transaction costs and uncertainty, and the provision of information. In turn, these benefits make it easier for states to strike agreements. On the whole, Keohane stresses that regimes are useful to states, in the sense of being a functional solution to a common problem. One upshot of this argument is that cooperation may be more difficult to establish than to maintain, as existing arrangements reduce uncertainty and have proven utility, whereas untested mechanisms do not. However, this logic also suggests that regimes may persist beyond their founding mandate, as the costs of establishing new regimes mean that states are less willing to do so. Writing soon after 9/11, Keohane was struck by the extent to which the Bush administration had turned to multilateral institutions, especially the UN Security Council, as part of its response. This would “provide a fruitful test for institutionalist theory,” especially in light of the apparent unilateralist proclivities of administration members.27 For Keohane, this move rather underscored the value of liberal approaches, as it provided evidence for a key institutionalist claim, that institutions work by “altering the costs of state strategies.”28 In other words, as states contemplate action on any issue, prevailing multilateral arrangements are likely to figure in their calculations and, subsequently, in their negotiations. Where states anticipate that multilateralism will be mutually beneficial, those negotiations ought to yield cooperation. Keohane’s interpretation of the United States’ engagement of international organizations after 9/11 would be viewed more skeptically by realists. By itself, the starting assumption of realist theory that states face an unrelenting “security dilemma” as a result of the anarchic nature of the international system suggests that cooperation will be the exception rather than the rule. It is unsurprising, then, that realists discuss multilateralism less than liberals and constructivists. Still, two realist arguments can be discerned.29 The first of these, generally associated with neo-realism, takes the skeptical claim to the extreme. This approach suggests that instances of cooperation are either imposed by powerful states, or worse, are empirically inconsequential.30 The analytical foundation of the former claim is compelling and addresses a shortcoming in the liberal position. Namely, liberals suggest that states are able to achieve mutual benefits through cooperation, i.e. that the gains from cooperation are “absolute” (all parties gain something). But if we take the security dilemma seriously, surely states would be concerned that their partners would gain more from cooperation relative to themselves. After all, under conditions of anarchy, today’s partner may be tomorrow’s adversary. In negotiating the terms of cooperation, then, states should be concerned about “relative gains” more than “absolute 10 gains” and that, in turn, is a fundamental constraint upon achieving consensus.31 This is especially so if we accept that, in cooperating on any particular issue, there may be multiple different agreements that could be negotiated and achieving consensus on the terms of a deal (that benefits everyone, equally) is more problematic than liberals admit.32 Again, the barriers to multilateralism are likely to be high where cooperation has distributive consequences: that is, where the terms of cooperation benefit some states more than, or relative to, others. Subsequent realists have built on these claims in a more pragmatic way, acknowledging the volume of international cooperation in world politics today. Beyond simply explaining the failure to cooperate, they analyze patterns of international cooperation. Again, their emphasis is on relative power and they see cooperation as a tool or tactic that states can use to advance their interests.33 This approach offers an account of why states seek cooperation (to advance interests), how they do it (by acting through fora amenable to their influence) and how others respond. Regarding the latter, if cooperation has distributive consequences, we should expect less powerful states to resist attempts at cajoling them into joint action. That resistance might itself trigger forms of cooperation and, consequently, “forum shopping,” where states utilize different cooperative mechanisms to preserve their interests or ameliorate the consequences of being bound by others.34 Overall, the dynamics of cooperation tend here to resemble a form of “posi- tional conflict,” as states compete for influence.35 Where cooperation canadvance or defend states’ interests, we ought to observe them pursuing “tactical multilateralism” in this way.36 As this brief overview confirms, scholars disagree about the paths to multilateralism. This difference of opinion extends to explanations of the form that cooperation takes. In this regard, as an empirical matter,several observers have noted a trend towards increasing diversity in the way that states cooperate, beyond formal international organizations alone: “Over the past several decades, a range of innovative modalities has emerged in the form of hybrid institutional arrangements … inter- agency coordinating mechanisms … new inter-governmental coalitions … public-private partnerships … and private sector initiatives.”37 More- over, as Kal Raustiala and David G. Victor point out, multiple coop- erative mechanisms may arise within a single issue domain, giving rise to what they call “regime complexes,” i.e. “an array of partially over- lapping and nonhierarchical institutions governing a particular issue area … [and] marked by the existence of several legal agreements that are created and maintained in distinct fora with participation of dif- ferent sets of actors.”38 Among this diversity, it is useful to note recent