particular, it would acknowledge and respect people’s existing values and honestly incorporate their realistic concerns about losing at least some of the things they value. At the same time, it would encourage deeper exploration of where existing values conflict, and how and why values might be understood or prioritized differently. That is to say, it would help people to look at the situation differently, to re-think and refeel what matters to them and why. A stronger story would help people to re-imagine what 138 C. Hall it could mean to be free, happy and powerful without insisting that there is no true happiness, freedom, or power as things stand. There is no dichotomy between acknowledging the need for sacrifice and articulating the rewards such sacrifices can bring. Environmentalists can and must encourage reflection on both. Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 Acknowledgements I am grateful to the following people for constructive feedback at various stages in my work on this paper and the larger project of which it is a part: Max Boykoff, Sheri Breen, Mark Brown, Peter Cannavò, Deserai Crow, Ben Hale, Lauren Hartzell Nichols, James Lowe, John Meyer, Zev Trachtenberg, Kerry Whiteside, Justin Williams, Harlan Wilson, Rafi Youatt, and Michael Zimmerman. I am also grateful to two anonymous referees and additional audience participants at panels at the International Conference on Culture, Politics, and Climate Change and annual meetings of the Western Political Science Association. Finally, I thank the Humanities Institute at the University of South Florida for much appreciated funding in the form of a summer grant. Notes An ecological footprint is the ‘area of biologically productive land and water that a population . . . uses to generate the resources it consumes and absorb its wastes under prevailing technology’ (Kitzes et al., 2008, p. 468). Ecological footprint calculations are admittedly somewhat controversial; still, they can serve as rough estimates. 2 Indeed, the situation may be even worse, as some climate change scientists have recently argued that even an increase of 28C will prove quite dangerous (Anderson & Bows, 2010, p. 23). 3 On the question of climate change, climate scientists Anderson and Bows note the common and telling view that ‘reductions in [carbon] emissions in excess of 3 –4% per year are not compatible with economic growth’ (2010, p. 40). This view has led policy advisers to reject proposals for larger reductions. Unfortunately, Anderson and Bows argue, considerably larger reductions are needed to have even a reasonable chance of keeping global temperature increase below 28C. They reach a blunt conclusion: ‘(extremely) dangerous climate change can only be avoided if economic growth is exchanged, at least temporarily, for a period of planned austerity within Annex 1 nations and a rapid transition away from fossil-fuelled development within non-Annex 1 nations’ (2010, p. 41). 4 I would add that they may well fear corporate backlash even more. 5 Although Shellenberger and Nordhaus offer broad criticism of an entire movement, their specific complaints were developed in the course of interviewing ‘more than 25 of the [U.S.] environmental community’s top leaders, thinkers, and funders’ (Shellenberger & Nordhaus, 2004, p. 4). In other words, they focused primarily on the leadership of mainstream environmental organizations in the United States. Interestingly, whether due to their influence or not, major organizations such as the Environmental Defense Fund, the Sierra Club, and the National Resources Defense Council currently tell a story that, in significant respects, is much closer to the one that Shellenberger and Nordhaus advocate than the one they decry. In particular, they tend to emphasize win/win strategies, such as the economic benefits of green jobs. 6 In Break Through, Nordhaus and Shellenberger clarify that King in fact began his speech with a nightmare—but that this beginning only shows how important it was to move on to his dream (Nordhaus & Shellenberger, 2007a, pp. 2–4). 7 It is important to note that the claim that fear-based appeals are ineffective is disputed. Other research suggests that results depend greatly on whether people are addressed as individuals or as members of a community, and whether or not fear appeals are combined with guidance for effective group action (Camill, 2010; van Zomeren, Spears, & Leach, 2010; Witte & Allen, 2000). 8 For more on the notion of unacknowledged sacrifices already being made, see the discussions in several chapters of The Environmental Politics of Sacrifice (Maniates & Meyer, 2010). 1 What will it mean to be green? Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 9 139 Or to use Rebecca Solnit’s terminology, those who argue that we can rely on technological progress for salvation, as Nordhaus and Shellenberger do, offer optimism rather than genuine hope. According to Solnit, hope is crucial but we should not ‘mistake hope for optimism. Optimism and pessimism are siblings in their certainty. They believe they know what will happen next, with one slight difference: Optimists expect everything to turn out nicely without any effort being expended toward that goal. Pessimists assume that we’re doomed and there’s nothing to do about it except try to infect everyone else with despair while there’s still time . . . . Hope, on the other hand, is based on uncertainty, on the much more realistic premise that we don’t know what will happen next’ (Solnit, 2011). Of course, Nordhaus and Shellenberger are hardly arguing that no effort needs to be expended. Nevertheless, they are essentially arguing that ordinary citizens need expend no effort other than to agree to fund scientific research and its application by their government, and all will be well. It is in this sense that they offer optimism rather than hope. I thank John Meyer for bringing Solnit to my attention and encouraging me to think about the distinction between hope and optimism. References Alexander, R. (2008). Framing discourse on the environment: A critical discourse approach. New York: Routledge. Anderson, K., & Bows, A. (2010). Beyond ‘dangerous’ climate change: emission scenarios for a new world. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 369 (1934), 20–44. Andreou, C. (2010). A shallow route to environmentally friendly happiness: Why evidence that we are shallow materialists need not be bad news for the environment(alist). Ethics, Place & Environment: A Journal of Philosophy & Geography, 13(1), 1–10. Anon. (n.d.). Apollo Alliance: Clean energy and good jobs j Mission. Retrieved from http://apolloalliance.org/ about/mission/ Broder, J. M. (2009). Seeking to save the planet, with a thesaurus. The New York Times. Retrieved from http:// www.nytimes.com/2009/05/02/us/politics/02enviro.html Brulle, R. J. (2010). From environmental campaigns to advancing the public dialog: Environmental communication for civic engagement. Environmental Communication, 4(1), 82–98. Camill, P. (2010). Climate communication: Is fear þ collective action a winning strategy? Global Change: Intersection of Nature and Culture. Retrieved from http://www.globalchangeblog.com/2010/03/climatecommunication-is-fear-collective-action-a-winning-strategy/ Dagger, R. (2006). Freedom and rights. In A. Dobson & R. Eckersley (Eds.), Political theory and the ecological challenge (pp. 200–215). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. De Boer, J., Wardekker, J. A., & Van der Sluijs, J. P. (2010). Frame-based guide to situated decision-making on climate change. Global Environmental Change, 20(3), 502– 510. Ereaut, G., & Segnit, N. (2006). Warm words: How are we telling the climate story and can we tell it better? London: Institute for Public Policy Research. Retrieved from www.ippr.org Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2011). Apocalypse soon? Psychological Science, 22(1), 34–38. Feygina, I. (2010). System justification, the denial of global warming, and the possibility of ‘system-sanctioned change’. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 36(3), 326–338. Fletcher, A. (2009). Clearing the air: The contribution of frame analysis to understanding climate policy in the United States. Environmental Politics, 18(5), 800–816. Hansen, J., Sato, M., Kharecha, P., Beerling, D., Berner, R., Masson-Delmotte, V., . . . Zachos, J.C. (2008). Target atmospheric CO2: Where should humanity aim? arXiv:0804.1126. Retrieved from http://arxiv.org/ abs/0804.1126 Huesemann, M. (2006). Can advances in science and technology prevent global warming? Mitigation and Adaptation Strategies for Global Change, 11(3), 539–577. Huesemann, M., & Huesemann, J. (2008). Will progress in science and technology avert or accelerate global collapse? A critical analysis and policy recommendations. Environment, Development and Sustainability, 10(6), 787–825. Kitzes, J., Wackernagel, M., Loh, J., Peller, A., Goldfinger, S., Cheng, D., & Tea, K., (2008). Shrink and share: Humanity’s present and future ecological footprint. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 363(1491), 467– 475. Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 140 C. Hall Lambacher, J. (2009). Limits of freedom and the freedom of limits: Responding to the extinction crisis with responsibility, restraint, and joy. SSRN eLibrary Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, (pp. 1 – 47). Toronto, Canada. Retrieved from http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm? abstract_id¼1451845 Leahy, T., Bowden, V., & Threadgold, S. (2010). Stumbling towards collapse: Coming to terms with the climate crisis. Environmental Politics, 19(6), 851–868. Maibach, E., Nisbet, M., Baldwin, P., Akerlof, K., & Diao, G., (2010). Reframing climate change as a public health issue: An exploratory study of public reactions. BMC Public Health, 10(299), 1–11. Maniates, M. F. & Meyer, J. M. (Eds.). (2010). The environmental politics of sacrifice. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Mann, M., Kinzig, A., Miller, C., Schmidt, G., Henson, R., & Nisbet, M., (2009). Is there a better word for doom? SeedMagazine.com. Retrieved from http://seedmagazine.com/content/article/ is_there_a_better_word_for_doom/ Meyer, J. M. (2010). A democratic politics of sacrifice? In M. Maniates & J. Meyer (Eds.), The environmental politics of sacrifice (pp. 13–32). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Miller, C. (2000). The dynamics of framing environmental values and policy: Four models of societal processes. Environmental Values, 9, 211 –234. Moser, S., & Dilling, L. (2004). Making climate hot: Communicating the urgency and challenge of global climate change. Environment: Science and Policy for Sustainable Development, 46(10), 32–46. Moser, S., & Dilling, L. (2007). Creating a climate for change: Communicating climate change and facilitating social change (reissue). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Nisbet, M. (2009). Communicating climate change: Why frames matter for public engagement. Environment Magazine: Science and Policy for Sustainable Development. Retrieved from http://www. environmentmagazine.org/Archives/Back%20Issues/March-April%202009/Nisbet-full.html Nordhaus, T., & Shellenberger, M. (2007a). Break through: From the death of environmentalism to the politics of possibility. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co. Nordhaus, T., & Shellenberger, M. (2007b). Second life: A manifesto for a new environmentalism. The New Republic, 30–33. Nordhaus, T., & Shellenberger, M. (2009). Apocalypse fatigue: Losing the public on climate change. Yale Environment 360. Retrieved from http://thebreakthrough.org/blog/Yale%20Environment%20360%3A% 20Apocalypse%20Fatigue%3A%20Losing%20the%20Public%20on%20Climate%20Change.pdf Nordhaus, T., & Shellenberger, M. (2011). The long death of environmentalism. Retrieved from http:// thebreakthrough.org/blog/2011/02/the_long_death_of_environmenta.shtml. O’Neill, S., & Nicholson-Cole, S. (2009). ‘Fear won’t do it’: Promoting positive engagement with climate change through visual and iconic representations. Science Communication, 30(3), 355–379. Ockwell, D., Whitmarsh, L., & O’Neill, S. (2009). Reorienting climate change communication for effective mitigation. Science Communication, 30(3), 305 –327. Pew Research Center for the People & The Press. (2013). Deficit reduction rises on public’s agenda for Obama’s second term: Public’s policy priorities: 1996–2013. Pew Research Center for the People & The Press. Retrieved from http://www.people-press.org/2013/01/24/deficit-reduction-rises-on-publics-agendafor-obamas-second-term/ Porritt, J. (1995). Liberty and sustainability: Where one person’s freedom is another’s nuisance. London: John Stuart Mill Institute. Revkin, A. (2006). Yelling ‘fire’ on a hot planet. The New York Times. Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/ 2006/04/23/weekinreview/23revkin.html?agewanted¼all. Revkin, A. (2007). Are words worthless in the climate fight? Dot Earth, NYTimes.com. Retrieved from http:// dotearth.blogs.nytimes.com/2007/12/03/are-words-worthless-in-the-climate-fight/ Rosa, E. A., York, R., & Dietz, T. (2004). Tracking the Anthropogenic Drivers of Ecological Impacts. Ambio, 33 (8), 509 –512. Schor, J. B. (2010). Plenitude: The new economics of true wealth. New York: The Penguin Press. Shellenberger, M., & Nordhaus, T. (2004). The death of environmentalism: Global warming politics in a postenvironmental world. Retrieved from www.thebreakthrough.org/PDF/Death_of_Environmentalism.pdf Solnit, R. (2011). Hope: The care and feeding of Grist. Retrieved from http://grist.org/living/2011-08-02-hopethe-care-and-feeding-of/ Spence, A., & Pidgeon, N. (2010). Framing and communicating climate change: The effects of distance and outcome frame manipulations. Global Environmental Change, 20(4), 656– 667. What will it mean to be green? 141 Downloaded by [University of Tennessee At Martin] at 23:42 02 October 2014 Van Zomeren, M., Spears, R., & Leach, C. (2010). Experimental evidence for a dual pathway model analysis of coping with the climate crisis. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 30(4), 339– 346. Vanderheiden, S. (2010). Living green and living well: Climate change and the low-carbon imaginary Paper presented at Annual Meeting of the Western Political Science Association, (pp. 1– 23). San Francisco, CA. Witte, K., & Allen, M. (2000). A meta-analysis of fear appeals: Implications for effective public health campaigns. Health Education & Behavior, 27(5), 591–615. York, R., Rosa, E. A., & Dietz, T. (2003). Footprints on the earth: The environmental consequences of modernity. American Sociological Review, 68(2), 279–300.