Shared losses reduce sensitivity to risk: A laboratory study of moral

Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
Journal of Economic Psychology
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/joep
Shared losses reduce sensitivity to risk: A laboratory study
of moral hazard
Michael T. Bixter ⇑, Christian C. Luhmann
Stony Brook University, United States
a r t i c l e
i n f o
Article history:
Received 8 February 2013
Received in revised form 2 December 2013
Accepted 15 December 2013
Available online 19 December 2013
JEL classification:
C91
C70
PsycINFO classification:
2340
3020
Keywords:
Moral hazard
Risk
Shared losses
Decision making
a b s t r a c t
Moral hazards are said to occur when one party makes decisions that have potential negative consequences that will either be fully or partially experienced by another party. The
present experiment sought to explore moral hazard in a laboratory setting. Participants
made choices between certain and risky rewards. On some trials, participants bore the full
brunt of a loss if the risky reward was chosen and lost. On other trials, participants believed
losses would be shared with another party creating the opportunity for moral hazard. Our
design allowed us to measure whether the presence of a moral hazard influenced participants’ choice behavior and to quantify the magnitude of this influence. Results suggested
that participants were more tolerant of risk when they believed losses would be shared
with another party compared to choices when all of the loss would be experienced personally. More importantly, concern for the third party losses appeared to exert no influence on
choices whatsoever. These results were found when the third party was anonymous
(Experiment 1) but also when they met the third party face-to-face (Experiment 2). The
relationship between the current results and real-life moral hazards, as well as possible
future research directions, is discussed.
Ó 2013 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
1. Introduction
Moral hazard is a well known problem in the insurance industry. It is said to occur when individuals (as a result of the
provision of insurance) adopt behaviors that make it more likely that the event being insured against will occur (Rowell &
Connelly, 2012). Using the example of fire insurance, Crosby (1905) differentiated between two types of moral hazard:
direct and indirect. Direct moral hazard would be when a property owner (e.g., restaurant owner, landlord), recognizes,
as a result of depreciation, that she would gain more by setting the property on fire and collecting the insurance than
by continuing to own and operate the property. Indirect moral hazard1 would occur when a property owner, as a result
of being covered by insurance, decreases spending on fireproofing her property (e.g., failing to maintain the insulation of
structural members against heat). In the former scenario, the individual directly commits a deliberate action to bring about
a hazard, whereas in the latter it is an individual’s indifference, negligence, or increased risk-taking that leads to a greater
probability of the hazard occurring.
⇑ Corresponding author. Address: Department of Psychology, Stony Brook University, Stony Brook, NY 11794-25001, United States. Tel.: +1 (630) 281
0210.
E-mail address: michael.bixter@stonybrook.edu (M.T. Bixter).
1
Insurance agencies often refer to indirect moral hazards as morale hazards (McLeman & Smit, 2006).
0167-4870/$ - see front matter Ó 2013 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.joep.2013.12.004
Downloaded from http://www.elearnica.ir
64
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
Most empirical research on moral hazards has looked at the relationship between the presence or absence of a particular
insurance (as well as varying levels of coverage of the insurance) and the behavior of policyholders regarding the event being
insured against.2 These studies include, to name just a few, crop insurance (Quiggin, Karagiannis, & Stanton, 1993), workers’
compensation insurance (Butler & Worrall, 1991), sickness insurance (Khan & Rehnberg, 2009), and automobile insurance
(Cummins & Tennyson, 1996). Even though moral hazards are most often associated with individuals in insurance markets,
moral hazards can also exist on an organizational or institutional level (Okamoto, 2009). An example is the behavior of banks
and other depository institutions that have deposit insurance (Grossman, 1992; Roy, 2008). By having depositors’ accounts
guaranteed by a third party (usually a government), the institution has an incentive to make more risky investments because
any losses that result ultimately do not have an effect on the requirements the institution has to cover the costs of its funds (i.e.,
the accounts of its depositors).3
The negative consequences of moral hazards in insurance markets can have large societal costs that are not solely confined to the insured individuals and their insurance agencies. One well-known example of this occurrence is the moral hazard created by government-subsidized flood insurance (Bagstad, Stapleton, & D’Agostino, 2007; Botzen & van den Bergh,
2008; Burby, 2001, 2006; Huber, 2004). Because of the low-probability/high-impact nature of floods, as well as the uncertainty surrounding the probability of floods occurring, private insurers have historically not covered this natural hazard
without charging high premiums. As a result, the U.S. congress established the National Flood Insurance Program (NFIP)
in 1968, which, among other things, sought to reduce long-term flood damage and shift land development away from
flood-hazard areas (Anderson, 1974; Felton, Ghee, & Stinton, 1971). Instead, the percentage of U.S. residents living in coastal
counties rose from 28% in 1980 to 53% in 2003 (Cutter & Emrich, 2006). Moreover, since the inception of the NFIP, development in flood-hazard areas has actually increased (an estimated 53% over the first three decades of the program’s existence,
Burby, 2001). The NFIP currently insures 5.5 million policyholders with an estimated $1.2 trillion in provisional insurance
coverage (Federal Emergency Management Agency, 2012). Elements of the program, such as heavily-subsidized premium
rates by the federal government, have made development in flood-hazard areas more attractive and more affordable than
they would be otherwise, which contributes to the moral hazard. Additionally, it has been found that more than 85% of policyholders took no additional action to reduce flood vulnerability prior to experiencing flooding beyond what is minimally
required in order to receive the insurance (Burby, 2006).4 The result has been an increase in property damage, loss of lives, and
ecological damage due to flooding over the past couple of decades (Bagstad, Stapleton, & D’Agostino, 2007; Birkland, Burby,
Conrad, Cortner, & Michener, 2003; Cummins, 2006; Holladay & Schwartz, 2010).
Although most often associated with behavior in insurance markets, the concept of moral hazard can be applied more
generally to situations where risk and losses can be shared. Specifically, any situation where an individual or institution
is making decisions that have potential negative consequences that will be fully or partially shared with other parties, moral
hazard is possible. For instance, if an investment firm increases its risk-taking behavior because it knows that excessive
losses will be bailed out by an intervening government, the potential losses of the firm will be shared with the government
(i.e., taxpayers) and a moral hazard will have occurred (Okamoto, 2009). However, one does not have to look at the level of
modern finance to see this principle at work. Even something as simple as driving more recklessly when using a rental car
can be viewed as an example of a moral hazard.
As mentioned above, most of the empirical research on moral hazards has consisted of econometric studies investigating
changes in behavior due to insurance coverage. However, there have been a small number of laboratory studies examining
risk-sharing and distributed losses (Berger & Hershey, 1994; Deck & Reyes, 2008; Di Mauro, 2002). For example, Deck and
Reyes (2008) had undergraduate business students play a costly investment game. In the game, a participant was to make an
investment (ranging from $0 to $10). The larger the investment, the greater the probability that a $10 reward (minus the
investment) was received by the participant. For instance, an investment of $4 might result in a 50% chance of earning $6
total (10 4 = 6), with a 50% chance that no reward would be received (and the investment being subtracted from an initial
endowment). In this example, investments greater than $4 would lead to a greater chance of receiving the reward, but the
reward would be smaller, whereas the opposite was true for investments smaller than $4. Importantly, on some trials, there
was a second investor present. Their role was to make an investment that would be added to the initial investment. This
would increase the overall probability of the $10 rewards (minus the investment costs) being received by the two participants. Deck and Reyes (2008) found that participants’ investments were reduced when they knew that a second investor
was present. Presumably, this occurred because participants believed that the second investor would compensate for their
reduced initial investment. These results are relevant for the study of moral hazard because they show that participants were
more tolerant of risk (by making lower initial investments) when the risk was shared with another party. However, the task
used by Deck and Reyes is not entirely consistent with the concept of moral hazard. Specifically, even though risk was shared
2
Moral hazard is most often associated with changes in risky behavior in the insured (e.g., less fireproofing of a building when fire insurance is present), but
this is not exclusively the case. For instance, more generous health insurance policies can often lead to an increased consumption of medical services (e.g.,
Abraham, DeLeire, & Royalty, 2010; Joseph, 1972). Increased use of health and medical services is not necessarily associated with risky behavior (with risky
behavior referring to behavior that leads to a greater probability of some negative consequence occurring), but the increase demand of the services increases
the cost paid for by the insurance agency, so a moral hazard is said to occur. Situations where policyholders increase/exaggerate the size of an insurance claim
(such as stemming from overconsumption of a medical service) are usually referred to as ex post moral hazards (Di Mauro, 2002).
3
See Hooks and Robinson (2002) for empirical evidence that the introduction of state-sponsored deposit insurance in Texas led to increased risk-taking by
banks and subsequent bank failures in the 1920s. See Wheelock (1992) and Wheelock and Kumbhakar (1995) for similar results in Kansas.
4
In the sample that they studied, Blanchard-Boehm, Berry, and Showalter (2001) found this number to be 97%.
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
65
in the two-investor trials, losses were not. That is, on the two-investor trials, if the joint investment resulted in a loss, a participant still fully experienced the loss of her initial investment and did not share this loss with the second investor.
Even though laboratory studies of moral hazard have been scarce, there has been a recent interest in exploring social
influences on risk preferences more generally (for a review, see Trautmann & Vieider, 2011, chap. 29). This has included
studying risk taking in situations where choices are made on behalf of other individuals (Hsee & Weber, 1997; Humphrey
& Renner, 2011; Pahlke, Strasser, & Vieider, 2012a). For instance, it has been found that decision makers are less risk averse
when making choices on behalf of others than when making choices for themselves (Chakravarty, Harrison, Haruvy, &
Rutström, 2011). Other recent work has explored how other-regarding preferences involving risk or uncertainty differ from
those under certainty (Brennan, González, Güth, & Levati, 2008; Güth, Levati, & Ploner, 2008). This line of research is important because other-regarding preferences have traditionally been studied in riskless situations where payoffs are delivered
deterministically (e.g., the dictator and ultimatum games, Hoffman, McCabe, & Smith, 1996). This contrasts with many realworld situations in which social decisions involve varying degrees of risk, such as a financial portfolio manager entrusted to
invest her clients’ funds. Studying moral hazard in a controlled, laboratory setting has the ability to contribute to both of
these lines of research. That is, moral hazard involves risky choices in a situation where specific payoffs, namely losses,
are jointly experienced by two individuals. Moreover, the study of moral hazard also sheds light on the degree to which concern for other’s losses affects preferences in the presence of risk.
The goal of the current study is to explore moral hazard in a laboratory setting. In particular, we are interested in how the
sharing of potential losses with a third party affects individuals’ sensitivity to risk. By including instances in which an individual’s losses are asymmetrically shared with a third party, our study accurately simulates real-life moral hazards (cf. Deck
& Reyes, 2008). Specifically, the present study offers choices between certain and mixed gambles. The mixed gambles vary in
the magnitude of the potential rewards and the level of risk involved. On some of the trials participants must bear the full
brunt of a loss if the risky gamble is chosen and lost (i.e., the entire loss is subtracted from their total earnings). Importantly,
on other trials, losses (but not gains) are split with a third party (creating a moral hazard since participants only have half of
the loss subtracted from their total earnings). Our design allows us to investigate whether individuals are less sensitive to
risk when negative consequences will be shared with a third party, but it also allows us to quantify the magnitude of any
such change. Furthermore, because of the nature of moral hazard, our results may also be interpreted as reflecting the relative balance between individuals’ self-interest and their concern for others.
2. Experiment 1
2.1. Method
2.1.1. Participants
Participants were 20 Stony Brook University undergraduates. In exchange for participating in the study, participants
received partial course credit and monetary compensation of $5.
2.1.2. Task
The decision making task contained three types of trials: Standard, Shared Loss, and Matched. Each trial type consisted of
a choice between $15 to be delivered with certainty and a risky gamble consisting of a larger amount that could be gained
with some probability and lost with some probability. For the Standard trials, risky gambles offered wins/losses of $20, $30,
$40, $50, and $60. These amounts were paired with the following probabilities (in percentages) of winning the gamble: 50%,
60%, 70%, 80%, and 90%. An example of a Standard trial is shown in Fig. 1. This specific trial presents a choice between the
certain $15 and a gamble offering a 70% chance of gaining $30 and a 30% chance of losing $30. Whether the certain reward or
the risky reward was presented on the left or right side of the screen was randomized on each trial (the same was true for the
other two trial types described below).
The Shared Loss trials were the same as the Standard trials, except that the words ‘‘Shared Loss’’ were included beneath
the risky gamble. Participants were instructed that choosing the risky gamble and losing on such trials would result in the
loss being shared evenly between them and another participant that would be run in the experiment exactly one week later
(i.e., the third party).5 Choosing the risky gamble on Shared Loss trials and winning resulted in the gain being added fully to
participants’ total earnings (just as on the Standard trials). For the Shared Loss trial displayed in Fig. 1, if a participant chose
the risky gamble and won, the entire $30 would be added to her total earnings. However, if she chose the risky gamble and lost,
only half of the loss (in this case $15) would be subtracted from her total earnings. Participants were instructed that the other
half (the remaining $15) would be subtracted from the total earnings of the third party.
Matched trials were trials that contained risky gambles with an expected value (EV) that was equivalent to the risky gambles on Shared Loss trials assuming that participants considered the personal portion of the loss but completely disregarded
the third-party’s portion of the loss. For the Matched trials, simply dividing the losses in the Standard and Shared Loss trials
5
Participants were told that there were two types of players in this experiment, one who makes choices on the Shared Loss trials that have possible
consequences for both players and another who is solely affected by these consequences. In reality, there was only the former type, but participants were given
this instruction so that they did not think another participant had previously made choices that negatively affected their total earnings.
66
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
Standard Trial
Shared Loss Trial
Which would you prefer?
100% Win $15
70% Win $30
Matched Trial
Which would you prefer?
100% Win $15
Which would you prefer?
70% Win $30
30% Lose $30
100% Win $15
70% Win $30
30% Lose $15
30% Lose $30
Shared Loss
Fig. 1. Example trials for the three types of trials in the decision making task. Choices were always between a certain $15 and a larger risky reward that
varied in magnitude and the probability that it would be won or lost. On Shared Loss trials, 50% of the loss associated with the risky reward would be
experienced personally, with the other 50% being shared with the third party.
in half resulted in the same EVs of the Shared Loss trials if participants only considered the personal losses (see Fig. 1 for an
example trial). Fig. 2 presents the EVs of the risky gambles in both the Standard and Matched trial types. For the Shared Loss
trials, the subjective value of the risky gambles would be the same as the Standard trials if participants seek to avoid third
party losses exactly as they seek to avoid personal losses. If participants instead considered only the personal loss and
ignored the third party loss, the subjective value of the risky gambles on the Shared Loss trials would be the same as the
EVs of the Matched trials. If participants seek to avoid third party losses, but only to some extent, the subjective value of
the risky gambles on the Shared Loss trials would fall somewhere in between the Standard and Matched trials. As a result,
participants’ concern for third party losses on Shared Loss trials can be measured by comparing choices on Shared Loss trials
to the two extremes (i.e., choices on the Standard trials on the one hand and choices on the Matched trials on the other).
2.1.3. Procedure
Participants signed a consent form upon entering the lab. They were then directed to a small room where they were
tested individually. Next, the experimenter gave instructions to participants. The instructions included descriptions of the
different types of trials. Participants were also informed that if they accumulated an unspecified amount of earnings during
the experiment they would receive $5 in real money. This compensation scheme was used to incentivize participants so that
they made choices that were aligned with their actual risk preferences. Moreover, by having real money rewards, participants would believe that the Shared Loss trials could have real consequences for the third party. By leaving the earning
requirement unspecified, participants could not compute where their earnings were relative to the required amount needed
to receive the $5 reward (further aiding in trials being treated independently).
After receiving instructions, participants completed a brief practice session. Participants were told that their choices during practice did not contribute to their chance of receiving the $5; the practice session was solely to familiarize participants
with the task. The practice session contained 18 trials, with 6 Standard trials, 6 Shared Loss trials, and 6 Matched trials. After
practice, the experimenter answered any remaining questions. Participants were then told that they would begin the actual
Standard Trial Expected Values
$20W/$20L
$30W/$30L
$40W/$40L
$50W/$50L
$60W/$60L
0.50
0
0
0
0
0
0.60
4
6
8
10
12
0.70
8
12
16
20
24
0.80
12
18
24
30
36
0.90
16
24
32
40
48
Matched Trial Expected Values
0.50
$20W/$10L
5
$30W/$15L 7.5
$40W/$20L 10
$50W/$25L 12.5
$60W/$30L 15
0.60
8
12
16
20
24
0.70
11
16.5
22
27.5
33
0.80 0.90
14
17
21
25.5
28
34
35
42.5
42
51
Fig. 2. The expected values of the various risky gambles on both the Standard and Matched trials. Darker shades of green (red) mean the expected values of
the risky gambles were increasingly higher (lower) than the certain $15. (For interpretation of the references to color in this figure legend, the reader is
referred to the web version of this article.)
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
67
task and that all subsequent choices would contribute to their accumulated earnings and would thus influence whether or
not they received the $5. The experiment contained 75 trials, with 25 Standard trials, 25 Shared Loss trials, and 25 Matched
trials. Participants made choices on each trial by pressing the left or right arrow key on the computer keyboard. After each
choice, the screen was cleared and the next trial began two seconds later. Feedback was not given to participants after each
trial. This was to prevent participants’ choices from being influenced by the outcomes of past risky gambles (again to prevent
inter-trial dependencies). After completion of the task, participants were thanked and debriefed. All participants received the
$5 compensation regardless of their choices.
2.2. Results
Fig. 3A presents the proportion of trials on which participants chose the risky gamble. A repeated measures analysis of
variance (ANOVA) revealed a significant effect of trial type (F(2, 38) = 4.537, p < .05). Paired-samples t-tests showed that
the proportion of risky choices on the Standard trials (M = .43, SD = .16) was significantly lower than the proportion of risky
choices on both the Shared Loss trials (M = .52, SD = .18) (t(19) = 2.726, p < .05) and Matched trials (M = .52, SD = .20)
(t(19) = 2.483, p < .05). Choices on the Shared Loss and Matched trials did not differ significantly (t(19) < 1). These results
suggest that participants were more tolerant of risk when losses were believed to be shared with another party. Furthermore, the similarity between choices made on Shared Loss and Matched trials means that participants made choices on
the Shared Loss trials as if they only factored in the amount of a loss they would personally experience, entirely discounting
the shared portion of the potential loss.
Though the main effect of trial type was the a priori interest of the current study, we also conducted exploratory analyses
to evaluate whether the degree of risk affected risky choices. A 3 (trial type) by 5 (risk level) repeated measures ANOVA was
performed. Sphericity could not be assumed for the risk level factor and the interaction between trial type and risk level, so
the Greenhouse–Geisser correction was applied. Results indicate a significant main effect of risk level (F(2.94, 55.77) = 85.64,
p < .001) and a significant interaction between trial type and risk level (F(5.00, 95.08) = 3.72, p < .01) (the main effect of trial
type is reported in the previous paragraph). Comparing choices on the Standard and Shared Loss trials, significant differences
were found for the 60% and 70% risk levels (both ts > 3.16, ps < .006), but not for the 50%, 80%, and 90% risk levels (all
Proportion of Risky Choices
A
0.6
0.5
0.4
0.3
Standard
Shared Loss - Standard
B
Shared Loss
Matched
Trial Type
0.25
0.15
0.05
-0.05
0.5
0.6
0.7
0.8
0.9
Probability of Winning Risky Gamble
Fig. 3. Experiment 1. (A) The overall proportion of trials where the risky gamble was chosen broken down by trial type in Experiment 1. (B) The moral
hazard score refers to the proportion of Standard trials where the risky gamble was chosen subtracted from the proportion of Shared Loss trials where the
risky gamble was chosen. This difference score is broken down by risk level.
68
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
ts < 1.75, ps > .10). Fig. 3B presents the difference between choices on the Shared Loss and Standard trial types (what we refer
to as the moral hazard score) broken down by risk level. As is displayed, there was a difference of approximately .2 between
the two trial types at the 60% and 70% risk levels, which means that the proportion of risky choices on the Shared Loss trials
was 20 percentage points higher than the proportion of risky choices on the Standard trials. These results show that sharing
losses with another party did not reduce sensitivity to risk uniformly across all risk levels. This is most likely due to the fact
that participants, across trial types, rarely chose the risky gamble when the probability of winning was 50%, and rarely chose
the certain reward when the probability of winning was 80% and 90%. However, for the intermediate risk levels (i.e., 60% and
70%), the greater distance from the two extremes allowed differences between trial types to emerge.
Finally, we investigated how participants’ choices on the different trial types affected their expected earnings. Expected
earnings were computed for each participant by summing the expected values across trials based on participants’ choices.6
OLS regression was then used with the proportion of risky choices for the three trial types as the predictors and total expected
earnings as the criterion variable. As expected, the overall model accounted for a significant proportion of the variance in total
expected earnings (R2 = .65, F(3, 16) = 10.084, p < .001). Further, it was found that the proportion of risky choices on Shared Loss
trials was a marginally significant predictor of total expected earnings (b = .418, t = 1.82, p = .088), whereas choices on the other
two trial types were not significant predictors (ts < 1.23, ps > .238). This means that participants’ sensitivity to risk on the Shared
Loss trials was the strongest independent predictor of task performance. Specifically, participants with lower sensitivity to risk
on the Shared Loss trials were expected to earn more than participants with higher sensitivity. This illustrates why increased
risk-taking in the presence of a moral hazard can be in the self-interest of a decision maker (e.g., the insured) while simultaneously being bad for the third party (e.g., the insurer).
2.3. Discussion
The results of Experiment 1 show that individuals’ sensitivity to risk is reduced when losses are shared with a third party.
Importantly, it was found that participants made choices on Shared Loss trials as if they completely disregarded the shared
portion of the losses. This was evidenced by the finding that choices on the Shared Loss trials were indistinguishable from
choices on the Matched trials. Instead of tempering their own self-interest with concern for the third party, participants in
Experiment 1 made choices that maximized their own earnings at the expense of third parties. This finding stands in contrast
to the extensive body of work that has found individuals to exhibit strong other-regarding preferences (for reviews, see
Cooper & Kagel, 2009; Fehr & Schmidt, 1999; Sobel, 2005). To pursue this finding further, Experiment 2 sought to investigate
whether individuals would show concern for others’ losses under moral hazard when the social distance between the parties
was dramatically reduced.
3. Experiment 2
In Experiment 1, participants were instructed that choices on the Shared Loss trials would have potential negative consequences for themselves as well as another participant that would be run in the experiment a week later (the third party).
The nature of the third party was intended to simulate real-life moral hazard situations. That is, the two (or more) parties
that are sharing losses (e.g., an insurance company, a government) can often have little-to-no direct contact with each other
(Akerlof, 1997; Buchan, Johnson, & Croson, 2006). However, it could be argued that the social/temporal distance between
participants and the third parties in Experiment 1 may have artificially caused participants to disregard the shared portion
of the losses on the Shared Loss trials. For instance, some participants may have doubted that there was actually a third
party, which would lead those participants to ignore the amount of the shared losses that would be experienced by the third
party. Experiment 2 sought to explore whether the results of Experiment 1 generalize to situations in which participants had
direct contact with the third party. To do so, two participants were brought to the lab simultaneously and instructed that the
shared losses would be experienced by the other participant.
3.1. Method
3.1.1. Participants
Participants were a new sample of 20 Stony Brook University undergraduates. In exchange for participating in the study,
participants received partial course credit and monetary compensation of $5.
3.1.2. Task and procedure
The task and procedure of Experiment 2 were the same as Experiment 1, with the following exceptions. Pairs of participants were brought to the lab at the same time and received instructions in the same room. Participants were told that there
were two types of players in the task, one who would be presented the Shared Loss trials (referred to as Player A) and could
make choices that have potential consequences for the other player and another (referred to as Player B). Player B, on the
6
If the risky gamble was chosen on a Shared Loss trial, the expected value that was used was based on the amount of loss that would be personally
experienced by the participant (i.e., not the half of the loss that would be shared with the third party).
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
69
other hand, was not presented any Shared Loss trials (and as a result could not affect Player A’s earnings). Participants were
instructed that the computer would randomly assign one of the two participants to be Player A and the other to be Player B.
Moreover, participants were told that, at the end of the experiment, Player B would see how much was deducted from her
total earnings as a result of Player A’s choices on the Shared Loss trials. After receiving instructions, the two participants were
led to adjacent rooms where they performed the task individually. At the start of the task, both participants were told by the
computer that they were assigned to be Player A (i.e., the player that was presented Shared Loss trials).
3.2. Results
Fig. 4A presents the proportion of trials in which participants chose the risky gamble broken down by trial type. A
repeated measures ANOVA revealed a significant effect of trial type (F(2, 38) = 5.538, p < .01). Paired-samples t-tests showed
that the proportion of risky choices on the Standard trials (M = .41, SD = .18) was significantly lower than the proportion of
risky choices on both the Shared Loss trials (M = .49, SD = .20) (t(19) = 2.108, p < .05) and Matched trials (M = .52, SD = .20)
(t(19) = 4.439, p < .001). Choices on the Shared Loss and Matched trials did not differ (t(19) < 1). These results suggest that
the moral hazard effect found in Experiment 1 (i.e., increased risk-taking when losses are shared) was not confined to
situations in which large social/temporal distance separated the parties. Furthermore, the equivalent choices on Shared Loss
and Matched trials imply that participants entirely disregarded the portion of the losses shared by the third party, despite
having met this party in person.
We again performed exploratory analyses to assess how the level of risk affected the likelihood of choosing the risky gamble for each of the three trial types. A 3 (trial type) by 5 (risk level) repeated measures ANOVA was performed. Sphericity
could not be assumed for the risk level factor, so the Greenhouse–Geisser correction was applied. The main effect of risk level
was significant (F(2.66, 50.45) = 65.51, p < .001) (the main effect of trial type is reported in the previous paragraph), but the
interaction between trial type and risk level was not (F(8, 152) < 1). Fig. 4B presents the differences between choices on the
Standard and Shared Loss trials (the moral hazard score) broken down by risk level. As is displayed, the moral hazard effect
was not as confined to the moderate risk levels (i.e., 60% and 70%) as it was in Experiment 1.
Finally, we were interested to see how participants’ choices on the different trial types affected their task performance.
OLS regression was used with the proportion of risky choices for the three trial types as the predictors and total expected
earnings as the criterion variable. As expected, the overall model accounted for a significant proportion of the variance in
total expected earnings (R2 = .62, F(3, 16) = 8.570, p < .001). Further, it was found that the proportion of risky choices on
Shared Loss trials was a significant predictor of total expected earnings (b = .522, t = 2.60, p < .02), whereas choices on the
other two trial types were not significant predictors (ts < 1.20, ps > .25).
3.2.1. Cross-experimental analysis
Because the only substantive difference between Experiments 1 and 2 was the social/temporal distance between the two
parties, we wished to more directly explore whether reducing the distance between parties had any effect on participants’
choices. The mean moral hazard scores were similar across the two experiments (Experiment 1 = .082, Experiment 2 = .080;
t(38) < 1). The similarity in choice behavior across the two experiments was also evidenced by the finding that participants’
choices on the Shared Loss trials led to the third party incurring similar expected losses (Experiment 1 = $61.50, Experiment
2 = $59.93; t(38) < 1). Despite observing no overall differences in the moral hazard scores across the two experiments, we do
note that visual inspection of the data suggest that there was a subset of participants in Experiment 2 who were much more
risk-seeking on the Standard trials compared to the Shared Loss trials, with 15% of the sample in Experiment 2 having a moral hazard score less than .10 vs. 0% of the sample in Experiment 1.
3.3. Discussion
Just as in Experiment 1, the results of Experiment 2 demonstrated that individuals’ sensitivity to risk is reduced when
losses are shared with a third party. Furthermore, it was again found that participants’ choices on the Shared Loss trials were
indistinguishable from choices on the Matched trials. This is evidence that concern for the losses of the third party played no
role in choices made under moral hazard. Because previous research has shown that reducing social distance between parties encourages other-regarding preferences (e.g., Charness & Gneezy, 2008), it is surprising that a similar manipulation
failed to exert any obvious influence on the results of Experiment 2. Participants in Experiment 2 were put in direct contact
with the individual they believed was the third party, but made choices that were indistinguishable from those observed in
Experiment 1 (in which the third party was an unknown individual). This may suggest that the social aspects of moral hazards are psychologically distinct, or at least weaker, than those involved in more traditional behavioral economic tasks that
involve social factors (e.g., the Dictator game). Other possible explanations are reviewed in Section 4.
4. General discussion
The concept of moral hazard is well known in the insurance industry and in economics more generally (Grubel, 1971;
Kunreuther & Slovic, 1978; Rowell & Connelly, 2012). The present experiment sought to create a moral hazard situation
70
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
Proportion of Risky Choices
A
0.6
0.5
0.4
0.3
Standard
Shared Loss - Standard
B
Shared Loss
Trial Type
Matched
0.2
0.1
0
0.5
0.6
0.7
0.8
0.9
Probability of Winning Risky Gamble
Fig. 4. Experiment 2. (A) The overall proportion of trials where the risky gamble was chosen broken down by trial type in Experiment 2. (B) The moral
hazard score refers to the proportion of Standard trials where the risky gamble was chosen subtracted from the proportion of Shared Loss trials where the
risky gamble was chosen. This difference score is broken down by risk level.
in which participants made risky choices but would not bear the full brunt of a loss. It was found that participants were more
risk-seeking on Shared Loss trials that provided the opportunity for moral hazard compared to choices on Standard trials that
did not. This finding, in and of itself, may not be particularly surprising. However, the present experiment also included trials
that matched the moral hazard trials in expected value if participants only considered the personal portion of the loss on the
Shared Loss trials. Because choices were equivalent on the Shared Loss and Matched trials, we are able to additionally conclude that participants made choices exclusively reflecting the magnitude of the personal loss.
Though it would have been implausible to expect that choices on Shared Loss trials would resemble choices on Standard
trials (implying that participants valued their partner’s losses as much as their own), one might have reasonably expected
that choices on Shared Loss trials would fall somewhere between those on Standard trials and those on Matched trials. Such
a pattern would have suggested that choices under moral hazard reflect a compromise between self-interest and concern for
the third party; a pattern commonly observed in behavioral economic settings (Charness & Rabin, 2002; Cooper & Kagel,
2009; Fehr & Schmidt, 1999; Hoffman et al., 1996). In contrast, the observed pattern of results suggested that participants
were maximizing their own earnings by exposing third parties to losses.
It was also found that the proportion of risky choices participants made on the Shared Loss trials was related to their
total expected earnings. It could be argued that this was a result of the structure of the task. This is because the majority
of the risky gambles had expected values that were larger than the certain $15 (see Fig. 2). Thus, more risky choices might
naturally be expected to lead to greater total earnings. However, this explanation holds true for all three trial types. But as
the OLS regression analyses in both experiments showed, earnings were mostly strongly predicted by the number of risky
gambles accepted on Shared Loss trials. This appears to be evidence that participants who saw the Shared Loss trials as an
opportunity to ‘‘take advantage’’ of the situation, were better able to increase their expected earnings in comparison to
participants who failed to capitalize on this opportunity. These findings are often representative of real-life moral hazard
situations. That is, when two parties agree to share losses (or risk), the increased risk-taking that follows can often result
in short-term profits for one (or both) of the parties. However, there are many real-world situations where the moral
hazard created by the sharing of losses can lead to long-term negative consequences (e.g., bank failure, Hooks & Robinson,
2002; Wheelock & Kumbhakar, 1995). As a result, future research may consider exploring situations in which there
are tradeoffs between short-term gains stemming from increased risk-taking (in the presence of a moral hazard) and
long-term repercussions.
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
71
The results of Experiment 2 showed that decreasing the distance between parties did not have a substantial influence on
overall risk-taking on the Shared Loss trials. That is, in Experiment 1, participants believed that the third party that would
potentially be affected by their choices on the Shared Loss trials would be run in the experiment one week later. In Experiment 2, participants believed that the third party was the person who was in lab with them, received the instructions with
them, and performed the task in an adjacent room. The results of Experiment 2 showed that sharing potential losses induced
greater risk-taking in participants even with the added social pressure of possibly affecting the chance that another person
whom they have interacted with will earn a monetary reward. The results of Experiment 2 are especially surprising because
increased risk-taking on the Shared Loss trials can be seen as a lack of generosity. That is, by choosing the risky gamble on the
Shared Loss trials, a participant was exposing the third party to losses that she was not directly responsible for. Past research
in experimental economics and social psychology has found a strong influence of distance (whether temporal, social, or
spatial) on generosity in economic and bargaining behavior (Charness, Haruvy, & Sonsino, 2007; Handgraaf, Van Dijk, &
De Cremer, 2003). This is especially the case with ultimatum and dictator games, in which one player is asked to divide a
sum of money between herself and another player7 (for a review of these games, see Camerer & Thaler, 1995; Thaler,
1988). Previous research has found that reducing social distance between the two players (e.g., having participants meet
face-to-face) leads to increased offerings in the dictator game (i.e., more equitable divisions of the allotted money) (Bohnet
& Frey, 1999; Hoffman et al., 1996). Charness and Gneezy (2008) found that simply providing participants with the names of
their counterparts in a dictator game led to more generous divisions. Given that our participants took advantage of moral
hazards even when we decreased the social distance between participants and third parties, it may be the case that decision
makers do not see the sharing of losses as an issue of fairness or generosity.
One reason for this difference is that there may be a difference in how social distance affects other-regarding preferences
in riskless situations (e.g., allotments in the dictator game) and situations that involve risk or uncertainty (e.g., moral hazard). For example, Güth et al. (2008) conducted an experiment in which participants evaluated certain and risky rewards,
some of which would be personally experienced and some of which would be experienced by another, anonymous partner.
Whereas manipulating the level of risk of participants’ own payoffs affected participants’ evaluations, manipulating the level
of risk of the other partners’ payoffs did not. In a follow up study, Güth, Levati, and Ploner (2011) included a condition in
which participants first viewed a two-minute silent video of the person they believed was their partner. This manipulation
was designed to make the other partner more identifiable and reduce social distance. However, it did not influence participants’ evaluations. This is similar to the results of our Experiment 2, in which reducing the social distance between parties
did not alter risky choices on Shared Loss trials.
One reason that other-regarding preferences may differ in risky environments is because it is easier to justify selfish
behavior when payoffs are stochastic. This is because an individual can claim that inequitable outcomes were not a certain
consequence of their self-serving choices. This stands in contrast to inequitable allotments in the dictator game in which
inequitable outcomes are a direct and certain consequence of dictators’ choices. This explanation would suggest that increased accountability for decisions would be an effective way to influence risk preferences in social situations (Vieider,
2009, 2011). For example, it has been found that increasing accountability reduces harvesting amounts in a resource dilemma involving uncertainty (de Kwaadsteniet, van Dijk, Wit, De Cremer, & de Rooij, 2007). It was also recently found that
increasing accountability led to reduced levels of loss aversion when decision makers made risky choices for themselves
and a second recipient (Pahlke, Strasser, & Vieider, 2012b). It is important to note that participants in our Experiment 2 were
told that Player B would see how much was deducted from her earnings as a result of Player A’s choices on the Shared Loss
trials. Yet, participants’ choices on Shared Loss trials were still significantly riskier than choices on Standard trials (and did
not differ from the choices made by participants in Experiment 1). The belief that Shared Loss outcomes would be made public to Player B can be seen as outcome accountability, which contrasts with process accountability (Lerner & Tetlock, 1999).
Outcome accountability refers to when decision outcomes are made public, whereas process accountability refers to when
decision processes and reasons have to be explained by a decision maker. It has recently been found that a process accountability manipulation (compared to an outcome accountability manipulation) has a stronger effect on reducing self-serving
decisions when individuals are entrusted to make decisions that affect another’s payoffs (Pitesa & Thau, 2013). As a result,
it would be prudent for future research to explore whether including process accountability affects risk sensitivity under
moral hazard.
5. Conclusions
The current study found that participants make riskier choices when they believe that the negative consequences that
could result from their choices will be shared with a third party. This moral hazard effect was found when participants
had no direct contact with the third party, as well as when they met the third party face-to-face. Importantly, concern for
the losses shared with the third party appeared to exert no influence on choices made by participants under moral hazard.
This lack of concern, though detrimental to the third party, had substantial, positive benefits on participants’ earnings.
7
In the ultimatum game the recipient player can choose to reject the division (in which case both players receive nothing), whereas in the dictator game the
recipient player has no choice and must accept the division.
72
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
References
Abraham, J. M., DeLeire, T., & Royalty, A. B. (2010). Moral hazard matters: Measuring relative rates of underinsurance using threshold measures. Health
Services Research, 45(3), 806–824.
Akerlof, G. A. (1997). Social distance and social decisions. Econometrica, 65(5), 1005–1027.
Anderson, D. R. (1974). The National Flood Insurance Program: Problems and potential. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 41(4), 579–599.
Bagstad, K. J., Stapleton, K., & D’Agostino, J. R. (2007). Taxes, subsidies, and insurance as drivers of United States coastal development. Ecological Economics,
63, 285–298.
Berger, L. A., & Hershey, J. C. (1994). Moral hazard, risk seeking, and free riding. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9, 173–186.
Birkland, T. A., Burby, R. J., Conrad, D., Cortner, H., & Michener, W. K. (2003). River ecology and flood hazard mitigation. Natural Hazards Review, 4(1), 46–54.
Blanchard-Boehm, R. D., Berry, K. A., & Showalter, P. S. (2001). Should flood insurance be mandatory? Insights in the wake of the 1997 New Year’s Day flood
in Reno-Sparks, Nevada. Applied Geography, 21(3), 199–221.
Bohnet, I., & Frey, B. S. (1999). Social distance and other-regarding behavior in dictator games: Comment. The American Economic Review, 89(1), 335–339.
Botzen, W. J. W., & van den Bergh, J. C. J. M. (2008). Insurance against climate change and flooding in the Netherlands: Present, future, and comparison with
other countries. Risk Analysis, 28(2), 413–426.
Brennan, G., González, L. G., Güth, W., & Levati, M. V. (2008). Attitudes toward private and collective risk in individual and strategic choice situations. Journal
of Economic Behavior & Organization, 67, 253–262.
Buchan, N. R., Johnson, E. J., & Croson, R. T. A. (2006). Let’s get personal: An international examination of the influence of communication, culture and social
distance on other regarding preferences. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 60(3), 373–398.
Burby, R. J. (2001). Flood insurance and floodplain management: The US experience. Environmental Hazards, 3, 111–122.
Burby, R. J. (2006). Hurricane Katrina and the paradoxes of government disaster policy: Bringing about wise governmental decisions for hazardous areas.
The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 604, 171–191.
Butler, R. J., & Worrall, J. D. (1991). Claims reporting and risk bearing moral hazard in workers’ compensation. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 58(2),
191–204.
Camerer, C., & Thaler, R. H. (1995). Anomalies: Ultimatums, dictators and manners. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(2), 209–219.
Chakravarty, S., Harrison, G. W., Haruvy, E. E., & Rutström, E. E. (2011). Are you risk averse over other people’s money? Southern Economic Journal, 77(4),
901–913.
Charness, G., & Gneezy, U. (2008). What’s in a name? Anonymity and social distance in dictator and ultimatum games. Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization, 68, 29–35.
Charness, G., Haruvy, E., & Sonsino, D. (2007). Social distance and reciprocity: An Internet experiment. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 63,
88–103.
Charness, G., & Rabin, M. (2002). Understanding social preferences with simple tests. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(3), 817–869.
Cooper, D. J., & Kagel, J. H. (2009). Other-regarding preferences: A selective survey of experimental results. Working paper. Ohio State University.
Crosby, E. U. (1905). Fire prevention. Annals of American Academy of Political and Social Science, 26, 224–238.
Cummins, J. D. (2006). Should the government provide insurance for catastrophes? Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 88(4), 337–379.
Cummins, J. D., & Tennyson, S. (1996). Moral hazard in insurance claiming: Evidence from automobile insurance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 12, 29–50.
Cutter, S. L., & Emrich, C. T. (2006). Moral hazard, social catastrophe: The changing face of vulnerability along the hurricane coasts. The Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Science, 604, 102–112.
de Kwaadsteniet, E. W., van Dijk, E., Wit, A., De Cremer, D., & de Rooij, M. (2007). Justifying decisions in social dilemmas: Justification pressures and tacit
coordination under environmental uncertainty. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 33, 1648–1660.
Deck, C. A., & Reyes, J. (2008). An experimental investigation of moral hazard in costly investments. Southern Economic Journal, 74(3), 725–746.
Di Mauro, C. (2002). Ex ante and ex post moral hazard in compensation for income losses: Results from an experiment. Journal of Socio-Economics, 31,
253–271.
Federal Emergency Management Agency (2012). National Flood Insurance Fund (FY 2013 Congressional Justification). Washington, DC: Federal Emergency
Management Agency.
Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817–868.
Felton, R. S., Ghee, W. K., & Stinton, J. E. (1971). A mid-1970 report on the National Flood Insurance Program. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 38(1), 1–14.
Grossman, R. S. (1992). Deposit insurance, regulation, and moral hazard in the thrift industry: Evidence from the 1930’s. The American Economic Review,
82(4), 800–821.
Grubel, H. G. (1971). Risk, uncertainty and moral hazard. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 38(1), 99–106.
Güth, W., Levati, M. V., & Ploner, M. (2008). On the social dimension of time and risky preferences: An experimental study. Economic Inquiry, 46(2), 261–272.
Güth, W., Levati, M. V., & Ploner, M. (2011). Let me see you! A video experiment on the social dimension of risk preferences. AUCO Czech Economic Review, 5,
211–225.
Handgraaf, M. J. J., Van Dijk, E., & De Cremer, D. (2003). Social utility in ultimatum bargaining. Social Justice Research, 16(3), 263–283.
Hoffman, E., McCabe, K., & Smith, V. L. (1996). Social distance and other-regarding behavior in dictator games. The American Economic Review, 86(3),
653–660.
Holladay, J. S., & Schwartz, J. A. (2010). Flooding the market: The distributional consequences of the NFIP (Policy Brief No. 7). Retrieved from the Institute for
Policy Integrity. <http://policyintegrity.org/documents/FloodingtheMarket.pdf>.
Hooks, L. M., & Robinson, K. J. (2002). Deposit insurance and moral hazard: Evidence from Texas banking in the 1920s. The Journal of Economic History, 62(3),
833–853.
Hsee, C. K., & Weber, E. U. (1997). A fundamental prediction error: Self-others discrepancies in risk preference. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,
126(1), 45–53.
Huber, M. (2004). Insurability and regulatory reform: Is the English flood insurance regime able to adapt to climate change? The Geneva Papers on Risk and
Insurance, 29(2), 169–182.
Humphrey, S. J., & Renner, E. (2011). The social costs of responsibility. CeDEx discussion paper series, No. 2011-02.
Joseph, H. (1972). The measurement of moral hazard. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 39(2), 257–262.
Khan, J., & Rehnberg, C. (2009). Perceived job security and sickness absence: A study on moral hazard. The European Journal of Health Economics, 10, 421–428.
Kunreuther, H., & Slovic, P. (1978). Economics, psychology, and protective behavior. The American Economic Review, 68(2), 64–69.
Lerner, J. S., & Tetlock, P. E. (1999). Accounting for the effects of accountability. Psychological Bulletin, 125(2), 255–275.
McLeman, R., & Smit, B. (2006). Vulnerability to climate change hazards and risks: Crop and flood insurance. The Canadian Geographer, 50(2), 217–226.
Okamoto, K. S. (2009). After the bailout: Regulating systemic moral hazard. UCLA Law Review, 57, 183–236.
Pahlke, J., Strasser, S., & Vieider, F. M. (2012a). Responsibility effects in decision making under risk. Discussion paper, Social Science Research Center Berlin
(WZB), Research area markets and politics, WZB Junior Research Group Risk and Development, No. SP II 2012-402.
Pahlke, J., Strasser, S., & Vieider, F. M. (2012b). Risk-taking for others under accountability. Economics Letters, 114, 102–105.
Pitesa, M., & Thau, S. (2013). Masters of the universe: How power and accountability influence self-serving decisions under moral hazard. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 98(3), 550–558.
Quiggin, J., Karagiannis, G., & Stanton, J. (1993). Crop insurance and crop production: An empirical study of moral hazard and adverse selection. Australian
Journal of Agricultural Economics, 37(2), 95–113.
Rowell, D., & Connelly, L. B. (2012). A history of the term ‘‘moral hazard’’. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 79(4), 1051–1075.
M.T. Bixter, C.C. Luhmann / Journal of Economic Psychology 42 (2014) 63–73
73
Roy, A. (2008). Organization structure and risk taking in banking. Risk Management, 10(2), 122–134.
Sobel, J. (2005). Interdependent preferences and reciprocity. Journal of Economic Literature, 43, 392–436.
Thaler, R. H. (1988). Anomalies: The ultimatum game. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 2(4), 195–206.
Trautmann, S. T., & Vieider, F. M. (2011). Social influences on risk attitudes: Applications in economics. In S. Roeser (Ed.), Handbook of risk theory. Springer.
Vieider, F. M. (2009). The effect of accountability on loss aversion. Acta Psychologica, 132, 96–101.
Vieider, F. M. (2011). Separating real incentives and accountability. Experimental Economics, 14, 507–518.
Wheelock, D. C. (1992). Regulation and bank failures: New evidence from the agricultural collapse of the 1920s. The Journal of Economic History, 52(4),
806–825.
Wheelock, D. C., & Kumbhakar, S. C. (1995). Which banks choose deposit insurance? Evidence of adverse selection and moral hazard in a voluntary
insurance system. Journal of Money, Credit and Banking, 27(1), 186–201.