Uploaded by Laura Downham

3.0) States are the only actors that can commit acts of violence legitimately.

advertisement
Laura Downham
Thursday, 24 October 2019
States are the only actors that can
commit acts of violence
legitimately.
It is crucial to address before the subsequent essay that this author has a bias against
legitimising states. Foundational to the formation of states is violently enforced lateral
hierarchies of top-down power (Parise, 2013). These hierarchies form self-enforcing methods
of oppression, directly (e.g. the threat of police violence upon failure to follow the law
(Jacobs and O’Brien (1998)) or indirectly (e.g. alienation of workers through capitalistic
wage-theft (Marx, 1844). Due to this assumption, this essay will lean heavily in favour of the
populist exercise of legitimacy over the more liberal notion of the self-enforcing social
contract(Hobbes (1651), Locke (1764). The author holds that states actors have at their
discretion near-unlimited economic resources due to their ability to aggregate debt
(Rotherham, 2013; Smith, 1775, book II) and the faculty to exercise violence with impunity
as a result of these economic resources (Green and Ward, 2004 and Weber 1921/74: 54 in
Hay, Lister and Marsh 2014)). Contrastingly, the lack of these resources gives moral
dispensation to “the people” to act in the determination of their interests (Parise, 2013).
Only mass movements of collective resistance may legitimately commit acts of violence to
state action. The defence/pursuit of a group’s social interest upon the perception of injustice/
oppression against that group is collective resistance(). As, in liberal democracies, the
majority has the voice of most electoral weight (Berlin, 1969 in Held, 1992), mass
movements are the most effective means of making discontentment felt by political elites.
Also known as direct democracy, as the groups which feel disenfranchised by institutional
representation bypass this official position to make their interest more directly heard, if
through symbolic means (Shirky 2011, Pg. 28-32 ). These actions are given legitimacy
through sheer numbers and weight of presence made by the mass of resisters, for example,
the (time of writing) ongoing Chilean protests against growing national inequality (Barlette,
2019 and Kaltwasser, 2019). If a movement appears to have the majority support of the
population of a state, its grievances can be taken more seriously and thus have greater
legitimacy, than otherwise. However, as movements move digital, the physical presence of
activists can be less accurate to the actual support a movement has (e.g. Arab spring
movement(Carvin, 2013)). Either way, as a physical threat to the ruling body of the state or as
a momentous movement whose continued grievance and mobilisation is going to be
inconvenient for the stabilisation of society (Locke, 1764, pg. 302). This assumption applies
best to a democratic model of legitimacy by Haywood (“transformation of power into
authority” through the aggregation of consent hence the “moral criteria” of legitimacy).
Additionally, Weber’s rational authority theory (Weber, 1919) maps onto this assumption, as
the consent of the governed within these models is critical to a state maintaining legitimacy:
POLI109 2019/2020
!1
“the power of a president, prime minister or government official is determined …by formal,
constitutional rules which constrain or limit what the officeholder can”. In the case of
Weber’s demand for a constitution, to guarantee restrictions on governmental power, such
documents often assure the freedoms of people to “peaceful assembly and association”; as
well as “freedom of opinion and expression,” both stated in 18th and 19th articles of the UN
Declaration on Human Rights (Roosevelt, 1948). Collective resistance in the 20th century has
come in two varieties: violent and non-violent. Generally, (for the sake of maintaining the
impression of moral purity by the resistors and the optics of injustice of the persecutors’
actions) non-violent resistance is preferred and more effective in garnering institutional
support (Flintoff, 2013). However, violent resistance is often more effective in terms of
sending a political message, illuminating injustice and receiving attention from the political
establishment (The Red Pheonix, 2009).
For example, the Soweto Uprising, organised by the Action Committee of the Soweto
Students Representative Council (SSRC), the planned march on the Orland stadium met with
tear-gas and live-ammunition shot into the crowd of unarmed students by the white
police( Christie, 1991 and Cross, 1992). Clearly shown as unjust state violence against
children and teenagers, leaving nearly 200 dead, the black community reciprocated.
Solidarity marches, arson and the destruction of government property filled the subsequent
days, as the movement spread to Thembisa and Kagiso (The Soweto Uprising, no date).
Recruitment spurred forward by the African National Congress (ANC) and the Pan Africanist
Congress (PAC) by the violence(Christie 1991). By the involvement of state enforcers, the
protest became legitimate, in terms of its ability to animate support, as the meeting of
violence to initial non-violence demonstrated the gratuitous subduing of black voices and the
need for black solidarity and uprising (Saunders and Southey 1998). Due to the
transcendence of hostility and aggression toward their oppressors, it was able to sustain
public imagination and command support even from white South Africans. Therefore mass
movements, such as the example given above, are the only actors who may legitimately use
violence in an assertion of their interest within society(Noam Chomsky debates with Hannah
Arendt, Susan Sontag, et al, 1967), as by definition, these violent acts are in the assertion of
the interests of a significant amount; if not the majority of those under state jurisdiction.
Some may argue, however, that a state’s use of violence as an assertion of the consent of the
governed is a legitimate use of violence( Nagel, 1987 Pg. 215-50 and Noam Chomsky
debates with Hannah Arendt, Susan Sontag, et al., 1967), along the same liberal paradigm.
The assertion comes through expressing ideals of state and people. For example, this was the
case of the removal of First Nation people from their land, promoting the enterprise and selfdetermination of the white settlers in North America as described by Dunbar-Ortriz (2014).
“Manifest destiny” rhetoric garnered near unilateral support by white American settlers. Here,
the genocidal violence was an expression by the United States government, of its
commitment to (white) American values: exceptionalism and expansionist policy.
Explemplared is the use of state militarism to defer to the representation of those whom
politicians most identify with, regardless of others. Admittedly, the colonial state has some
legitimacy issues exempt from its use of violence alone(Dewulf, 2011 and Gathii, 2000).
However, it offers a useful point of analysis for where we cannot necessarily purely derive
the passive consent of the majority to justify state violence against a marginalised indigenous
group. As G. Rockhill commented “there is no contradiction or supposed loss of democracy
because the United States simply never was one,” eluding the lack of legal voting equality in
the nation until the introduction of 19th amendment and 1964 Voting Rights Act-although the
democratic participation disparity arguably continues, with the implementation of the
electoral college and gerrymandering practice (Johnson,2018). For the majority of its history,
POLI109 2019/2020
!2
Alexis de Tocqueville’s “tyranny of the majority” was inapplicable to the US, as the majority
of its citizens could not vote and provide their consent to a discriminatory policy. Therefore,
these colonial states have insufficient consent, inferred by a mandate, to use violence as an
assertion of said imaginary consent.
On the other hand, insurgencies may garner legitimacy, using violence as a body in its
arsenal to refute consent to be ruled by a government that it observes as illegitimate (Locke,
1764 Pg. 228-231, Green and ward, 2004 Pg. 46, Cockroft 1998)— for example, the black
panthers of Oakland, California. The use of community patrols, as well as open endorsement
and utilisation of their 2nd amendment rights, showed an unabashed confrontation of
racialised hypocrisy in American society-then and now (The Black Panthers: Vanguard of the
Revolution, 2015). The threat of violence and confrontations with the police (symbols of the
“tough on crime” era’s “law and order”(13th, 2018)) were a convincing refutation of the
“submissive negro [sic]” stereotype from civil-war propaganda (Sociology Group, 2018).
They were vital in encapsulating the anger of the era in a way that Dr King’s passivism may
not have. As said by Malcom X (1964), “You will get your freedom by letting our enemy
know you will do anything to get your freedom” (Zinn, 1980, Pg. 831-859). This zeitgeist
representation held greater legitimacy and relevance to the transition of the civil rights
movement from overturning Jim Crow to Black Power. The objective of the Black Panthers
was to refute the legitimacy of the white supremacist US government by constructing a dual
power structure and legitimised their use of and threats of violence through the preservation
and defence of their communities.
Political violence is a neutral tool like any other; the content of this essay demonstrates that
state actors too frequently use violence to sustain power at the expense of the welfare of their
own historically colonised, brutalised peoples. This essay maintains the following as
legitimate uses of violence, knowing that intention and outcome are not synonymous:
1) Actors with the intent to sustain or achieve their self-determination (i.e. first nation
Americans)
2) Actors with the intent of expanding declared universal human rights to themselves and
others (i.e. both this and the prior point is evident in the efforts of native Africans during the
Apartheid period)
3) Actors with the intent to make evident their displeasure with their current governance and
the removal of their consent to be governed (i.e. the black panthers)
This essay concluded that the only legitimate forms of violence are those which expand the
participation of individuals and groups in society and often the violence enacted by states
have been counterintuitive to this goal or downright exclusionary to the very people most in
need of the protection of so-called “law and order.”
Bibliography:
• Publisher:A&E Television Networks; Last Updated:June 7, 2019; Original Published Date:November 9, 2009 ;https://
www.history.com/topics/france/alexis-de-tocqueville(Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• Christiano T; 2006; https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/democracy/#LimAutDem (Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• Laurence M; LAST REVIEWED: 19 MAY 2017 https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/
obo-9780199756223/obo-9780199756223-0162.xml#obo-9780199756223-0162-bibItem-0009 (Sunday, 20 October
2019)
• Rockhill G; DECEMBER 13, 2017; https://www.counterpunch.org/2017/12/13/the-u-s-is-not-a-democracy-it-neverwas/; (Sunday, 20 October 2019)
POLI109 2019/2020
!3
• TITLE:Politics;EDITION:4;AUTHOR:Andrew Heywood; PUBLISHER: Palgrave Macmillan;PRINT PUB DATE:
2013-03-22 (Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• https://www.sahistory.org.za/article/june-16-soweto-youth-uprising:
A. Brits, J. P. (1995). The Concise Dictionary of Historical and Political Terms, London: Penguin.
B. Christie, P. (1991). The Right to Learn: The Struggle for Education in South Africa, Johannesburg: Sached Trust/Ravan
Press.
C. Cross, M. (1992). Resistance and Transformation: Education Culture and Reconstruction in South Africa, Johannesburg:
Skotaville.
D. Howcroft, P. unpublished South African Encyclopaedia papers.
E. Kallaway, P. (ed) (1984). Apartheid and Education: The Education of Black South Africans, Johannesburg: Ravan
Press.
F. Saunders, C. & Southey, N. (1998). A Dictionary of South African History, Cape Town: David Philip.
• South African History; Produced 21 March 2011Last Updated 27 August 2019; https://www.sahistory.org.za/
article/defiance-campaign-1952; (Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• O’Malley P; no publication date; https://omalley.nelsonmandela.org/omalley/index.php/site/q/
03lv01538/04lv01539/05lv01540/06lv01543.htm(Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• no author; no publication date; https://www.apartheidmuseum.org/resources(Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• United Nations; no publication date for website; https://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human-rights/ ; (Sunday, 20
October 2019)
• No author given, What Uncle Sam Really Wants (The Real Story Series) 1st edition ISBN-13: 978-1878825018 Odonian
Press; (July 1st, 2002) (Monday, 21 October 2019)
• Barbara F. Walter, Civil War: Why Bad Governance Leads to Repeat
DOI: 10.1177/0022002714528006 ; Journal of Conflict Resolution 2015, Vol. 59(7) 1242-1272 (Monday, 21 October
2019)
• Citation: C N Trueman; The Black Panthers; The History Learning Site, 27 Mar 2015. 15 Oct 2019"The Black Panthers”;
historylearningsite.co.uk.(Tuesday, 22 October 2019)
• https://www.sociologygroup.com/black-panther-party-history/History of the Black Panther PartyOCTOBER 11,
2018 BY SOCIOLOGY GROUP (Tuesday, 22 October 2019)
• Citation Information: Baggins, Brian. History of the Black Panther Party. Marxists Internet Archive (marx.org), copyleft 2002.
Retrieved on (Tuesday, 22 October 2019). URL: http://www.marxists.org/history/usa/workers/black-panthers/
• https://schoolshistory.org.uk/topics/world-history/america-c1945-1971/black-panthers/; no publication date, (Tuesday, 22
October 2019)
• Balis J, Smith S, Owens P; 2017; The globalisation of world politics; seventh edition (2017) ; Oxford University Press; ISBN
978-0-19-873985-2; Pages: 223-378 and 385-527; (Monday, 30 September 2019)
• State: theories and policies; APR 14th, 2014; London: Palgrave-Macmillan; EBOOK ISBN: 9780230802278; (Monday, 30
September 2019)
• Naím M; 2013; The end of power; Basic Books; Perseus Books Group; ISBN 978-0-465-03156-6; (Monday, 30 September
2019)
• Green P, Ward T; 2004; State Crime; Pluto press; Chapter 1: Defining the state as criminal, Chapter 2: Corruption as state
crime, Chapter 5: police crime , Chapter 7: state terror and terrorism , Chapter 11: the political economy of state crime;
(Thursday, 10 October 2019)
POLI109 2019/2020
!4
• Herman E S, Chomsky N; 2008; Manufacturing Consent; The Bodley Head Random House; ISBN 9781847920706;,
(Thursday, 10 October 2019)
• Arendt H; 1969, 1970; On violence; Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company; ISBN 978-0-15-669500-8; ISBN
978-0-15-669500-8;(Thursday, 10 October 2019)
• Heazle M, Kane J; 2016; Policy legitimacy, Science and Political Authority: Knowledge and action in liberal
democracies; Rouledge Taylor and Francis group; ISBN 978-1-315-68806-0;Chapter 2: The undead linear
model of expertise
• Otunnu O,2017; Crisis of legitimacy and political violence in Uganda 1979 to 2016;,London: Palgrve Macmillan; e-ISBN
978-3-319-56047-2;; Chapter 2: under the UNFL, Chapter 3: Under Obate II regime, Chapter 4: Under the Tito Okelo
regime, Chapter 5: Under the Museveni regime; (Thursday, 10 October 2019)
• Cris of the republic; 1972 (4th edition) Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company; e-ISBN
978-0-547-623200-6; Arendt H; Chapter 2: Civil disobedience, Chapter 3: On violence, Chapter 4: Thoughts
on politics and revolution; (Thursday, 10 October 2019)
• Isenberg N; 2017; White Trash,New York: Penguin Random House LLC; ISBN: 978-1-78649-298-2; Chapter;2-9;
(Sunday, 20 October 2019)
•
2014;An Indigenous Peoples’ History of the United States;,Boston: Beacon Press Boston; ISBN:
978-0-8070-0041-0; Chapter 2: Culture of conquest, Chapter 3: Cult of the covenant , Chapter 9: Us
triumphalism and peacetime colonialism; (Sunday, 20 October 2019)
• Zinn H; 1980; A peoples’ history of the united states;New York: Harper Colins publishing; ISBN 978-1-4472-7972-3 Pages
831-859; (Friday, 25 October 2019)
• O’Brien R and Jacobs D, 1998, The determinant of deadly force: A structural analysis of police force, American Journal of
Sociology,Volume 103 Number 4, Pg. 837-62, Available at: https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/action/doSearch?
AllField=police+violence(Friday, 1 November 2019)
• Shi F and Cai Y, 2006, Disaggregating the state: networks and collective networks in Shanghai, China Quarterly (no volume
number given), doi: 10.1017/S0305741006000038 (Friday, 1 November 2019)
• The Black Panthers: Vanguard of the Revolution (2015), Netflix, 23 October 2015, Available at: 80049128, Accessed: 22
October 2019
• Chomsky N, Arendt H, Sontag S et al. (1967, December 15) Debates on legitimacy of violence as a political act, Accessed:
chomsky.info/19671215, Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Ghandi was wrong-Non-violence doesn’t work, Red Pheonix, published: 18 October 2009, URL: https://theredphoenixapl.org/
2009/10/18/gandhi-was-wrong-nonviolence-doesnt-work/, Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Mill J, London: Cambridge University Press, The collected works of John Stuart Mills, 1861, Considerations on Representative
Government, Chapter 3, Pg. 3915-3924, Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Vickers T, 2016, Opportunities and limitations for collective resistance arising from volunteering by asylum seekers and refugees in
Northern England, critical sociology, 42(3), Pg. 437-454, URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.117770896920314526623
• Shirky C, 2011, Political power of social media, https://nyuscholars.nyu.edu/en/publications/the-political-power-of-socialmedia-technology-the-public-sphere- 2 October 2019
• Held D, 1992, Democracy: from city-states to a cosmopolitan order? Political studies “special issue” Pg. 10-39, dos: 10.1111/j.
1467.9248.1992.tb0110.x
• Alimohomed-Wilson J and Williams D, 2016, State violence, social control and resistance, Journal of social justice, Vol 6 ISSN:
2164-7100
• Enos R, Kaufman A and Sands A, 2019, Can violent protest change local policy support? American political science review, Vol 4,
Issue 14, Pg. 1012-1028, doi: 10.1017/S0003055419000340
• Brabeck K, 2003, Testimonio: A strategy for collective resistance, cultural survival and building solidarity: feminism and
psychology Vol.13(2), Pg. 252-258, https://doi.org/10.1177/0959353503013002009 Accessed: Monday, 4 November
2019
POLI109 2019/2020
!5
• Flintoff P, 2013, Gene sharp: The Machiavelli of non-violence URL: https://www.newstatesman.com/politics/yourdemocracy/2013/01/gene-sharp-machiavelli-non-violence, Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Renegade cut, 2019, Saturday neoliberalism, 28 September 2019, URL: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=7gQFvf19Jec
Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Cox J, 1998, \introduction to Marx’s theory of alienation, International socialism, Issue 79 URL: http://
pubs.socialistreviewindex.org.uk/isj79/cox.htm, accessed: 28 October 2019
• If Piñera wants to wage war in Chile he should fight the real enemy: inequality, Kaltwasser C, 23 October 2019, URL:
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2019/oct/23/chile-protest-war-pinera-inequality accessed: 2 November 2019
• Roth B, Governmental illegitimacy in International law Review by Gathii J, Neoliberalism, Colonialism and International
governance: decentred the international law of governmental legitimacy, Michigan law review, Vol. 9, No. 6, May 2000, Pg
1996-2055, URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1290272, accessed: 2 November 2019
• Thoreau H, 1849, Resistance to Civil Government, 6th edition, London: Penguin classics, Accessed: 21 October 2019
• Kropotkin P, 1892, The conquest of Bread, New York: Vanguard Press
• Marx K, 1844, Economic and Philosophic manuscripts of 1844, New York: Dover publications
• Smith A, An inquiry into nature and causes of the wealth of nations, 1776, London: create space publications platform
• Hobbes T, 1651, Leviathan, St. Pauls’ Churchyard: Andrew Crooke, Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Locke J, 1764, Second treatise of government, London: Salus Populi Suprema Lex esto, Accessed: 1 November 2019
• Parise T, 2013, Principles of Anarchism, Hawaii: The Maui Company, 1st edition, Accessed: 2 November 2019
• Mudde C and Kaltwasser C, Populism, 2017, New York: Oxford University Press, Accessed: 1 November 2019
• Marx K, 1847, Wage labour and Capital, Germany: Neve Rheinische Zeitung
• Nagel T, 1987, Moral conflict and political legitimacy, Philosophy and public affairs, Vol. 16, No. 3, Pg. 213-240, URL:
https//www.jstor.org/stable/2265265, Accessed: 1 November 2019
• Flinders M and Kelso A, 2011, Mind the gap: political analysis, public expectations and parliamentary decline thesis , Political
studies association, Vol 13, Pg. 249-268, doi: 10.1111/j.1467.856x.2010.00434.x Accessed: Monday, 4 November 2019
POLI109 2019/2020
!6
Download