International Phenomenological Society Descriptive Phenomenology and Constructivism Author(s): Hans Seigfried Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 37, No. 2 (Dec., 1976), pp. 248-261 Published by: International Phenomenological Society Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2107196 Accessed: 18-04-2020 00:28 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and Phenomenological Research This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DISCUSSION DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM Phenomenologists, committing themselves to the description of the life-world, frequently criticize scientific knowledge for being abstract and constructivistic. Discussing the relationship between ontology and science in a Heideggerian context, I dismiss such criticism by arguing that the pheomena which phenomenology describes are by their very nature constructions and that phenomenology itself is nothing but a method modeled on that of the sciences and designed to finally turn philosophy into a strict science after centuries of random speculation. Phenomenology, consequently, cannot function as a basis for diatribes against science and technology. Heidegger's main concern in his phenomenological period was, as for EHusserl, the justification and foundation of scientific knowl- edge (Grundlegung der Wissenschaften). The very idea of fundamental ontology is proof of it because it is the explicit task of funda- mental ontology to lay the foundations for regional ontologies which in turn provide the foundations for the various positive sciences. A most decisive step in the clarification of the idea of a fundamental ontology is the differentiation between ontology and science, between the procedures of ontological and of positive scientific research. The task of fundamental ontology is to exhibit the ontological fundaments of scientific knowledge by securing access to the structure of the being of entities themselves through the "disclosure of the internal possibility of the comprehension of being" (K, 242).1 However, Heidegger's characterization of such access seems to be so vague, ambiguous, and even contradictory, that it becomes nearly impossible to distinguish ontological from scientific research procedures. On the one hand, Heidegger insists that such access and disclosure is possible "only through the understanding insofar as this has the character of projection (Entwurf)," and that "the explicit achievement of projection . . . is necessarily construction (Konstruk- 1 M. Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. by J. S. Churchi (2nd ed.; Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1965), p. 242. Abbreviated in the t as K, followed by the page reference. Occasionally I changed the translation where felt it to be misleading or unnecessarily obscure. This also holds for my quotation from Being and Time. 248 This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 249 tion)" (K, 240f). From this one could conclude that the difference between the procedures of ontology and science cannot be the difference between description and construction but only between two forms of construction, granted, of course, that scientific procedures are constructive. On the other hand, Heidegger claims that ontology, which exhibits the ontological fundaments of scientific explanations by disclosing their a priori, is not "a-prioristic construction," but that it is empirical, descriptive, and phenomenological (BT, 490nx, 60, 62).2 In other words, "only as phenomenology, is ontology possible" (BT, 60), for "the term 'phenomenology' expresses a maxim which can be formulated as 'To the things themselves!' It is opposed to all freefloating constructions and accidental findings; it is opposed to taking over any conceptions which only seem to have been demonstrated; it is opposed to those pseudo-questions which parade themselves as 'problems,' often for generations at a time" (BT, 50). Scientific research, in contrast, Heidegger claims, takes over its "basic concepts" (Grundbegriffe), which it uses as "proximal clues for disclosing" a particular area of research "concretely and for the first time," naively and without demonstration from "our pre-scientific ways of exper- iencing and interpreting" that area (BT, 29). Occasional and more or less radical revisions of such concepts, if not transparent to the scientists, lead to research crises. The special and monumental task of ontological research is to prevent and overcome such crises through the clarification and justification (verification: K, 241) of such 'basic concepts' (BT, 29-31). And from this one could conclude that the difference between the procedures of ontology and scienc must be the difference between phenomenological description an free-floating, abstract construction. However, I think that textual and conceptual analyses can dissolve this seeming contradiction in the differentiation between the procedures of ontology and science and by so doing shed light on some high-flown claims by some phenomenologists as to the justifi- cation and verification of scientific knowledge. There are many ways of defining the task and program of pheno-' 2 M. Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. by J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), pp. 490 (note x), 60, 62. Abbreviated in the text as BT, followed by the page reference. This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 250 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH menology.3 The most common one today is still that it is the descriptive grasping and disclosing of the a priori of scientific knowledge. What is called the a priori of scientific knowledge consists of the so-called 'guidelines' legitimately used in scientifc research in the disclosure of the various domains of things. Most phenomenologists claim that only "the truly original structures of the objects"4 can legitimately be used as guidelines, the structures of the things themselves as they are "immediately given in primordial experience,"5 in an experience "prior to any contribution of thought."6 They call the things themselves as given in immediate experience (intuition) phenomena and the description of the phenomena in this sense phenomenology. The task of phenomenology is, thus, the description of the structures of the things themselves as they are immediately given in primordial experience, prior to any contribution of thought, i.e., the description of the things as they are given in 'lived' experience or, as they say, of the things of the life-world.7 Phenomenology, consequently, "describes its objects instead of constructing explanations"8 as in fact the sciences do with the help of dogmatically accepted concepts and inherited "prejudices"' which they use to frame the objects of their investigations, thus creating a split between the world scientifically explained and technologically managed and the natural world we live in. In this way the sciences squander their value for life (Lebens- bedeutung),10 resulting in an ever increasing estrangement from life (Lebensentfremdung),"1 which can only be overcome by the reduction 3 Husserl's development of the idea of phenomenology is, of course, better known than any other, although it is only one development of that idea among many (e.g., Heidegger's, Sartre's, Merleau-Ponty's, et al.). However, phenomenology, as developed by Husserl students, has recently led to assessments of science and technology which I take to be highly questionable. The purpose of this paper is to show that the idea of phenomenology can and was, in fact, developed differently from the way it was developed by Husserl himself and by his students. It seems to me that phenomenology as developed and practiced by Heidegger is philosophically more promising with regard to the assessment of science and technology. 4 J. J. Kockelmans, "What Is Phenomenology," in Phenomenology. The Philosophy of Edmund Husseri and Its Interpretation, ed. by J. J. Kockelmans (Garden City: Doubleday & Co., 1967), p. 33 t. 5 Ibid., p. 34. 6 J. M. Edie, "Transcendental Phenomenology and Existentialism," in J. J. Kockel- mans, op. cit., p. 244. 7Cf. J. J. Kockelmans, ibid., p. 34, and J. M. Edie, ibid., p. 248 f. 8 R. Schmitt, "Husserl's Transcendental-Phenomenological Reduction," in J. Kockelmans, op. cit., p. 58. 9 J. J. Kockelmans, ibid., p. 34. 10 G. Brand, Die Lebenswelt. Eine Philosophie des konkreten Apriori (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1971), p. 7. 11 G. Brand, ibid., p. 15. This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 251 of the scientific explanations to or their derivation from the life- world.12 And since it is presupposed that the life-world is always already clearly and 'naturally' understood and accepted with 'lived' and unshakable certainty,13 it is claimed, naturally, that the reduction of scientific explanations to the world we live in promises finally to draw the limits and to provide that long searched for fundamentum certum et inconcussum for the abstract, artificial, and constructivistic explanations of the sciences. Well, the outline of the nature and task of phenomenology in Heidegger's Being and Time seems to be slightly but decisively different, mainly because Heidegger 'deformalizes' the ordinary concept of phenomenon and defines the phenomenological concept of phenomenon more precisely and in a way which is philosophically more promising (BT, 59). Heidegger does not question the contention that the task of phenomenology is the genuine disclosure of the a priori, i.e., of the ontological foundations of positive research (BT, 490nx) through a "grasping and explicating of the phenomena in a way which is 'original' and 'intuitive,'" but he insists that this 'original' and 'intuitive' grasping and disclosing is "directly opposed to the naivete of a haphazard, 'immediate,' and thoughtless 'beholding'" (BT, 61). Phenomenology is the 'science of phenomena,' and it is a descriptive science, so much so that 'descriptive phenomenology' becomes a tautological expression for Heidegger (BT, 59). However, what phenomenology 'describes' are not simply the phenomena in the ordinary sense, namely 'that which shows itself in itself,' the things which are accessible through 'original' and 'immediate' intuition, but what phenomenology thematically 'describes' are the phenomena in the phenomenological sense only: that which shows itself necessarily but 'unthematically' in the ordinary phenomena (BT, 4f). Heidegger illustrates this thesis in reference to Kant's philosophy by pointing out that what phenomenology 'describes' are not the things which are accessible through empirical intuition but rather what Kant calls the 'forms of intuition' (BT, 55). It is impossible to see the need for a special and distinctive 'science of phenomena' unless one 'deformalizes' the formal and ordinary concept of phenomenon. For if the concept of phenomenon is taken formally and in the ordinary sense, then "any exhibiting of an entity as it shows itself in itself, may be called 'phenomenology' with formal justification" (BT, 59) as, for example, the descriptive 12.. Janssen, Geschichte und Lebenswelt. Ein Beitrag zur Diskussion von Husserts Spitwerk (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1970), p. 150. 13G. Brand, ibid., p 16 f. This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 252 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH part of any science may be called 'phenomenology.' Thus, if the task of phenomenology would be to simply describe whatever shows itself in itself, it could never have become a special and distinctive 'science' alongside, above, or below the positive sciences, as many phenomenologists claim it to be. However, if there is something else besides what shows itself in itself which does not show itself, but which necessarily has to be 'described' thematically whenever we explicitly exhibit something which shows itself in itself, i.e., whenever we try to elaborate an understanding of what shows itself in itself which is critical and transparent to itself and which is not merely a naive, 'immediate,' and thoughtless 'beholding,' then there would be a need for a special and distinctive 'science of phenomena' (BT, 60). This would be in addition to the ordinary 'phenomenologies,' i.e., in addition to the positive sciences or, more accurately, to the phenomenological parts in the positive sciences which have already taken it up as their task to exactly describe whatever shows itself in itself, the things themselves. This presupposes, of course, not only (1) that there is a need for such transparency but also (2) that even what shows itself in itself cannot be grasped without some-'unthematic'-familiarity with that 'something else.' The description of what shows itself in itself, thus, remains provisional, naive, and dogmatic without the explicit and thematic exhibition of that 'something else.' "Thus, that which demands that it become a phenomenon, and which demands this in a distinctive sense and in terms of its ownmost content as a thing, is what phenomenology has taken into its grasp thematically as its object" (BT, 59). And since the thematic 'description' of that 'something else' could obviously not be the task of the ordinary 'phenomenologies,' it would have to become the task of a special and distinctive 'science of phenomena.' What the special and distinctive 'science of phenomena' thematically 'describes' is manifestly "something that proximally and for the most part does not show itself: it is something that lies hidden, in contrast to that which proximally and for the most part does show itself; but at the same time it is something that belongs to what thus shows itself, and it belongs to it so essentially as to constitute its meaning and its ground" (BT, 59). In short, what the special and distinctive 'science of phenomena,' phenomenology in the narrow sense of the term, thematically exhibits and 'describes' is not what proximally and for the most part shows itself but the hidden 'meaning' and 'ground' of it. Of course, the point of departure of phenomenology in this sense This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 253 must be, like that of any science whatsoever, that which shows itself in itself, the things themselves, the phenomena in the formal and ordinary sense. To secure such a point of departure phenomenology has to grasp them "in such a way that everything about them which is up for discussion must be treated by exhibiting it directly and demonstrating it directly" (BT, 59). In other words, it has to start out as 'descriptive phenomenology,' with a concise description of what shows itself in itself, whereby the term 'description' simply has the sense of a prohibition-the avoidance of characterizing anything without direct demonstration (BT, 59, 50). But how does phenomenology gain and secure access from what shows itself in itself to that which proximally and for the most part does not show itself but which necessarily belongs to what thus shows itself as its 'meaning' and its 'ground,' i.e., how does phenomenology gain and secure access to the phenomena in the phenomenological sense, exhibit them and make them show themselves? It is the declared business of phenomenology to describe these phenomena. But in what sense can that which does not show itself be described? Certainly not in the ordinary sense of the term. But if 'pheno menological description' "does not signify such a procedure as we find, let us say, in botanical morphology" (BT, 59), then what kind of procedure does it signify, then what is, positively, the meaning of 'phenomeneological description'? Heidegger claims that Being and Time, the investigation itself, shows "that the meaning of phenomenological description lies in interpretation" (BT, 61), i.e., that the business of phenomenology is the business of interpreting. And he calls phenomenology, for this reason, "a hermeneutic in the primordial signification of this word" (BT, 62). But Heidegger's investigation shows as perspicuously that, for this very reason, 'phenomenological description' is by its very nature dependent upon (mediated by) 'prejudices' because "whenever something is interpreted as something, the interpretation will be founded essentially upon fore-having, fore-sight, and fore-conception. An interpretation is never a presuppositionless apprehending of something presented to us" (BT, 191f). Consequently, phenomenology does not and cannot give an un-'prejudiced' description of objects of 'immediate' experience, as many phenomenologists emphatically claim,14 simply because there is no such experience, as Being and Time demonstrates. 14 See note 7, above. This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 254 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH The problem which has to be taken up in conjunction with this result of the Heideggerian investigation (which, in persuance of the main objective of this paper, I merely present here without extensive argumentation) and which Heidegger has taken up thematically in Being and Time and in part, in Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics is how to conceive the character of this 'fore' of experience and description. Obviously, it is not enough to say simply that it is something a priori which, in fact, prestructures experience and description in such and such a way. The problem is much more to explain why experience and description have this character and how access can be gained and secured to the phenomena in view of it. Heidegger claims that there has been no attempt so far to pose explicitly and thematically the problem of why understanding not only has in fact but why it must have these forestructures. Being and Time claims to be the first attempt at an explicit elaboration of this problem. The analysis starts out with a descriptive account of the phenomenal findings about questioning and understanding, research and explanation, then 'points out' the constitutional structures. found, and finally 'supplies,' i.e., constructs, the 'ground' for the structures found, the 'ground' being temporality (BT, 486). This thesis is not regarded as an unchallengeable dogma, still less as a final solution of the problem, but rather as a first and elaborate formulation of the problem which, even at this point, still remains obscure enough. Thus, Being and Time is understood as a laborious attempt to secure a horizon for the problem itself and for possible solutions to it. The question is: how is the understanding of being and entities at all possible? Being and Time suggests that this question can be answered by 'going back' to the primordial constitutionof-being of man who understands being and entities, and it argues extensively and in much detail that the existential-ontological constitution of the totality of man's being is 'grounded' in temporarily. Consequently, the elaborate state of the problem at the end of Being and Time is how to interpret temporarily, i.e., how to construct temporalily in such a way that the possibility and necessity of all modes of understanding, non-conceptual as well as conceptual, become intrinsically comprehensible. Being and Time argues that the elaboration of the problem must and can avoid free-floating speculations by critically securing the point of departure of the whole phenomenological and hermeneutical analysis and by insisting on direct demonstration of the necessity of This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 255 the various steps taken in the construction of the 'ground' upon which all forms of understanding become intrinsically comprehensible and transparent. The arguments which are supposed to critically secure the point of departure are designed to show that it is particularly important to realize that it is a mistake in principle to start out with the account of some specific and definite way of understanding, with the way of understanding as we find it, e.g., in today's astronomy-or, more properly, astrophysics. For what we are left with in all such cases is the familiar persausive assurance that the chosen form of understanding is the 'original' one, the 'all-decisive' one, etc., against which we are urged to measure all other forms of understanding. Ordinarily, a closer look easily discovers that the alleged 'original' form is in many ways 'derivative from' or 'based on' more 'primitive' and more 'simple' forms of understanding. Instead, the analysis starts out with a descriptive account of the phenomenal findings about the undifferentiated character of understanding which it has 'proximally and for the most part,' i.e., of the 'average everyday' kind of understanding. The reasons given to justify this starting point are twofold. It is claimed (1) that as a matter of principle the start should be made with what is 'ontically closest to us and well known,' in other words, with the most familiar 'average everyday' kind of understanding, and (2) that all other forms of understanding originate in and lead back again to the average everyday kind of understanding. This latter claim remains empty at first, but the progressing analysis itself can and in fact does substantiate it by demonstrating that in fact and how precisely all other kinds of understanding emerge from and lead back again to the average everyday kind of understanding (BT, 69). Of course, the phenomenal findings about the average everyday kind of understanding have to be clearly and laboriously circumscribed and the adequacy of the description directly demonstrated. But it would be a fatal mistake to think that this kind of description, the descriptive account of the phenomenal findings about the average everyday kind of understanding, is what phenomenological description intends to give in the end; it merely provides the point of departure for the phenomenological description, and not its point of destination. The phenomenological description of 'x' is certainly not the same as the descriptive account of the phenomenal findings about x'; the latter is a description of 'x' in the ordinary sense of the term, the former is the construction of the necessary a priori of 'x' as circumscribed in and only in the given descriptive account of the phenomenal findings about 'x.' To put it in reference to the task of Being This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 256 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH and Time: The phenomenological description, e.g., of Dasein's 'average everydayness,' does not describe how we manage a knife and fork, but it constructs its necessary a priori by showing how all handling of a knife and fork 'presupposes' the transcendence of Dasein, its being-in-the-world (K, 243). To ignore this difference and to confuse phenomenological de- scription with the descriptive account of the phenomenal findings is to confuse the 'apriorism,' i.e., the a priori research (the disclosure and construction of the a priori) of phenomenology with the mere preparation of its phenomenal basis (BT, 490nx). We find this preparation not only at the beginning of phenomenology but at the beginning of many sciences, e.g., zoology, though not at the beginning of all sciences, e.g., Newtonian physics (the Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematics start out, as is well known, with definitiones, axiomata, etc., instead). Such misunderstanding and misrepresentation of the program of phenomenology has too often turned phenomenology, the a priori research, into a 'knite-and-tork-phenomenology,' whose relevance and importance for scientific research, as claimed by phenomenologists, must be considered terribly overstated. The point of departure, consequently, does not necessarily distinguish phenomenological from scientific research, although in some cases it obviously does-to a degree. However, the critical securing of the point of departure by the method of accurate description of the phenomenal findings alone cannot avoid free-floating speculations and guarantee the access to the phenomena of phenomenology, i.e., to the 'ground' and necessary a priori of what is given in the descriptive account of the phenomenal findings. Because the 'meaning,' 'ground,' and necessary a priori or whatever one prefers to call that which allows us to understand and comprehend and without which we simply cannot understand the given-is not 'accessible,' does not 'show itself,' and cannot be 'found' in what is given in the descriptive account of the phenomenal findings; it has to be 'provided,' 'added,' and 'supplied.' And phenomenology claims to 'supply' it in a way which methodically avoids mistaking free-floating speculations for the necessary a priori by insisting on direct demonstration of the necessity of the provided construction for the understanding and for the transparency of what is given in the critically secured descriptive account of the phenomenal findings. The conceptual construction has to be provided directly and exclusively for the understanding of the phenomenal findings. Unfortunately, many phenomenologists give the impression that the demand for direct demonstration is satisfied This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 257 by the sheer claim that something is 'essential' to something. The construction cannot be freely and arbitrarily invented-as the working hypotheses of scientists often incorrectly appear to be to many phenomenologists. It has to be demonstrated in each case that it is necessarily linked up with the phenomenal findings in such a way that without it we could not understand the phenomenal findings as we in fact do and that theses-findings could not appear to be transparent otherwise. Its sole purpose is, to use an old phrase, the saving of the phenomena; however, phenomena taken not in the deformalized sense of phenomenology but simply in the sense of the phenomenal findings. The only possible verification and justification of such construction is, of course, the understanding which it 'provides'-an understanding which is clear and transparent to itself (K, 241). From what has been said it follows, of course, that neither the point of departure nor the point of destination nor the procedure from the one to the other distinguishes phenomenological from scientific research. The title 'phenomenology' is simply the name for any genuine scientific and philosophical empiricism, i.e., for the method of every science and of every scientific, i.e., respectable philosophy (BT, 490nx). To claim a radical difference between phenomenological and scientific research, as many phenomenologists emphatically do, is to mistake the task and the procedure of phenomenology and of science as well. For from what has been said it follows that the term 'phenomenology' does not and cannot characterize any discipline or form of research with regard to its object or subject matter. It characterizes, instead, all responsible research, philosophical as well as scientific, solely with regard to its procedure or method (Behandlungsart, BT, 62), i.e., the title 'phenomenology' merely and solely "informs us of the 'how' with which what is to be treated . . . gets exhibited and handled" (BT, 59); in short, it signifies a "methodological conception" (BT, 50). In other words, the phenomenological procedure, as outlined, truly and radically distinguishes all philosophical and scientific research; however, not from each other, but it distinguishes and separates toto caelo both together from all free-floating speculations, arbitrary constructions, accidental findings, and all "those pseudoquestions which parade themselves as 'problems,' often for generations at a time" (BT, 50). The maxim of phenomenology, 'To the things themselves!,' is, as Heidegger not only admits but emphasizes, "abundantly self-evident, and it expresses . . . the underlying principle of any scientific knowledge whatsoever" -(BT, 50). It is the expression of a prohibition-in philosophy as well as in science: 'Avoid This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 258 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH characterizing anything without demonstration!' (BT, 59). Ignoring this principle and prohibition leads necessarily to arbitrary speculations, stupefying dogmatism, and blundering obscurity-in science as well as in philosophy. However, Heidegger's exposition of the idea of phenomenology, of something "'so self-evident" (BT, 50), in the course of the clarifi- fication of the only possible and justifiable method of his fundamental-ontological research, and this research itself, frequently misled many to confuse phenomenology with philosophy, with fundamental ontology, and with the analysis of the average everydayness in particular, especially in view of the still ongoing analysis and discussion of the life-world and its relationship to science and technology, a discussion and analysis to which so many phenomenologists have committed themselves exclusively. The high-flown and often infamous attacks, indicated at the beginning of this paper, of so many lifeworld phenomenologists against scientific research and technology, and the overselling of the phenomenology of the life-world as a panacea for their shortcomings, are merely consequences of such a confusion. But only a hazy understanding of the idea of phenomenology and a hasty reading of Being and Time in particular can lead to such consequences. For phenomenology itself can never be legitimately contrasted with science, nor can it be identified with a particular, 'special' kind of science, or for that matter with philosophy, and even less with any of its many identified 'disciplines,' such as ontology, fundamental ontology, or the philosophical analysis of the life-world. None of the many kinds of philosophical research can be distinguished from scientific research merely on the ground that it is phenomenological. For all kinds of philosophical and scientific research are and have to be phenomenological, if they are not to degenerate into freefloating speculation and arbitrary constructivism. What distinguishes philosophical research from scientific research is, consequently, not the alleged fact that the one is phenomenological and the other one not, nor for that matter that the one is descriptive and the other one constructive. However, there are decisive differences between philosophical and scientific research, and I would like to point out only one-one which helps to further clarify the idea of phenomenology. Heidegger argues in Being and Time that what distinguishes philosophical research from scientific research is the fact that the one is ontological, or even fundamentalontological, whereas the other one is purely ontical. Ontological research tries (1) to 'disclose' the a priori 'presupposed' and already This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 259 operative in a particular area of scientific research, or even in average everyday life, in other words, it tries to 'supply' the a priori necessary to understand and to make fully transparent the de facto understanding of the things in a particular area of scientific research or in ordinary life, and most importantly, in carrying out its critical and philosophical task, it tries (2) to establish the limitations of that a priori and to justify it within the established limitations. Ontical research, on the other hand, describes and explains the things observable in a particular area of research, always 'presupposing' and 'taking for granted' (1) some particular (regional) a priori together with (2) some fundamental (universal) a priori. In other words, it always works within some rich and firmly compacted particular system of categories and principles and it is always 'guided' by some 'basic' and 'common' concepts in its study of the things observable in a particular area of scientific research, whose critical analysis and justification it leaves to other 'disciplines'-to the various regional ontologies and to fundamental ontology. In short, ontological research, since Plato and Aristotle, is thematically concerned with the explanation and understanding of the understanding of things, whereas ontical research is merely concerned with the explanation and understanding of things. Being and Time, a treatise in fundamental ontology, is understood as an attempt to 'disclose' the a priori which is still hidden but nevertheless already operative in our average everyday understanding of things and which remotely 'guides' all scientific research; in other words, it tries to 'supply' the a priori which is necessary to make the average everyday understanding of things transparent to itself-and, more importantly, it tries to point out its limitations and to establish its legitimacy. At the beginning of such an enterprise the problem of the proper procedure has to be discussed because it is still, despite Kant's 'Copernician Revolution,' the main obstacle to lasting success in philosophical and ontological research. The analogous problem in scientific research was solved long ago, and this explains, in Kant's words, why "the study of nature has entered on the secure path of a science, after having for so many centuries been nothing but a process of merely random groping.""5 However, although it was understood since Kant that only a "method modelled on that of the student of nature"1 can promise real success in philosophical research, it was Husserl, according to Heidegger, who made philosophical progress Is I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by N. K. Smith (Toronto: Macmillan 1965), p. 20 f. 16 Ibid., p. 23, note a. This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 260 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH really possible again. For "Edmund Husserl has not only enabled us to understand once more the meaning of any genuine philosophical empiricism; he has also given us the necessary tools" (BT, 490nx), i.e., the elaborate "method modelled on that of the student of nature": phenomenology. Husserl showed (1) how the method used in the empirical sciences can be modified for its special purposes and used successfully in philosophical and ontological research as well, and, by doing so, he showed (2) how philosophy can become a 'strict science' after centuries of free-floating speculation and construct- ivism. The purpose of the presentation and discussion of the idea of phenomenology in the introduction to Heidegger's treatise in fundamental ontology is, consequently, to show first, that research in fun- damental ontology in order to succeed has to proceed in exactly the same way the sciences do: it has to be demonstrative, i.e., phenomenological (BT, 60, 62), in its construction of the necessary a priori, and not speculative or, to use Heidegger's term, constructivistic (BT, 490nx). Secondly, the difference between scientific research and philosophic research is not a difference in the method (constructivism-descriptivism) but rather a difference in the understanding and explaining of things in terms of an accepted a priori, on the one side, and an explicit grasping of the 'presuppositions' of such understanding and explaining, on the other side. And, thirdly, philosopical research does not halt at such explicit grasping but it aims ultimately at a insight into the legitimacy and scope (Recht und Grenzen, K, 251) of such 'presuppositions,' i.e., it does not rest with an answer to the quaestio facti, it seeks, beyond that, an answer to the quaestio iuris. Consequently, to halt at the mere construction of a necessary a priori, of scientific research in a particular area as well as of average everyday life, would vitiate the decisive difference indicated between philosophical and scientific research. For the mere construction of any a priori whatsoever, even of the lifeworld a priori, answers only the quaestio facti and leaves the quaestio iuris untouched. Merely to construct the a priori of average everyday life and to interpret things in terms of that a priori is no less dogmatic and no less in need of justification-even if accepted and presupposed with 'lived' and unshakable certainty-than is scientific understanding which interprets things in terms of a less 'original' and less 'common' a priori. To demonstrate, therefore, the 'abstractness' of scientific knowledge and of its a priori, and to 'reduce' it to-or, for that matter to 'deduce' it from-the 'original' and 'supportive' a priori of This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms DESCRIPTIVE PHENOMENOLOGY AND CONSTRUCTIVISM 261 the life-world, does not prove anything whatsoever about the legitimacy of either one. Such 'reduction' by itself cannot overcome the 'prejudice'-free region of experience which can then become subject to phenomenological description and which can be claimed to be the only solid fundament of scientific knowledge. It merely exchanges the 'prejudices' of the positive sciences for the 'prejudices' and the 'given' of ordinary, unexamined life; for if one appeals to what is 'given,' in any form whatever, then one will always find that what is 'given' "is nothing other than the obvious undiscussed assumption (Vormeinung) of the person who does the interpreting" and describing (BT, 192). Thus, if phenomenologists want to attain absolutely valid knowledge of things, as they claim, through a phenomenological foundation of the 'abstract,' 'artificial,' and 'estranged' scientific knowledge, then they have to raise and answer-with the-rigor and exactness of the sciences ("nach den strengsten Regein einer schulgerechten Piinktlichkeit")"7-the quaestio iuris. To appeal, in response to such a demand for critical justification, to the forestructure, prejudgmental structure, or circularity of all understanding, interpretation, and de- scription, and to claim that the life-world a priori into ing appear meaningless, not of a 'given' and unshakably this structure not only forbids putting question, but indeed makes such questiononly does not guarantee the identification accepted a priori with a legitimate one, as Habermas pointed out against Gadamer,18 but it turns phenome- nology, the radical movement against free-floating speculation and arbitrary constructivism in matters philosophical, into a reactionary movement against philosophy and science through the construction of an a priori and through the dogmatic claim that it is unchallengeable in principle and beyond improvement. HANS SEIGERIED. LOYOLA UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO. 171. Kant, Prolegomena, in Werke, Bd. 4 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., p. 261. 18 J. Habermas, "Summation and Response," in Continuum 8 (1970), pp. 123ff. This content downloaded from 35.176.47.6 on Sat, 18 Apr 2020 00:28:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms