Bekir Konakovic PHI 2630 March 2nd, 2017 Word Count: 1,993 Utilitarianism & Virtue Ethics Utilitarianism as an ethical theory relies solely on a consequentialist outlook, maintaining that the determinate factor of morality lies among the happiness and unhappiness created by the outcome. Virtue ethics encompasses a more holistic and practical approach by looking towards a person’s means and motives regarding an action; therefore, utilitarianism is reduced to a less acceptable ethical theory when paired against virtue ethics because of the higher detriment that arises from its institution and practice. The final constructs of utilitarianism arose from Jeremy Bentham’s views on morality1. He opposed the views of morality during his time by claiming morality is not derived from a deontological faith in divine rules or duty to pleasing God, but rather morality is achieved by attaining the greatest volume of happiness amongst the vast majority of people resulting from an action. Thus, utilitarianism maintains that an action may be deemed morally right if it promotes happiness and is beneficial to the majority of those affected2. A main component of utilitarianism is consequentialism which looks to a person’s actions and the following consequences of those actions to determine their place on the moral spectrum. The action’s reflection on the majority’s happiness and benefit governs its status as moral or immoral. Per Bentham, “there is one ultimate 1 Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 91. 2 Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 91. moral principle, the Principle of Utility”3. This principle stands at the crux of Utilitarianism; it requires that a person faced with a choice amid various options and alternatives choose the one with the superlative overall outcome for those involved. This principle was later solidified by Bentham’s disciple John Stuart Mill as “the Greatest Happiness Principle”; Mill’s principle confirms that an action must seek utility, or happiness, with the exclusion of pain to achieve a moral standing, therefore binding Utilitarianism within these statutes. Utilitarianism focuses solely on the happiness of those in the aftermath of an action, considering each person equal to the other. Virtue Ethics on the other hand looks to a person’s moral character and the virtues by which they act to determine the moral standing of an action or otherwise. A virtue is defined as “a trait of character, manifested in habitual action, that is good for anyone to have”4. The strength or weakness of the virtues respective to a person and their moral situation is considered by weighing them along a metaphorical scale. The scale incorporates the two extremes of a virtue and a person may move along the scale to either extreme dependent on their consistency and exhibition of the virtue throughout time. To exhibit a virtue and fall under the moral category, the person must exemplify that virtue habitually and unwaveringly5. Common virtues considered include, but are not limited to, charity, compassion, courage, honesty, loyalty, and so on6. Virtue ethics as an ethical theory is solely person based, focused entirely upon the character, values and intent of the person doing the act without looking at the actual consequence to those related to the act. 3 Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 92. 4 Miller, Michael Ben. “Virtue Ethics.” 23 Feb. 2017, Tallahassee, Florida State University, Ethical Issues and Life Choices. Slide 4. 5 Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 175. 6 Miller, Michael Ben. “Virtue Ethics.” 23 Feb. 2017, Tallahassee, Florida State University, Ethical Issues and Life Choices. Slide 4. Utilitarianism and its overall focus on the concept of consequentialism as the sole determinate of morality completely disregards vital components of the ethics of an action, its actor, and the result; the means by which an action is executed and the motives by which an action is instigated are not considered under utilitarianism, however they hold a firm and decisive bearing on the true morality of both a person’s action and its result. Why a person does something and how they do it go hand in hand when trying to decide whether they are ethical in doing so and whether the action itself is ethical at the end. In the case of York vs. Story 1963, a utilitarian perspective would find the result of an unlawful, degrading and ethically unjust action morally sound solely because the result of the action saw a greater amount of happiness in the majority involved as opposed to unhappiness in a single person. York vs. Story 1963 was a case dealing with the defendant, police officer Ron Story of the Chino police department, and the plaintiff, Angelynn York, in which Story acting under his “police authority” subjected York to a series of unlawful and degrading photographs (to which she objected) of her in the nude and in indecent positions. Story claimed that the pictures were necessary to document “bruises”, however York assured him this was not the case as the bruises would not show in any photograph. Story later told York that the photos did not come out and that he had discarded them from existence. In actuality, he went on to make copies and share the nude pictures to the rest of the Chino police department; the officers involved would then go on to receive a great amount of happiness from this action, leaving the majority of persons involved happier as a result. York sued the officer and the police department and won the case7. York’s rights under the law of the United States as well as her indivisible human rights were violated drastically by Story’s initial act of taking the pictures, and further when he distributed these pictures to the department. Story’s means of taking the pictures 7 Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 106-107. and distributing them were immoral as they were unlawful and damaging to York. His motives were malicious as he knowingly and purposefully broke the law and stripped York of her rights for his own personal gain and happiness. “Utilitarianism requires [an actor] to be as strictly impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator”8; the fault of utilitarianism is found within that statement. “Benevolent” is defined as being well-meaning and kind. In no way, did officer Story act benevolently towards Ms. York by directly lying to her and reducing her to a nude and indecent state solely for the benefit of himself and those like him at the Chino police department. His benevolence is non-existent and therefore utilitarianism in this situation will within itself, implode. Additionally, utilitarianism requires the treatment of all individuals as equal when considering a moral or immoral situation. If officer Story “needed” to take pictures of a family member or significant other rather than a random civilian, would he have committed to the same act to bring about great happiness to his department with the pictures? The virtues of loyalty cannot be considered, as means and motives do not play a part in determining morality under utilitarianism. A proponent of utilitarianism will ask in rebuttal to these points, does one person’s unhappiness outweigh the happiness of many people; “many” reaching amounts anywhere greater than the amount of the unhappy. The simple fact that more people are made happier with the least amount of unhappy people in an end result should conquer over ethical thinking and dictate the actions of moral agents. Story can be viewed as a moral agent as he acted to heighten the happiness of his entire police department, which significantly surpass the one unhappy Ms. York. Taking the pictures and leading Ms. York to believe they did not come out and that he had destroyed them indefinitely was Story’s way of sparing her of any shame, embarrassment, or pain. Anticipating her to remain unaware of his keeping and distribution of the pictures while the police department 8 Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 102. benefits and enjoys them without her knowing of any potential wrongdoing against her plays to the utilitarian view that what Story did was indeed moral. Story’s efforts towards increasing the majority’s happiness while accounting for the exclusion of pain for Ms. York, or at least sacrificing her to make many others better off in respect to their happiness, is an ethically sound justification of his actions. Further, in response to the claim that utilitarianism dictates that Story commit his act in the same fashion even if it were a family member or significant other will be rebutted by a utilitarian as he/she will maintain that utilitarianism is commonsensical and that such a response to a scenario is preposterous as it is not a true simulation of the real world. Virtue ethics is highly susceptible to objection. Virtue ethics is problematic in a similar sense as is cultural relativism; the virtues of people of different cultures around the globe overlap, differ, and change, therefore leaving morality of a character’s virtue up to chance and variance, contingent upon said character’s location in the world and corresponding culturally relevant virtues. Similarly, virtue ethics is disposed to immorality as moral virtues can be present and exemplified in an action or situation, but that situation or act could end up being an immoral one. The goal of virtue ethics to create a state of rules and norms relative to the virtues of character exhibited by people falls highly prone to abuse and can end up turning a virtue into a vice that ultimately results in an unethical action and result. Virtue ethics also risks potentially contradicting one virtue with another, creating a moral quandary that may ultimately result in an unethical action or outcome. A great deal of thought experiments embody the pitfalls of virtue ethics and present the vulnerability of this philosophical position to immoral acts and outcomes. For instance, a poor man who robs a bank for the sake of using that money for moral acts, such as feeding his young children and sick wife, or acquiring health care for his terminally ill child or mother. It takes courage to rob the bank, it takes loyalty to use the money for a loved one’s betterment (saving their life), it takes benevolence, compassion and charity to understand that if the man had not done this, great pain and loss (potentially death) would come about. Similarly, honesty, patience, prudence, self-discipline, etc. are all virtues relinquished and abandoned by robbing the bank. Does the man act on virtue or vice? Does he achieve a greater good and happiness in the end, or has he done wrong and further escalated his problematic situation? Surely regarding the virtues by which he acts on, his motives, heart and character lie in the right place as he tries to save life, but the means by which he has done so ultimately result in an immoral act. A proponent of virtue ethics will argue that this thought experiment, while potentially valid, does not discredit the validity of virtue ethics as the theory is commonsensical and maintains that the virtues present at the time of a person’s action deem its morality. Virtues turned to vices do not apply and therefore if a virtue is used as a vice then virtue ethics will deem that person’s act to be immoral; this idea appropriates the correct judgement of morality upon an action. Utilitarianism operates on the premise of consequentialism, confirming that the outcome of an action is the determinate factor of the morality or immorality of it. The confirmation of an act as moral or immoral lies within the happiness ratio of the result; as long as more people are made happy than are made unhappy, the act is moral. Virtue ethics looks to an actor’s motives, virtues, upon determining whether he/she has acted in a morally just way or not. As the objections of both utilitarianism and virtue ethics are analyzed and the counter arguments to those objections are accounted for, virtue ethics looks to encompass a more holistic and practical approach by looking towards a person’s means and motives regarding an action, rather than basing the morality of the action solely on making more people happy with the result of the action than are made unhappy. By this philosophy, utilitarianism allots a higher susceptibility to immoral and unethical actions and results as it creates a large grey area for immoral agents to bend utilitarianism to their liking and use the doctrine as a bypass for committing unethical acts and labeling them as moral. Therefore, the institution and practice of virtue ethics, when challenged against utilitarianism on the premise of true and accurate moral deeming, is superior with less disposition to immoral results. Works Cited Rachels, Stuart, and James Rachels. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill Education, Dubuque, 2015, pp. 91-97; 102-111; 173-187. Miller, Michael Ben. “Virtue Ethics.” 23 Feb. 2017, Tallahassee, Florida State University, Ethical Issues and Life Choices.