Melbourne Institute Policy Briefs Series Policy Brief No. 4/15 Beyond Nudge: The Potential of Behavioural Policy Reuben Finighan THE MELBOURNE INSTITUTE IS COMMITTED TO INFORMING THE DEBATE Beyond Nudge: The Potential of Behavioural Policy* Reuben Finighan Melbourne Institute of Applied Economic and Social Research The University of Melbourne Melbourne Institute Policy Brief No. 4/15 ISSN 2201-5477 (Print) ISSN 2201-5485 (Online) ISBN 978-0-7340-4385-6 July 2015 * I thank Deborah Cobb-Clark, Paul Jensen, Guyonne Kalb and Mike Pottenger for useful comments and suggestions. For correspondence, email <reuben.finighan@unimelb.edu.au>. Melbourne Institute of Applied Economic and Social Research The University of Melbourne Victoria 3010 Australia Telephone (03) 8344 2100 Fax (03) 8344 2111 Email melb-inst@unimelb.edu.au WWW Address http://www.melbourneinstitute.com Melbourne Institute Policy Briefs Series The Policy Briefs Series is a collection of research publications that examines current policy issues and provides an independent platform to examine pertinent issues in public debate. Log onto melbourneinstitute.com or follow @MelbInstUOM for more details on this and other series from Australia’s leading and longest standing research institute in the field of economics and social policy. Abstract Policymakers often mistakenly see behavioural policy as synonymous with “nudging”. Yet nudges are only one part of the value of the behavioural revolution—and not even the lion’s share. This policy brief looks at the full potential of behavioural policymaking. Using examples in cigarette regulation, retirement savings, and poverty, it makes three arguments: 1. Trade-offs between social welfare and individual freedom of choice affect both nudges and conventional policy tools (like mandates, taxes and transfers). Nudges are not special tools that avoid such trade-offs. 2. Nudges typically sacrifice social welfare in favour of individual choice, and for this reason many well-known nudges will be unattractive in Australia. Some nudges can, however, play a complementary role by fine-tuning conventional policy regimes. 3. Conventional policy tools will continue to be the most powerful tools for countering behavioural biases, and have the most promise for driving major, behaviourallyinformed reforms in Australia. Policymakers should not ask “can we nudge this?”, but should instead ask how behavioural evidence changes the way they think about all the options in the policy toolkit. JEL classification: D03, D60 Keywords: Behavioural economics, behavioural policy, public policy, nudges, regulation, paternalism 2 Behaviouraleconomicsisbeinghotlydebatedinpolicymakingcirclesacrosstheworld.In Australiatoo,ithasbeenwelcomedwiththeblendofenthusiasmandscepticismthatisrightly duetoanyparadigmshift.Whilethefieldhaswonsubstantialacademiccredibility—with economistswidelyacceptingthatbehaviouraleconomicscanimproveuponthestandard analysisinimportantways—itfacesanewsetofcontentiousquestions.Whatarethefield’s practicalpolicyimplications?Doesbehaviouralpolicymakinghavethepotentialtocontribute bigideasandstimulateimportantreforms,orwillitmerelytinkerattheedges? Intryingtoanswerthesequestions,manypublicservantssubstitutethemwithanother:“what isthepotentialofnudges?”Thisisanerror,andapotentiallyseriousone.Nudgesarenot synonymouswithbehaviouralpolicymaking,butrepresentjustonepartofitsvalue.Theclose identificationofnudgeswithbehaviouraleconomicsislargelyahistoricalquirk:Sunsteinand Thaler’sgroundbreakingNudge(2008,YaleUniversityPress)wasthefirstbooktopopularise behaviouralpolicymaking,andhaspowerfullyframedthediscussion. Thispolicybriefaimstotakeamorecompletelookatthepotentialofbehaviouralpolicymaking, payingspecialattentiontopolicytoolsbeyondthenudge.Nudges,itargues,largelytinkeratthe edges.Majorreforms,especiallyinAustralia,aremorelikelytocomethroughusingbehavioural evidencetoinformtheuseofconventionaltools,liketaxes,transfersandmandates.Behavioural policymakingdoesnotmeanasking,“canwenudgethis?”Muchlikeconventionalpolicymaking, itinvolvesweighingeachoftheoptionsinthepolicytoolkittofindthetoolthatbestbalances thevalueofindividualchoicewiththemagnitudeofpotentialwelfaregains.Whatisnewabout behaviouralpolicymakingisthatittakestherichbodyofbehaviouralevidenceintoaccount. Thebriefbuildsthiscaseuponthreekeyinsights: 1. Trade‐offsbetweenagencyandwelfareaffectbothnudgesandconventionaltools. Nudgesarenotspecialtoolsthatcanachievemajorwelfaregainswithoutinterfering withchoice.Inpractice,theyareaffectedbythesametrade‐offsasconventionaltools. 2. Nudges,whichSunsteinandThalerpointouthavebeeninuselongbeforeNudge, havegenerallybeenbestsuitedtodrivingmodestchangesinbehaviouratlow cost.Theytendtoplayacomplementaryrole,extendingtheeffectofconventional policyregimes.Onlyunderidealconditionsaretheypowerfulbythemselves. 3. Conventionalpolicytoolslikemandates,taxesandtransfershavebeen,andwill continuetobe,themostpowerfultoolsforcounteringbehaviouralbiases.The major,prosperity‐enhancingreformsthatbehaviouraleconomicswilldriveinthe comingdecadeswill,forthemostpart,employconventionalpolicytools. 3 Theoreticalfoundations:Behaviouralbiasesandmarketfailure Thebehaviouraleconomicsliteratureexplainsobservedbehaviourastheinteractionoftwo factors:normativepreferences(whattheindividualactuallywantstoachieve,orwhatwould actuallymaximisetheirwelfare),whicharethendistortedbybehaviouralbiasestoform revealedpreferences(theactualchoicesobserved,whichoftenfailtomaximisewelfare).The literaturedescribeshundredsofdifferentbehaviouralbiases,andamultitudeofthemcould applytoagivenpolicyproblem.Forexample,thetypicalindividualholdsanormative preferencetosaveenoughtohaveacomfortableretirement.Intheabsenceofasupportive policyregimelikesuperannuation,thispreferencemaybedistortedbypresentbias,analytic errors,forgetfulness,inattention,andmanybiasesbeyondthese.Foracomplex,intertemporal choicelikesavings,thislistofbiasescouldgoonandon. Biasesareusuallyorganisedintothreecategories:first,imperfectoptimisation,comprisingthe biasesthatpreventusfromcalculatingtheconsequencesofourchoices,suchasthebiastoward forecastingexponentialgrowthasthoughitwerelinear;second,boundedself‐control,including psychologicalphenomenalikeprocrastination,emotionsandimpulses,whichpreventusfrom implementingournormativepreferences(andguaranteethefailureofourNewYear’s resolutions);andthird,non‐standardpreferences,wherewesimplywantthingsthat conventionaleconomistsdonotexpectustowant,suchastoavoidexperiencingpainfullosses evenifthismeanswinninglessoverall.Notethislastcategoryincludessomephenomenathat canbegenuinedesires,likeconformitywithsocialnorms,althoughthesetooareregularly exploited—forexample,bymarketerspayinghandsomeactorstosmokecigarettes. Whenbehaviouralbiasesdistortnormativepreferences,thedecisionswemakemaybefarfrom welfare‐maximising.ScholarslikeBrigitteMadrianarguethatbiasesshouldthereforebe regardedasanewclassofmarketfailure.1Behaviouralmarketfailures,likeotherkindsof marketfailure,openuppotentialroomforgovernmentintervention.Wherepolicyiswell‐ designed,itmayimprovetheefficiencywithwhichthemarketproducessocialwelfare. Conventionalpolicytoolstypicallyaddressmarketfailures,orindeedachieveotherpolicygoals, byshiftingmonetaryincentivesorrestrictingwhatpeoplecanchoose.Theyincludetaxesand subsidies,mandatesorregulations,andvariouskindsofmaterialtransfers.Nudges,onthe otherhand,eschewmonetaryincentivesorstrongrestrictionsonchoice,andinsteaddepend uponsmallchangesin“choicearchitecture”thatgentlyguidechoicesinthedesireddirection. Nudgesareonlyeffectivebecauseofthewaysinwhichreal‐worldpeoplearedifferenttothe 4 rational,self‐interestedagent—inRichardThaler’sterms,goodnudgeswillaffectthereal‐world “Humans”ofpsychology,butnottheperfectlyrational“Econs”ofeconomics.Notethat conventionaltoolscanbestrengthenedbehaviourally,suchthatanEconwouldnotnoticethe change(e.g.reframeanincentiveasaloss,morepainfulforHumanssubjecttolossaversion). Importantly,abehaviouralpolicyproblemdoesnotnecessarilycallforanudgesolution.Aswe shallsee,nudgesandconventionalpolicyinterventionscanbeusedtoresolveeither behaviouralorconventionalpolicyproblems.Table1illustratesthiswithamatrixoffour possibilities—althoughnotethatpolicyproblemsareoftenamixoftheconventionalandthe behavioural,andinterventionsareoftenamixofnudgesandconventionalapproaches. Table1:Therangeofapproachesavailabletothebehaviourally‐informedpolicymakertoresolve bothconventionalandbehaviouralpolicychallenges Conventionalpolicyproblem Behaviouralpolicyproblem Conventional intervention E.g.alignteacherinterestswith studentlearningbyprovidingapay bonusforbetterstudent performance. E.g.toovercomesavingsmyopia,use amandate(e.g.superannuation)ora financialincentivetoincrease savings. Nudge intervention E.g.alignteacherinterestswith E.g.toovercomesavingsmyopia,use studentlearningbyprovidingsocial anudge‐likeinterventionsuchaspre‐ rewards,likerecognitionandthanks. commitmenttosaving. InsightOne:Bothnudgesandconventionaltoolsaresubjecttotrade‐offs betweenagencyandwelfare Nudge‐likepoliciesarenotnew.Policymakershavelongintuitedthatpeoplearenotperfectly rational—thatframingisimportant,thatwefollowsocialnorms,thatwetendtostickwith defaults,andsoon.Whatrecentadvancesinbehaviouraleconomicshavedoneisdramatically enrichedourunderstandingofhownudgesworkandhowtheyshouldbedesigned—and, notably,increasedtheirsalience.Asimportantly,orperhapsevenmoreso,behavioural economicshasimprovedourunderstandingofwhenconventionaltoolsshouldbeusedand howtheyshouldbedesigned.Why,then,hasalltheemphasisbeenonthenudge? Theanswerispartlypolitical.SunsteinandThalerwroteNudgewithintheuniquepolitical contextoftheUnitedStates,wherethelibertarianismofpoliticalentitiesliketheTeaPartyisa powerfulforcetobereckonedwith.Theypromotethepoliticalphilosophyof“libertarian 5 paternalism”asawayofresolvingthetensionbetweenlibertariansandprogressives—onthe onehand,thedesiretopreserveindividuals’agencyinbeingabletochoosewhattheyprefer, andontheother,thegrowingrecognitionthatindividuals’choicesarestronglyshapedby cognitivelimitationsandcontextualfactors,withsometimessevereconsequencesforwelfare.2 Nudgesaresupposedtoinfluencechoicesinwaysthatincreasewelfarebutthatavoidcoercing choices,lettingpolicymakerssteerasafecoursebetweenthesewarringtribes. Iftheideaofavoidingpoliticallychargedtrade‐offsbetweenwelfareandagencysoundstoo goodtobetrue,unfortunatelythisisbecauseitistoogoodtobetrue.Thedistinctionbetween nudgesandconventionaltoolsturnsouttobeexaggerated,withnudgessubjecttomuchthe sametrade‐offs.Taketwoexamples:first,theSaveMoreTomorrownudgescheme,whichhas beentoonon‐coercivetobeeffective;andsecond,effortstoreducesmoking,anexampleof nudgesthatareeffectivepreciselybecausetheyarecoercive. Savingsbehaviourisstronglyaffectedbyarangeofbiases,andthecelebratedSaveMore Tomorrowschemeusesasetofcleverlydesignednudgestocounterthem.Thescheme’smost importantinnovationisadefaultautomaticescalationinsavingsovertime,soindividualswill savemoreinfutureyearswithoutexperiencingalossinincometoday.Inanearlytrial,average savingsreachedalmost14%.Yetactualimplementationhasbeenlessimpressive:amajorityof employersofferedautomaticescalationby2011,butonly11%ofemployeeschosetoenrolin theplan.Theescalationdefaultwas3%over3years,withnofurtherincreasesthereafter.The US‐widesavingsrateincreasedbyafeeble0.33%,3atinyfractionoftheeffectachievedby schemeslikeAustralia’ssuperannuation—withenormousimplicationsforwelfare. Theproblemwithagency‐preservingnudgeslikeSaveMoreTomorrowisthattheycontinueto relyuponthediscreditedrationalmodel.Peoplemustchoosetoparticipateandmustchoose therightsettings,butthesearechoicesthatthebehaviouralevidenceclearlyshowswecannot reliablymake.YetifanudgeschemelikeSaveMoreTomorrowwasstrengthenedenoughtobe effective—say,allemployersarerequiredtoplaceemployeesinopt‐outsavingsescalation schemes,withahighdefaultsavingsrate,andpenaltiesforthosewhodoopt‐out—thenit effectivelybecomesacoercivemandatewithacostlyescapeclause.Evidencefromthe behaviouralsciencessuggeststhateventhisschemecouldbewelfarereducing,becausepeople whochoosetoopt‐outoftendosoirrationally,withsometimesenormouswelfarecosts. Anoppositecaseisillustratedbycigarettesmokingnudges,whicharesubstantiallymore coercivethantheSaveMoreTomorrowscheme.Plainpackagingrulesmakecigarettes 6 unattractive;theQuitcampaignprovidesservicesthatpromptsmokerstoplanaheadandmake commitments;removingcigarettesfromviewandsellingthemataseparatecountermakes themhardertoaccess;healthwarningsplacedatthepointofsalemakeforatimelyand emotionallypowerfulreminder;andsocialstigmapitssmokersagainstthepowerfulforcesof socialconformity.Peoplearestillfreetoexercisethechoicetosmoke,buteverynudgeinthe bookispointingintheotherdirection.Thoughthisisanudgeregime,itisclearlyhighly coercive—anditispreciselythehighcostsimposedonsmokersthatmakestheregimeeffective. InsightTwo:Nudgesarebestsuitedtodrivingmodestchangesinbehaviour atlowcost,andcanenhancetheeffectsofconventionaltools Nudgesarenotspecialtoolsthatevadeagency‐welfaretrade‐offs.Theyare,nonetheless,very usefulundertherightconditions.Thispolicybriefwillnotattempttoimproveuponthemany excellentoverviewsthatalreadyexist.Amoreimportantquestionforthebriefisthis:given nudgessometimescompletelyshiftaggregatebehaviour,andonotheroccasionsareentirely ineffective,whenshouldpolicymakersbeparticularlyenthusiasticaboutthepotentialof nudges? Awell‐designednudgemaybeaparticularlypowerfulpolicyoptionwhere: 1. individualunderlyingpreferencesarerelativelyhomogeneousandarealreadyaligned, oronlyweaklymisaligned,withthedesiredbehaviour; 2. thecognitivebiasesthatdistortunderlyingpreferencescanbeeasilyovercome,orused tothepolicymaker’sadvantage;and 3. eitherindividualchoicecannotbeavoided,oragencyisvaluableandthebenefitsof preservingagencyarenotoutweighedbywelfarecosts—ineitherofthesecases,the useofstrongerpolicyoptionsisnotpossible. Organdonationnudgesaretheposterchildforsuchsuccess:(1)alargemajorityofpeoplehold normativepreferencesthatarealignedwiththesociallyoptimaldecisiontodonate;and(2)the decisiontodonateisnotfixedbypowerfulbiases,butislargelytheresultofadefaultbiasthat policymakerscaneasilyharness.Theseconditionsallowanudge—aswitchfromanopt‐intoan opt‐outdefault—tocompletelytransformoutcomes,suchthatamajorityratherthanaminority choosetodonate.Onpoint(3),anudgeissuperiortoamandateherebecauseagencyiscrucial: peoplecannotreasonablybeforcedtodonatetheirorgans,andthebenefitsofpreservingchoice arejudgedtooutweighthecosts. 7 Amoremodestexampleisaprogramaimedatimprovingdrugprescriptionchartstoreduce medicalerrorsinhospitals:(1)doctorsandnursesholdanormativepreferencetoenter,and read,therightdrugandprescribeddosagefromtheprescriptionpaperwork;(2)theproblemof illegiblehandwritingcaneasilybeovercomewithbetterdesignedforms;and(3)thisisacase wherethebehaviourisalreadymandatedtothehilt—medicalpractitionersfacestrong incentivestodeliverthecorrectdrugsanddosages.Nudgescanhelpstaffcomplywiththe mandate(and,formostpractitioners,theirownpreferences).Indeed,thenewchartsvirtually eliminatederrorscausedbyconfusionbetweenmilligrams,or“mg”,andmicrograms,or“mcg”.4 Inmanycasestheseconditionsarenotmet,andnudgeswillproducerelativelysmallgainsat themargin—albeitusuallyatverylowcost.Theywillbeauseful,butlimited,partofawider policymix. InsightThree:Conventionalpolicytoolswillcontinuetobethemost importanttoolsforcounteringmanybehaviouralbiases Policymakersdonottypicallythinkofconventionalpolicyinstrumentsascentraltobehavioural policymaking,yettheyshould.Thissub‐sectionprovidesexampleswhereabehaviouralanalysis ofapolicyproblemfavourstheuseofaconventionalpolicytool,withexamplesprovidedunder mandates,standardincentives,andtransfers. Mandatesandregulation Mandateshavebeenthetoolofchoiceformanyimportantwelfareoptimisationproblems— seatbelts,bicyclehelmets,cigaretteadvertising,rentalpropertystandards,fairmortgage contracts,waterfluoridation,milkpasteurisation,superannuation,minimumwages,andmuch beyond.Regulationsarethemostpowerfulinstrumentsforshapingbehaviour,withthelevelof interferenceincreasingastheymovefromrequirementsorrestrictionsimposedonmarketing (e.g.paydayloanadvertising),toproductattributes(e.g.unfairinterestrates),andfinally behavioursorwholeproducts(e.g.paydaylending). Theirstrengthgivesthemhighpotentialforbothbenefitandharm,soitisunsurprisingthat theyareoftencontroversial.Benefitismostlikelywherenormativepreferencesarerelatively homogeneoussothataone‐size‐fits‐allmandatecanproducebenefitsformostpeople;where choiceerrorsarecommonandcostlyintheabsenceofamandate;andwhereagencyisnottoo 8 highlyvalued.Harmislikelywherenormativepreferencesareheterogeneous,andindividuals areblockedfromundertakingbehavioursthatgenuinelyenhancetheirwelfare. Mandatescanimprovewelfareincasesofboundedself‐controlorimperfectoptimisation. Beshearsetal.(2014)provideanexampleofhowmandatescanaddressboundedself‐control: theystudyamodelofretirementsavingswhereindividualsaresubjecttodifferentdegreesof presentbias,andthereforedifferentlevelsoflikelihoodforwithdrawingfromtheirsavingstoo early.Whatlevelofpenaltyonearlywithdrawals,todiscouragethebehaviour,wouldmaximise welfare?Theiranalysisfindsthewelfare‐maximisingpenaltyis100%—thatis,withdrawing shouldbeimpossible.Alowerpenaltydoesallowasmallnumberofpeopletowithdrawearlyin arationalway,buttheirwelfaregainsarecompletelyoverwhelmedbythewelfarelosses experiencedbythosewhoirrationallywithdrawduetopresentbias.5 Thisisoneweaknessofnudge‐basedsavingschemesthatallowopt‐outs,likeSaveMore Tomorrow:thepeoplewhoopt‐outofsuchschemesmaybelievetheycandobetterwithoutit, butthisistypicallynotthecase.Onaverage,theyexperiencesignificantwelfarelosses.Indeed, theUSInternalRevenueServiceimposesa10%penaltyonearlysavingswithdrawalfrom 401(k)plans,butevenso,forevery$1thatissaved,$0.40iswithdrawnprematurelyat substantialcost. Australia’ssuperannuationpolicyusefullyhighlightsanotherpropertyofasuccessfulmandate: popularconsent.Becausemandatesareopentochargesofpaternalism,theydependheavily upondemocraticlegitimacy.Mandatesaremostlikelytosucceedwhentheyareunderstoodto havebeenimposedbyacommunityuponitself,withoutmarginalisingunderrepresentedsub‐ groups;andwhentheyenactmostindividuals’normativepreferences,withouteliminatingany cherishedchoices.Inthecaseofsuperannuation,mostpeopledowishtosaveadequatelyand over80%ofAustraliansareinfavourofthescheme. Standardincentives Incentivesaremostusefulwhenchoicesareshapedbyself‐controlbiases.Theliteratureisthus focusedheavilyuponpolicyproblemslikethepromotionofhealthybehaviours,suchasquitting smokingorgoingtothegym;educationaloutcomes,likestudentperformance;andlabour marketoutcomes,likeincentivesforfindingajoborforworkingharder.Somepeoplerecognise thattheylackself‐control,andwillwillinglyimposecostsuponthemselvesinwaysthatwould bebizarreforarationalagent.Forexample,studieshavefoundthatdataentryworkers 9 willinglysubjectthemselvestopaymentschemeswithhighpotentialdownside,butnoobvious upside—forexample,theythreatenthemselveswithsubstantialmonetarylossiftheyfailto reachadailydesiredtarget,say,1,000entriesinaday.Peoplechoosesuchschemesas commitmentdevices,andtendtoworkharderundersuchself‐imposedthreats. Letusreturntocigaretteaddictionasaprimeexampleofindividualsstrugglingtoimplement theirnormativepreferences.Around70%ofsmokerswouldliketoquitatanygivenmoment, butonly3%succeedinagivenyear.Researchsuggeststhatsmokingimposescostsonone’s futureselfofaroundUS$35perpack,afigurethatisvastlyhigherthanwhatpeopleeverpayfor apack.Eventhemostcoercivenudgescannotprovideasignalthatreflectsthiscost.Cigarette taxes,ontheotherhand,canprovideamotivationalcountertoaddictionthatstudiessuggestis oneofthemoreeffectivepartsofapolicymixforreducingsmoking.6 Whileataximposeshighercostsonsmokersandhasbeencriticisedasregressive,behavioural evidencesuggeststhatitmayreducesmokingsufficientlythatitslong‐runeffectonmost individualsisnetpositive.Acigarettetaxcanthereforebeprogressiveratherthanregressive. BehaviouralstudiesofUSandCanadiansmokershavedemonstratedthatincreasingtaxeson cigarettescanactuallyincreasethewell‐beingofcigarettesmokers,byassistingthemtoexert self‐control.7 Incentivesarealsousedtoencouragepro‐socialbehaviour,andbehaviouralevidenceturnsout tobecrucialforsuccessfuldesign.Incentivesaremessages.Themerepresenceofanincentive, whichattachesapositiveornegativesignaltoachoice,canbemoreimportantthanthe magnitudeoftheincentive.Individualsinterpretthismessagewithinaparticularsocialcontext, andincentivesthusinteractwithsocialpreferencesinimportantways.Carelessuseof incentivescanbackfirebydisplacingand“crowding‐out”beneficialsocialpreferences,while well‐designedincentiveswillinstead“crowd‐in”andstrengthensocialpreferences. Whethercrowding‐outorcrowding‐inpredominatesisdeterminedbytheinterpretationofthe incentives.Incentivesaremorelikelytobackfirewhentheyareseenasmanipulativeor imposedfromabove;whentheyarearbitrary,difficulttoactupon,orunfair;whenthey encourageselfishmaximisationbehaviour;orwhentheysuggestthatanactivityisunpleasant andthereforemustbecompensated.Individualsaremorelikelytoseeanincentiveas legitimateiftheyunderstandandendorseitspurpose,andiftheyperceivetheincentiveas imposedbytheirpeersforthegoodofthegroupasawhole.Pro‐socialpreferencescanbe strengthenedwhensmallincentivesareusedtoreiterategroupnorms. 10 Finally,notethatincentivestendtobelesseffectiveforaddressingimperfectoptimisation biases.Anexcellentexampleisthedesignofanaircraftcockpit:earlydesignswereextremely complex,withhundredsofbuttons,leversandinstruments.Clearlypilotshaveeverypossible incentivetoflywell,giventheirverysurvivaldependsuponit—andyetthecomplexityofthe environmentledtocriticalerrors.Insuchacase,furtherincentivesareclearlyfutile. Optimisationbiasesarebettercounteredbynudges(suchasmakingthechoiceproblemeasier, ortheincentiveseasiertounderstand),aswellasmandatesandinsomecasestransfers, althoughincentivesmaybeusedtosuggestausefulstrategyforsolvingacomplexproblem(e.g. smallincentivesforinvestorstodiversifytheirportfolio). Transfers Therationalmodelholdsthattransfers,suchasthoseprovidedasunemploymentbenefits, shouldcomewithasignificanthasslecostinordertodisincentivisetheiruseandpreventmoral hazard. Acognitivescarcitymodelsuggestssomethingquitedifferent.8First,transfersshouldbe evaluatednotonlyfortheirwell‐beingbenefitsbutalsotheirimpactoncognitiveresources. CashinfusionsthatliberateIndianfarmersfrompoverty,forexample,produceincreasesinIQ ofnearlyafullstandarddeviation—adramaticeffectthatwouldbetheenvyofanyeducational system.Second,thehasslecostofmeetingtherequirementsofwelfareservicescanperversely imposea“cognitivetax”thatonlyaddstothecognitivechallengesofpoverty.Policymakers shouldbecarefultodesignschemesthatdonotposeexcessiveburdensonalreadycomplicated lives.9 Wherebehaviouralevidenceandtherationalmodelagreeisonhowindividualsspendsuch transfers:studiessuggestthatspendingisrelativelyrational.Thenumberofvicegoods purchasedasaproportionoftotalspendingtendstodecreasewhentransfersareprovided, whilespendingonpolicymakers’preferredgoods,likenutritiousfoods,tendstoincrease.10 Utah’shomelessnessstrategymakesforaninterestingcasestudy.In2005,“no‐stringsattached” housingwasfirstprovidedtothechronichomeless,withoutrequiringdrugtestsandwith minimalrent.Therewerefearsthattheprojectwould“incentivisemooching”,asperthe rationalmodel.Utah’schronicallyhomelesspopulationhassincefallen90%,andbytheendof 2015“maybevirtuallygone”.11Mostrecipientssuccessfullymakerentpayments,andcostsare 11 muchlowerthanthatofprovidingservicesforthechronicallyhomeless.Whilenobehavioural analysishasyetbeenperformed,theprojectmayhavepowerfulcognitiveeffects:providing housingsimplifiesthelivesofthehomeless,providesabufferagainstshocks,andfrees cognitiveresourcesforchallengingtaskslikequittingdrugsandfindingemployment. Conclusion Behaviouraleconomicshaspeeledawaytheaxiomsoftherationalmodeltorevealthelayersof psychologicalcomplexitylurkingunderneath.Policymakerscanusethisricherunderstandingof humanpsychologytoimprovethedesignofnudges,mandates,incentivesandtransfers.These toolsareessentialpartsofthepolicymix,andinpracticeareoftencomplementary. Conventionaltoolslikelyprovidethemostsubstantialpotentialforsignificantwelfare‐ enhancingreforms,whilenudgestendtobemosthelpfulforfine‐tuninginstitutionsinorderto bringefficiencygainsatlowcost.Whichevertoolisemployedforagivenpolicyproblem, policymakersshouldseektobalanceindividualagencywithsocialwelfare. Unlockingthispotentialwillrequirenewpracticesofpolicydesignandevaluation,focusedon generatingandapplyingnewevidence.Behaviourdepartsfromtherationalmodelinmyriad ways,andthereisanequallylargearrayofoptionsforsettingbehaviourontherightcourse. Suchawideandcomplexfieldofpossibilitymustbenavigatedwithaninterdisciplinarymixof methodsfromtheappliedbehaviouralandeconomicsciences,toidentifythecausalrelations thatunderliepolicyproblemsandthatmakeinterventionswork.Thisisbehavioural policymaking—theweighingofallpolicyoptionsinlightofthefullbodyofevidence. 1Madrian,B(2014)“Applyinginsightsfrombehavioraleconomicstopolicydesign”,WorkingPaperno. 20318,NationalBureauofEconomicResearch. 2Sunstein,C&Thaler,R(2008)Nudge.YaleUniversityPress. 3Benartzi,S&Thaler,R(2013)“Behavioraleconomicsandtheretirementsavingscrisis”,Science, 339(6124),1152–1153. King,D,Jabbar,A,Charani,E,Bicknell,C,Wu,Z,Miller,G,Gilchrist,M,Franklin,B&Darzi,A(2014) “Redesigningthe‘choicearchitecture’ofhospitalprescriptioncharts”,Healthservicesresearch,4(12). 5Beshears,J,Choi,J,Clayton,C,Harris,C,Laibson,D&Madrian,B(2014)“Optimalilliquidity”,paperfor theRetirementResearchConsortium,September26. 6E.g.seeLewit,E&Coate,D(1982)“Thepotentialforusingexcisetaxestoreducesmoking”,Journalof HealthEconomics,1(2),121–145. 7Gruber,J&Mullainathan,S(2005)“Docigarettetaxesmakesmokershappier?”,TheBEJournalof EconomicAnalysis&Policy,5(1). 8Mani,A,Mullainathan,S,Shafir,E&Zhao,J(2013)“Povertyimpedescognitivefunction”,Science, 341(6149),976‐980. 9Mullainathan,S&Shafir,E(2013)Scarcity:WhyHavingTooLittleMeansSoMuch.Macmillan. 10Evans,D&Popova,A(2014)“Cashtransfersandtemptationgoods:areviewofglobalevidence”,World BankPolicyResearchWorkingPaper6886. 11Rascon,J&NBCNews(2015)“Utah'sstrategyforthehomeless:givethemhomes”,NBCNews,May3. 4 12