This article is published in the International Journal of Science

advertisement
This article is published in the International Journal of Science Education, Vol 31 (3), Special
Issue on "Visual and Spatial Modes in Science Learning", February 2009. [copyright Taylor &
Francis]
International Journal of Science Education is available at http://journalsonline.tandf.co.uk/
Visual and spatial modes in science learning 12
Jayashree Ramadas
Homi Bhabha Centre for Science Education, TIFR
The paper surveys some major trends from research on visual and spatial thinking coming from
cognitive science, developmental psychology, science literacy and science studies. It explores the
role of visualisation in creativity, in building mental models and in the communication of scientific
ideas, in order to place these findings in the context of science education research and practice.
Keywords: Visual thinking, transformational reasoning, science learning
Motivation for this review
Visual and spatial thinking is an integral part of doing and learning science. The models or
idealisations of science are simplifications of complex, real-world phenomena, often expressed in
concrete, visual or symbolic modes. Visual imagery and non-verbal, spatial models have been
identified in significant discoveries, while in the communication of ideas in science we not only use
pictures but also narrations of visual experiences. Visual methods continue to be formulated in
pedagogy too, yet a principled and evidence-based basis for these methods is lacking. Although
visual thinking is studied in the psychological laboratory and through documentation of the practice
of science, this phenomenon has remained elusive for educational research generally and for
science education particularly.
Aristotle believed that the faculty of imagination was linked with perception, leading to the
production and recall of mental images. Versions of this idea have, barring a few decades in the
early twentieth century, remained influential in mainstream philosophy and psychology (Thomas,
2003). Experiences reported by prominent scientists and technologists have been supportive of a
strong visual and spatial component in their thinking (Hadamard, 1949; Ferguson, 1977). In
developmental psychology, Piaget carried out systematic studies of visual-spatial thinking and of
children's drawings (Piaget and Inhelder, 1948 and 1966). Yet, till relatively recently, literature in
this area was limited to striking introspective reports, from the psychological laboratory and from
real life, and novel pedagogical approaches based on visualisation and drawings.
In the last thirty-five years the situation changed significantly. New experimental techniques were
developed in psychology and cognitive science which demonstrated that mental imagery was an
1
The original version of this paper is part of epiSTEME-2 reviews, edited by B. Choksi and C. Natarajan and published in 2008 by
Macmillan India Ltd., 2/10, Ansari Road, Daryaganj, New Delhi - 110 002.
2
Visual presentation at epiSTEME-2 held at the Homi Bhabha Centre for Science Education, TIFR, Mumbai, in February 2007 http://www.hbcse.tifr.res.in/ep2visual-presentation.pdf
1
objective, reproducible phenomenon that could be studied empirically (Shepard and Metzler, 1971;
Paivio, 1995), and further, that it had an identifiable neurological basis (Kosslyn and Koenig,
1992). During the same period historians and sociologists of science started to investigate the role
of pictures, diagrams and other non-linguistic representations used by scientists in recording and
communicating their ideas (Shapin and Schaffer, 1985; Lynch, 1985; Gooding et al., 1989).
Philosophers addressed issues raised by visual-spatial and model-based reasoning in science (Giere,
1996; Shank and Cunningham, 1996).
In developmental psychology too there was interest in children's drawings (Goodnow, 1977;
Karmiloff-Smith, 1995) and in spatial reasoning abilities (Newcombe and Learmonth, 2005).
These developmental studies turn out to have direct implication for learning and pedagogy in
school, as they are carried out in more naturalistic contexts than are found in the psychological
laboratory.
School education tends to emphasise verbal and algebraic thinking, at the expense of visual and
spatial modes (Presmeg, 1986; Trumbo, 2006). Visual methods in pedagogy are formulated usually
without reference to cognitive, historical or philosophical considerations. The focus of research in
education has been on pictures rather than on mental imagery, and till recently very little of it has
addressed topics in school science (Levie, 1987; Mathewson, 1999). Moreover the large number
and variety of scientific images in the media have grown, giving rise to a concern that the required
visual literacy is not being developed in the population (Trumbo, 2006). In the last decade the
emergence of powerful computers, with the possibility of handling dynamic models and
simulations, has provided impetus for research on visual thinking in the classroom; one expects that
visualisation will become an active field in the near future (Gilbert, 2008; Mathewson, 1999; 2005).
Visual-spatial and diagrammatic reasoning in science is potentially an interesting and exciting area
of research. But the literature that bears on it originates from the rather specialised and disparate
areas of cognitive science, developmental psychology, science literacy and science studies. An indepth review of these areas would be a daunting task, more so for one who is not an expert in any
of these areas. Coming rather from a background of science education, I review the research
selectively and in rather broad strokes, in order to identify some specific themes that seem to me to
be relevant for the learning of science and for research in science education.
Outline of the review
I begin with the theme of creativity and discovery, going on to the link between imagery and
memory and the role of the visual in the communication of ideas in science. I note with some
surprise that all these three lines of research have highlighted one common yet unexpected idea.
Research on visual thinking, although placed initially in opposition to verbal modes of thinking, has
repeatedly encountered a role for language, text and, in general, analytically expressible meaning.
Language-based forms of reasoning appear to form an inseparable complement to imagery and
diagrammatic reasoning.
It is less surprising, from the viewpoint of science, that model-based reasoning turns out to be a
combination of verbal and visual, as well as symbolic and mathematical modes. For science
2
education then we need to find out how best semantic content can be integrated into visual
representations, in order to bring about meaningful learning.
A particular strength of visual representations, both internal mental ones and external diagrams and
concrete models, is that they are amenable to transformations. I review the evidence for
transformational reasoning in science, linking this research with cognitive analyses of mental
transformations and use of diagrams for transformational reasoning by children and adults. I
identify transformational reasoning as a crucial component in the process of making meaning
through visual representations.
Creativity and discovery in science
In self-reports of significant discoveries by scientists a dominant motif has been that of vivid
imagery and non-verbal, often spatial models. Paradoxically Francis Galton (1880) found that
while people in general society habitually reported instances of mental imagery, the scientists who
he spoke with tended to deny any such experience, questioning the very notion of mental imagery.
I will re-visit this anomalous observation in "transformational reasoning in science."
Jacques Hadamard (1949) questioned some well-known creative intellectuals of his time. He found
that almost all of them claimed to think in vague mental images that were most frequently visual,
but also sometimes kinetic and auditory. Visual-spatial conceptualisations in the radical
breakthroughs of twentieth century physics were analysed by Miller (1984) and Holton (1986a,
1995). In biology Kierns (1999) documented how visual evidence was critical to the highly
original research of Barbara McClintock. Technological designs and visualisations of mechanical
inventions over the years were studied by Ferguson (1977).
Though these studies are carefully documented as well as inspiring and persuasive, it is difficult to
confirm any general claims based on them regarding imagery, creativity and discovery. Restricting
ourselves to the context of science, it is not clear whether observations made with exceptional
individuals have strong implications for all scientists or for students of science. Another problem is
to arrive at good definitions of creativity and discovery in given contexts, let alone ones that might
hold across a range of contexts.
Roger Shepard, a pioneer in the scientific study of imagery, stepped out of the strict experimental
tradition of psychology to consider several documented cases of highly creative scientists,
technologists, mathematicians, writers, sculptors and others who reported using mental imagery.
Shepard (1978, 1988) suggested that imagery and spatial visualisation were essential for creativity
and discovery. He also conjectured some reasons to account for the apparent effectiveness of
imagery over language in the creative process.
Subsequent research provided indirect support to only some of Shepard's conjectures. A necessary
relationship between creativity and imagery has never been found. On the contrary most
standardised tests are explicitly designed to tap both visual and verbal creativity. But mental
imagery in simple situations has been shown to result in creative responses. In a series of
experiments Finke and his collaborators found that subjects could successfully combine and
3
mentally manipulate familiar shapes of letters, numerals and geometrical objects, to discover new
forms previously determined by the experimenters. The majority of subjects were able to mentally
synthesise such simple, familiar forms in creative ways, into meaningful patterns and entirely new
objects, or "preinventive forms" (Finke, 1990).
In other experiments, an expected developmental precedence of imagery over language was
supported by observations (Roskos-Ewoldsen et al., 1993; Newcombe and Learmonth, 2005).
Finally, a "drive towards symmetry", which is said to have motivated many of the scientists in
Shepard's accounts, found a parallel in the imagery responses of laboratory subjects: for example,
symmetrical patterns used in experiments were found to cohere easily in the mind and to require
less time for processing (Roskos-Ewoldsen et al., 1993).
What is perhaps not supported yet is Shepard's claim that, in creativity, imagery has some special
status over language. One clear result from psychological studies is that mental "images" are not
purely visual in character; rather they have both depictive and descriptive qualities (IntonsPeterson, 1993), and also abstract elements which are not easily expressible in either of these ways
(de Vega et al., 1996). Language and description may either facilitate or interfere with
interpretation of visual images (Intons-Peterson, 1993). Further, creativity and discovery in the
psychological lab is helped, not by imagery alone, but by the ability to transform information
between the verbal and imaginal. Along with mental manipulation of images, activities like
doodling or drawing, seeing, hearing and gesturing, when carried out in consonance with the task at
hand, enable more creative responses (Roskos-Ewoldsen et al., 1993).
These studies show that, given appropriate task situations, creative responses can be easily elicited
from ordinary lay persons. Later we see how historical sources and observations of practising
scientists give some insight into the phenomenon of creativity in science. How are these, the lay
and expert, kinds of creativity comparable? We leave aside, for the purpose of this discussion, the
very different social contexts of the scientific activities. But creative visualisations of scientists are
clearly built upon a deep and extensive knowledge of their field. Further, persons who demonstrate
exceptional creativity in particular domains might be marked more by their commitment to explore
in depth the possibilities suggested by their creations. This is a larger and more extended task,
spread over months and years, that must require much more than visual-mental manipulation over
milliseconds to minutes, that is tested in the laboratory. This "ninety-nine percent perspiration"
aspect of science has direct implications for pedagogy.
From mental images to mental models
The results on creativity show that apparently simple and de-contextualised mental images carry
meaning that is not entirely captured by their visual and spatial properties (de Vega and Marschark,
1996; de Vega et al., 1996). The meaning inherent in images may be at least partly expressible in
language and other abstract, symbolic notations. Sensory modalities besides the visual may also
contribute to these models. Current theories in cognitive science support such multimodal
representations of knowledge (Ramachandran and Hubbard, 2001; Barsalou et al., 2003).
4
What is found true for the kind of simple depictions employed in psychological research (for
example, the well-studied duck-rabbit figure), should be even more valid for the much richer
images in science. Images in science are not simple perceptual entities. Not just the sophisticated
images of high-level science, but the images occuring in school science too, carry a great deal of
conceptual, abstract and often mathematical content. Quite unlike images in art, and much less so
than images in design and technology, the images in science rarely stand on their own. They need
to be supported always by text and other formalisms.
There is limited literature on the understanding of images in semantically rich domains as in
science. A broad conceptualisation by Holton (1986b) proposes three closely related forms of
imagination in science: visual, metaphoric and thematic. Holton's ideas have found reflection in
science education and curriculum theory, though their effect on practice remains to be seen
(Matthewson, 1999; 2005). In the more operational terms required for empirical research, specific
problem-solving situations in complex domains might call for a combination of propositional
knowledge, abstract rules, manipulation of images and mathematical analysis.
In this view a mental image is more like a mental model, not quite a picture in the mind but a
scheme for depicting and processing visual, spatial, temporal, causal, or other types of information.
Though mental models in principle need not be bound to specific sensory modalities, yet it is
conceivable that mental models of blind persons have significant auditory, tactile and kinesthetic
components (Gouzman and Kozulin, 1998) while those of sighted persons may have a dominant
visual one.
Visual mental models do figure prominently in cases of conceptual change across the sciences
(Nersessian, 2002). Though in the creative process there may be no exclusivity to imagery, it is
possible that visual and spatial modes facilitate certain operations on mental models. Reasoning
with mental models could be described by the umberella term "transformational reasoning", a
characterisation that may help integrate visual-spatial with verbal and other modes of reasoning.
After reviewing the literature on transformational reasoning I suggest that model-based
transformational reasoning is the key to studying the visual and spatial aspects of science learning.
Imagery and memory
The unexpected relationship between verbal and visual thinking found in imaginal creativity and
discovery, seems quite natural when we look at the role of imagery in memory. From antiquity till
today visual imagery has remained popular as a mnemonic for verbal material (Anderson, 1998).
Till recently psychological research on memory dealt largely with words and text. Consideration of
visual material led to a new conceptualisation of long-term memory (Paivio, 1995) and also
working memory (Baddeley, 1992). Working memory, which is involved in temporary storage and
processing of information, consists of two complementary subsystems dealing with visual-spatial
and verbal information respectively (Baddely, 1992). The classic experiments on imagery (Shepard
and Metzler, 1971; Kosslyn and Koenig, 1992) address visual aspects of working memory.
Individual differences in imagery tasks are often attributed to limitations of working memory
(Hegarty, 2000). Mental models are thought to be constructed through the interaction of the visual
and verbal systems in working memory (Schnotz, 2002).
5
Long-term memory is classified into declarative and procedural memory; the former is further
found to comprise of episodic and semantic memory. Visual components in long-term memory are
indicated in a study by Kosslyn and Bower (1974), showing that children rely on visual imagery to
remember sentences unlike adults who encode sentences more in terms of their meaning. Memory
for language materials is found to be dependent on the image-evoking value of words, imagery
instructions and imagery strategies (Clark and Paivio, 1991; Paivio, 1995). Consistent with the
close interaction between the visual and verbal, mental images are possible to reconstruct based on
descriptive information stored in long-term memory (Hyman, 1993).
The research of Paivio and others indicates that imagery may have a role in episodic as well as in
semantic memory, in both of which linguistic and imaginal aspects are closely intertwined.
Examples from school science too could be recalled. The colours and smells from the chemistry
laboratory, a diagram of the digestive system, a schematic ray of light refracted through a crosssection of a slab of glass: these images persist in the memory of adults well past their school years.
Laboratory sequences or steps in problem-solving involve remembering of procedures. Research
with designers (e.g. Tversky, 2005), shows that imagery may be a component of procedural
memory too. Such studies remain to be done in the context of science.
Communication of ideas
The integration between the verbal and the visual needs no justification when we come to the
communication of ideas in science. Studies of the practice of science (Butterfield, 1949; Taylor
and Blum, 1991; Baigrie, 1996) look at the evolution of scientific illustrations and their role in the
creation of scientific knowledge. Phenomena in science are made visible through imagery and
drawings. Laboratory scientists in particular make extensive use of diagrammatic devices which
further play a key role in scientific argumentation (Lynch, 1985). In the sociology of science even
a textual experimental report has been seen as the narration of prior visual experiences - it points to
sensory experiences that lie behind the text, and it in turn constitutes a secondary visual source
(Shapin and Schaffer, 1985).
Ferguson (1977) and others have attributed the growth and spread of Western technology to the
invention of printing, which allowed finely detailed technical drawings to be reproduced and
distributed in large numbers. Large-scale printing made illustrated books available to the general
population and new discursive and representational styles evolved (Olson, 1994). In science these
"literate" linguistic and depictive devices allowed for clarity in reporting of research, enabling
separation of the experimental apparatus and conditions from the results, making possible the
replication of experiments to produce the accepted facts of science. Ability to make copies of text
and diagrams also led to standardisation of equipment which led to further accumulation of results.
Thus visual formulation and communication of content contributed significantly to the process of
development of science (Shapin and Shaffer, 1985; Subramaniam, 1999).
Research in developmental psychology, inspired by Vygotsky's theory of cognition mediated by the
social context of the learner, has focused on the relation between visualisation and communication.
Vygotsky emphasises the role of cultural, social and historical artifacts: thus visual images, graphic
6
symbols and models, plans and maps are instrumental in mediating cognition (Vygotsky, 1978).
This approach has been used to study science learning in a classroom as it can happen via
communication though drawing, speech, writing and model-making (Brooks, 2002). Studies of
collaborative learning in adults too have shown how visual information can be shared through
drawings and gestures, leading to efficient solution of problems (Heiser et al., 2004). Collaborative
learning with diagrams and other shared devices is described by Brooks in this issue. For
elucidating students' models in science however, we need to focus on the reasoning process, which
we do in the following sections.
Transformational reasoning in science
Mental manipulations and transformations of images are a recurrent theme in the reports of imagery
by scientists. Psychological research indicates that visual-spatial images are easily susceptible to
transformations: in the mind, or externally via concrete models, or on paper. Further, images can
hold powerful metaphorical connotations which suggest relations and concepts extending beyond
their concrete physical form (Arnheim, 1969; Tversky, 2005). Perhaps, beginning with perceptual
images, it may be possible to work up to abstract theoretical concepts and frameworks. This is not
to propose an empiricist view in which knowledge is derived from sense experience, but rather to
emphasise the theory-ladenness of the images themselves (eg. Topper, 1996) which makes them
amenable to model-based transformations.
Historical studies lend credence to this notion. Biology began with visual images recorded as
drawings by herbalists, naturalists and explorers. Over time the depictions of individual specimens
were transformed into idealised representations of types, ideals or species (Topper, 1996).
Generalisations then drawn from these visual images were codified and elaborated in the form of
taxonomy. These judgements of morphological similarity and differences must also have required
an intuitive kind of transformational reasoning. Such reasoning became more explicit in the work
of Georges Cuvier (1769-1832), a pioneer in comparative anatomy. Later, in 1917, D'Arcy
Thompson developed a theory of transformation in which he viewed morphology, growth and
evolution in terms of mathematical transformations involving the whole organism (Thompson,
1961). To take an example from geology, the study of landform structures involves transformation
of observational data via imaginal structural models into parameters that could be fitted into a
mathematical or computer model.
A remarkably similar transformation from observational drawings to idealised diagrams is seen in
Faraday's rendering of lines of force (Gooding, 1989) leading up to Maxwell's equations of
electromagnetism. For Faraday and Maxwell images were heuristic devices guiding their
discoveries (Wise, 1979; Nersessian, 1995). Faraday's diagrammatic representations, deriving
directly from experiment, corresponded to a concrete physical conception of lines of force.
Maxwell, who built on Faraday's work, developed diagrammatic representations that were more
abstract, serving to visualise the relationships between fields rather than the fields themselves.
Maxwell's visualisations led more explicitly to his mathematical formulations (Nersessian, 1995).
Transformational reasoning, in the sense indicated by these examples, goes well beyond mental
manipulations of simple figures. It is a challenge to characterise such reasoning in reasonably clear
terms and to find ways of studying it.
7
Contemporary physics, chemistry, physiology, molecular biology, pharmacology, geology and
metereology, offer numerous examples of problems that are formulated visually and solved through
visual-spatial transformations. These transformational techniques, through continuous usage, get
codified into systems of symbols that can be manipulated using a set of rules. Once the problems
have been formulated visually, analytical tools can take over and independently lead to further
progress without reference to the original visualisations.
For instance, after Maxwell formulated his mathematical relationships his visual models became
redundant (Nersessian, 1995). Today scientists routinely use Maxwell's equations without needing
to recreate his visualisations. Similarly Feynmann diagrams, created by an exceptionally visual
physicist, are now a standard calculation tool of quantum field theory. Stepping back to the
nineteenth century, it is perhaps significant that Galton's (1880) observations, cited in the section on
"creativity and discovery", were made at a time when the physical sciences appeared to have
reached a culmination in their development. Classical physics had been established on firm
theoretical and mathematical basis and further new discoveries seemed unlikely. This notion was
soon to be overturned, and we find that in the new mathematics and physics of the early 20th
Century there was a resurgence of interest in mental imagery (Hadamard, 1949; Miller, 1984).
Cognitive analyses of transformational reasoning
Piaget and Inhelder (1966) were perhaps the first to study mental visual transformations carried out
by children. They proposed that early childhood imagery is "reproductive" in nature; the
development from reproductive mental imagery to transformational reasoning with images
becomes possible with the emergence of mental operations. This theoretical stance was however
tempered by their observation that there are large individual differences in such transformational
reasoning in the adult population. Piaget and Inhelder's suggestions were, to identify such
typologies early and study them longitudinally, and to study people with extraordinary visual
achievements, for example earth scientists, and also those with psychopathological disruptions of
visual imagery as in hallucinations (Piaget and Inhelder, 1966).
Tests of spatial ability call for simple imaginal transformations like mental rotation, reflection,
cutting, folding and perspective-change (Sorby, this issue). In a survey of individual differences in
spatial ability Hegarty and Waller (2005) looked at factor-analytic studies of psychometric data. In
a result reminescent of Piaget's classification of imagery, at least two distinct cognitive processes
were found to underlie performance on tests of spatial ability: one corresponding to the
construction of an image and the other to its transformation in memory. In simple tasks involving
construction of a mental image, individual differences are observed only when a speed limit is
placed on the task. If enough time is provided for complex tasks then individual differences are
seen in the complexity of transformations that a person is capable of carrying out in memory.
There is evidence that spatial ability assessed through such relatively content-free tasks is
correlated with success in mechanical occupations, mathematics, physics and medical professions
(references cited in Hegarty and Waller, 2005; Tversky, 2005).
8
A distinction between visual and spatial is seen in neuropsychological studies. Visual processing in
the brain is found to involve a ventral pathway leading to the inferior temporal cortex, which
processes object features, and a dorsal pathway leading to the parietal cortex, which processes
information on spatial location and relationships (Kosslyn and Koenig, 1992).
The research of Shepard and of Kosslyn concerned mental rotations, mental scanning and zooming,
in which mental transformations were found to be linked to perceptual processes. Studies of more
complex visuospatial reasoning indicate that the order of performing the transformations may be
tied to motor processes, like the act of drawing or constructing a figure (Tversky, 2005) or the order
of actions involved in carrying out a physical process (Schwartz and Black, 1996; Hegarty, 2004a).
Mental representations of simple mechanical systems (pulleys and gears) are thought to encode, not
the visually observed motion of components of the system, but rather the causally understood chain
of events. Under different conditions students use either mental imagery or abstract causal rules to
solve problems related to such systems (Schwartz and Black, 1996; Hegarty, 2004a).
Shepard and Metzler's (1971) classic experiments showed that people rely on mental rotation for
comparison of generic three-dimensional objects. But when structurally similar objects rich in
information are used, such as molecules in stereochemistry, students are likely to apply rules
involving planes of symmetry. Only when they are forced to treat the molecules as generic objects,
do students resort to visualisation and mental rotation strategies (Stieff et al., 2005). Thus in
moderately complex contexts, transformations on internal or external representations may require
not only a perceptual and a motor basis, but also a conceptual basis.
The research described above uses drawings, which are considered as external representations that
facilitate operations on internal mental representations. Ways of analysing the conceptual basis of
such images, and further developing a pedagogy for them, are indicated by research specifically on
drawings and diagrams, which we consider next.
Transformational reasoning through drawings
Consider first the case of children's drawings. We observe that children's early drawings have both
expressive and depictive functions. The expressive aspects of their drawings are likely to have
significant bearing on our understanding of visual thought as a tool for creativity and the
conception of ideas. Yet these aspects have been relatively less encouraged in school; expressive
drawings have been studied mostly in contexts like the psychology of art, emotional development,
psychoanalysis and therapeutic use for trauma victims. The use of expressive drawings in more
"cognitive" tasks remains to be explored.
By necessity then we restrict the discussion to the case of depictive drawings and ask, what is the
relationship between children's external depictions and their mental representations? A common
and long-standing observation from children's drawings over the years has been an apparent
transition, from a schematic stage, when children draw "what they know", to a stage of visual
realism, when they start drawing "what they see" (Wales, 1990; Carvalho et al., 2004). In reality, a
host of other factors affect children's depictions, from physical constraints to cultural symbolism to
individual styles to value judgements (Wales, 1990, Goodnow, 1990). As for diagrams in science,
9
which carry significant conceptual content, it seems that another transition might be needed, from
"what one sees" to "what one knows (or has learnt)". We mentioned parallels in the history of
science with instances of exact depictions giving way to idealised, theory-laden ones (Gooding,
1989; Topper, 1996). Such studies are yet to be done in science learning. Another conclusion from
the developmental studies is that external depictions are not related in a staightforward way to
internal mental representations. We will return to this point.
A fruitful line of research in developmental psychology has adopted, not a "declarative", but a
"procedural" view of drawings. A child's first drawing is regarded, not as a simple "printout" of a
perceptual input but as a conceptual schemata constructed through activity, reflection and the
influence of culture (Olson, 1970). Thus the drawing does not so much indicate what the child sees
or even knows. Rather it shows how (s)he goes about solving a problem and developing a set of
conventions, strategies and organising principles that work for the task (Freeman, 1975; Goodnow,
1977). Drawing skills are represented, at a procedural level, as a sequence of steps (Goodnow,
1977; Karmiloff-Smith, 1995). Though significant changes in these procedures may be initiated
through encounter with novel problem situations, developmental change is believed to be a largely
internal, endogenously driven process (Karmiloff-Smith, 1995).
From the perspective of science learning one is interested in changes that occur due to exposure to
new concepts and materials. Research on scientific diagrams too, like the developmental research
cited above, supports a procedural view of drawing. Diagrams aid thinking and problem-solving by
exploiting certain capabilities of the visual system: like detecting spatial and geometrical relations,
efficiently encoding such information and going beyond it to form generalisations (Larkin and
Simon, 1987; Pylyshyn, 2003). We thus begin to see how diagrams support transformational
reasoning.
Diagrams facilitate mental operations by using space to convey abstract concepts, in that process
placing conceptually related information in spatial contiguity (Tversky, 2001). Apart from their
external referential meaning which may have to do with a complex reality, diagrams have their own
internal meaning. Reasoning with diagrams tends to be focused on the inscription, i.e. the internal
meaning, rather than on the external referential meaning (Döerfler, 2004). The rules for
transformation that might have applied in the complex situation thus get traded for simpler rules
that apply to the diagram. Efficient and successful diagrammatic reasoning needs extensive
experience with manipulating diagrams (Döerfler, 2004).
How experts use transformations
In the use of diagrams in complex knowledge domains there are clear differences between novices
and experts. Experts' internal representations encode a fair amount of subject knowledge, while
novices may encode mostly surface features of external representations (Hegarty, 2004b; Trumbo,
2006). Studies of practising scientists using external visualisations (Trafton et al., 2005; Trickett
and Trafton, 2006) show that spatial transformations are the key to connecting external with
internal representations. In analysing photographic and diagrammatic data as well as in
interpretation of graphical displays, the scientists (astronomers, physicists and metereologists) in
these studies frequently compared several (external) images on the computer screen with each
10
other, and also with their own internal representations, mentally transforming them so as to bring
about a match between the internal and external representations.
In another instance of transformational reasoning, experts did well in using diagrams to restructure
a problem situation. In a study of figure combination and restructuring it was found that while
mental imagery facilitates combination of given objects, radical restructuring happens only with the
help of a sketch. Experts in design and engineering are particularly good at solving problems in
this way (Verstijnen et al., 1998; Subramaniam and Padalkar, this issue).
The transformational reasoning afforded by diagrams results in a facilitation of the imaged mental
process. The most compelling arguments to support this "external-internal facilitation" view come
from use of drawings in design (Tversky, 1999). In design, the conceptual content lies almost
entirely in the drawings: the design is created as a drawing and is also communicated as a drawing.
In science the conceptual content may reside in a combination of text, drawings or diagrams and
other symbolic devices; thus more specialised rules of transformation would apply which might be
characteristic of the domain.
The conceptual component of mental models may derive from a combination of their visuo-spatial,
auditory, haptic and motor properties. Spatial cognition in childhood develops through an
interaction between tactile, visual and motor learning (Diamond, 1991; Newcombe and Learmonth,
2005). Later in adulthood, for professions that call for fine or large motor co-ordination, like
mechanical assembly, surgery, sculpture and gymnastics, the training consists largely of visual and
aural inputs. These may involve observing and listening to a master teacher, or analysing diagrams.
Thus in specific situations adults may continue to develop mental models with properties that are
visual as well as haptic and auditory, possibly also including other modalities (Barsalou et al.,
2003).
Transformational reasoning in the learning of science
The powerful concept of transformational reasoning helps integrate the visual-spatial with the
semantic component of mental models. Going beyond the classic and purely visual-spatial sense of
mental rotations and other manipulations of objects, we have considered transformations of
complex mental representations and of their schematic and symbolic externalisations in the form of
diagrams and other notations.
Transformational reasoning has perhaps been more studied in mathematics education, and more
recently, in design and technology, than in science education. Central to this notion is the ability to
envision, not a static state, but a dynamic process by which a new state or a continuum of states are
generated (Simon, 1996). In mathematics (Simon, 1996; Douek, 1998) the objects and the
operations on them can be defined with some clarity while in science this is more difficult to do.
Nonetheless the heuristics of operations in science may bear similarities with that in mathematics
and engineering. Douek (1998) for example points out a close relationship between metaphors and
transformational reasoning, considering metaphors as particular outcomes of transformational
reasoning. This kind of reasoning is more intuitive than inductive or deductive, appearing to
11
involve a series of leaps into the unknown. Some authors consider it to be a case of abduction
(Douek, 1998; Shank and Cunningham, 1996; Magnani, 2001).
A classic sequence in inquiry-based science first introduces a natural phenomenon and then goes
through a cycle of observation, description, prediction and explanation. Transformational
reasoning is essential to this cycle. For example, problem-solving in optics requires conversion of
real or imagined situations into schematic diagrams. In study of 13-14 year old students'
conceptions in optics, Ramadas and Driver (1989) found that diagrams as opposed to verbal
descriptions enabled students to work within an abstracted context consisting of light sources, rays
and geometrical projections. This conversion into diagrams allowed for the introduction of
conceptual elements into a perceptual description of the situations.
The data in this study was analysed by Ramadas and Shayer (1993) in terms of the descriptiveexplanatory dimension in students' responses. Scores along this dimension were dependent on the
demands of the problem and also on the mode of its presentation. Presenting the problem in the
form of a diagram rather than as pure text led to more responses of the explanatory type.
Interestingly the opportunity to set up the situation in the laboratory did not afford additional help.
We saw that developmental change in children's drawings comes about through the invention or
discovery of new procedures. In the context of science learning such development is likely to be
driven by classroom experience and conceptual change. In a study of 3rd-5th graders' drawings of
motion Ramadas (1990) found that younger children spontaneously used rich contextual, though
non-causal, cues to depict motion. Older children tended to use more causal cues and pictorial
conventions inspired by animations. The choice between contextual cues and pictorial conventions
in older students seemed driven by the type of problem situation: by posing a more demanding task
of depicting velocity, the choice was tilted in favour of pictorial conventions and, within these,
there was a preference for abstract symbolic rather than simple photographic conventions. Here we
see an interaction between age / experience and task demand, and evidence that changes in
procedure could be brought about exogeneously through learning experience on the task.
In the now standard terminology of conceptual change (Posner et al., 1982) I have argued that the
notion of transformational reasoning may be "intelligible" and "plausible", at an intuitive level. Is
it a "fruitful" concept for science education research and practice? Mathai and Ramadas (this issue)
use transformations to define visualisation of human body systems. In elementary astronomy,
earth-based perceptual data need to be reconciled with the learnt model of the solar system, for
which diagrams can help (Subramaniam and Padalkar, this issue). Our pedagogy for the round
earth has used tools found to be effective in developing spatial reasoning: 3-d models and
manipulative tasks, body gestures and schematic diagrams. In this case body gestures serve to
simulate a dynamic situation and to facilitate transformation between a situation or model and a
diagram (Padalkar and Ramadas, 2008).
Visual and spatial studies in science education have to map a space between the content-lean
research of cognitive psychology and the rich conceptual domains traversed by historical and
sociological studies of science. Inquiry learning approaches in particular are yet to solve the
problem of inductive generalisations from first-hand experience. Language-based methods offer a
way, but they must be supported by visual and spatial modes. We need studies of children learning
12
science to examine the mediating role played by 3-d models, diagrams, gestures and other visualspatial modes.
References
Anderson, R. E. (1998). Imagery and spatial representation. In W. Bechtel and G. Graham (Eds.) A
companion to cognitive science (pp. 204-11). Blackwell Companions to Philosophy. Malden, MA,
USA and Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing.
Arnheim, R. (1969). Visual thinking. Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Baddeley, A. (1992). Working memory. Science, 255, 556-9.
Baigrie, B. S. (1996). Picturing knowledge: Historical and philosophical problems concerning the
use of art in science (Toronto Studies in Philosophy), Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Barsalou, L. W., Simmons, W. K., Barbey, A. K. and Wilson, C. D. (2003). Grounding conceptual
knowledge in modality-specific systems. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7 (2), 84-91.
Brooks, M. (2002). Drawing to learn, PhD. Thesis. University of New England, Australia.
Retrieved on 29 Oct 2003 from http://www.une.edu.au/Drawing/main.html.
Butterfield, H. (1949). The origins of modern science, 1300-1800, London: G. Bell and Sons. As
cited in Baldasso, R. (2006). The role of visual representation in the scientific revolution: A
historiographic inquiry. Centaurus, 48, 69-88.
Carvalho, G. S., Silva, R., Lima, N. and Coquet, E. (2004). Portuguese primary school children's
conceptions about digestion: identification of learning obstacles. International Journal of Science
Education, 26 (9), 1111-1130.
Clark, J. M. & Paivio, A. (1991). Dual coding theory and education. Educational Psychology
Review, 3 (3), 149-170.
de Vega, M. and Marschark, M. (1996). Visuospatial cognition: An historical and theoretical
introduction. In M. de Vega, M. J. Intons-Peterson, P. N. Johnson-Laird, M. Denis and M.
Marschark (Eds.), Models of visuospatial cognition (pp. 3-19). New York: Oxford University
Press.
de Vega, M., Marschark, M., Intons-Peterson, M. J., Johnson-Laird, P. N. and Denis, M. (1996).
Representation of visuospatial cognition: A discussion. In M. de Vega, M. J. Intons-Peterson, P. N.
Johnson-Laird, M. Denis and M. Marschark (Eds.), Models of visuospatial cognition (pp. 198-226).
New York: Oxford University Press.
Diamond, A. (1991). Neuropsychological insights into the meaning of object concept development.
In S. Carey and S. Gelman (Eds.), The epigenesis of mind: Essays on biology and cognition. New
Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.
Döerfler, W. (2004). Mathematical reasoning and observing transformations of diagrams. In C.
Bergsten and B. Grevholm (Eds.), Mathematics and language (Skrifter fraan SMDF no. 3, pp. 719). Proceedings, Swedish Society for Research in Mathematics Education, Malmoe, Sweden.
Douek N. (1998). Some remarks about argumentation and mathematical proof and their educational
implications. First CERME international conference. Retrieved on 4 Oct 2006 from
http://www.lettredelapreuve.it/Resumes/Douek/Douek98.html.
Ferguson, E. S. (1977). The mind's eye: Nonverbal thought in technology. Science, 197 (4306) 827836.
Finke, R. (1990). Creative imagery: Discoveries and inventions in visualization. Hillsdale, N. J.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
13
Freeman, N. H. (1975). Do children draw men with arms coming out of the head? Nature, 254,
416-417.
Galton, F. (1880). Statistics of mental imagery. Mind, 5, 301-318. Source: Classics in the history of
psychology - http://psychclassics.yourku.ca/Galton/imagery.htm.
Giere, R. (1996). Visual models and scientific judgement. In B. S. Baigrie (Ed.), Picturing
knowledge (pp. 269-302). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Gilbert, J. (2008). Visualization: An emergent interdisciplinary field of practice and enquiry in
science education. In J. Gilbert, M. Reiner and M. Nakhleh (Eds.). Visualization: Theory and
practice in science education (pp. 3-24). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.
Gooding, D. (1989). 'Magnetic curves' and the magnetic field: experimentation and representation
in the history of a theory. In Gooding, D., Pinch, T. and Schaffer, S. (Eds.) The uses of experiment:
Studies in the natural science (pp. 183-224). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Gooding, D., Pinch, T. and Schaffer, S. (Eds.) (1989). The uses of experiment: Studies in the
natural science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Goodnow, J. (1977). Children's drawing. London: Fontana / Open Books.
Goodnow, J. (1990). The socialization of cognition: What's involved? In J. W. Stigler, R. A.
Shweder and G. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural psychology (pp. 259-286). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Gouzman, R. and Kozulin, A. (1998). Enhancing cognitive skills in blind learners. Paper presented
at the Annual Conference of the British Psychological Association (Educational Section). Retrieved
on 7 Sep 2008 from http://www.icevi.org/publications/educator/winter_00/article2.htm.
Hadamard, J. (1949). An essay on the psychology of invention in the mathematical field. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hegarty, M. (2000). Capacity limits in diagrammatic reasoning. In M. Anderson, P. Cheng & V.
Harslev (Eds.) Theory and application of diagrams (Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 1889),
pp. 194-206. Berlin: Springer.
Hegarty (2004a). Mechanical reasoning by mental simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8 (6),
280-5.
Hegarty, M. (2004b). Diagrams in the mind and in the world: Relations between internal and
external visualizations. In A. Blackwell et al. (Eds.) Diagrams 2004 Conference Proceedings. LNAI
2980 (pp. 1-13). Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.
Hegarty, M. and Waller, D. A. (2005). Individual differences in spatial abilities. In P. Shah and A.
Miyake (Eds.). The Cambridge handbook of visuospatial reasoning (pp. 121-169). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Heiser, J., Tversky, B. and Silverman, M. (2004). Sketches for and from collaboration. In J. S.
Gero, B. Tversky and T. Knight (Eds.). Visual and spatial reasoning in design III (pp. 69-78).
Sydney: Key Centre for Design Research.
Holton, G. J. (1986a). Thematic presuppositions and the direction of scientific advance. In The
advancement of science, and its burdens (pp. 3-27). Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
Holton, G. J. (1986b). Metaphors in science and education. In The advancement of science, and its
burdens (pp. 229-252). Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
Holton, G. J. (1995). Imagination in science. In Einstein, history and other passions (pp. 160-184).
Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Hyman, I. E. (1993). Imagery, reconstructive memory and discovery. In B. Roskos-Ewoldsen, M. J.
Intons-Peterson and R. E. Anderson (Eds.), Imagery, creativity, and discovery: A cognitive
perspective (Advances in Psychology, Vol.98, pp. 99-121). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
14
Intons-Peterson, M. J. (1993). Imagery's role in creativity and discovery. In B. Roskos-Ewoldsen,
M. J. Intons-Peterson and R. E. Anderson (Eds.), Imagery, creativity, and discovery: A cognitive
perspective (pp. 1-37). Advances in Psychology, Vol.98, Eds. G. E. Stelmach and and P. A. Vroon.
Amsterdam: North Holland (Elsevier Science Publishers B. V.).
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1995). The Child as a notator. In Beyond modularity: A developmental
perspective on cognitive science (Chapter 6). Massachusetts: Bradford Books, MIT Press.
Kierns, C. (1999). Seeing patterns: visual evidence and pictorial communication in the work of
Barbara McClintock. Journal of the History of Biology, 32, 163-196.
Kosslyn, S. M. and Bower, G. H. (1974). The role of imagery in sentence memory: a
developmental study. Child Development, 45, 30-38.
Kosslyn, S. M. and Koenig, O. (1992). Wet mind: The new cognitive neuroscience. New York: Free
Press.
Larkin, J. H., & Simon, H. A. (1987). Why a diagram is (sometimes) worth ten thousand words.
Cognitive Science, 11, 65-99.
Levie, W. H. (1987). Research on pictures: A guide to the literature. In D. M. Willows and H. A.
Houghton (Eds.), The psychology of illustration: Basic research (Vol. 1, pp. 1-50). New York:
Springer Verlag.
Lynch, M. (1985). Art and artifact in laboratory science. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason and science. New York: Plenum Publishers.
Mathai, S. and Ramadas, J. (this issue). Visuals and visualisation of human body systems.
International Journal of Science Education.
Mathewson, J. H. (1999). Visual-spatial thinking: An aspect of science overlooked by educators.
Science Education, 83 (1), 33-54.
Mathewson, J. H. (2005). The visual core of science: definition and applications to education.
International Journal of Science Education, 27 (5), 529-548.
Miller, A. I. (1984). Imagery in scientific thought: Creating 20th-Century physics. Boston:
Birkh äuser.
Nersessian, N. J. (1995). How do scientists think? Capturing the dynamics of conceptual change in
science. In R. N. Giere (Ed.), Cognitive models of science (pp. 3-45). Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
Nersessian, N. J. (2002). The cognitive basis of model-based reasoning in science. In P. Carruthers,
S. Stich and M. Siegal (Eds.) The cognitive basis of science (pp. 133-153). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Newcombe, N. and Learmonth, A. (2005). Development of spatial competence. In P. Shah and A.
Miyake (Eds.), Handbook of visuospatial reasoning (pp. 213-256). New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Olson, D. R. (1970). Cognitive development: The child's acquisition of diagonality. New York and
London: Academic Press.
Olson, D. R. (1994). The world on paper. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Padalkar, S. and Ramadas, J. (2008). Modeling the round earth through diagrams. Astronomy
Education Review, 6 (2), 54-74.
HTML: http://aer.noao.edu/cgi-bin/article.pl?id=254
PDF: http://aer.noao.edu/figures/v06i02/06-02-01-04.pdf
Paivio A. (1995). Imagery and memory. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.) The cognitive neurosciences (pp.
977-986). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
15
Piaget, J. and Inhelder, B. (1948). The child's conception of space. In H. E. Gruber and J. J.
Von èche (Eds.) The essential Piaget, New York: Basic Books (1977). Part VII, 576-642.
Piaget, J. and Inhelder, B. (1966). Mental imagery in the child. In H. E. Gruber and J. J. Von èche
(Eds.) The essential Piaget, New York: Basic Books (1977). Part VIII, 643-684.
Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A., Hewson, P. W., & Gertzog, W. A. (1982). Accommodation of a
scientific conception: Toward a theory of conceptual change. Science Education, 66 (2), 211-27.
Presmeg, N. C. (1986). Visualisation and mathematical giftedness. Educational Studies in
Mathematics, 17, 297-311.
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2003). Seeing with the mind's eye Part 3 - Visual thinking. In Seeing and
visualizing: It's not what you think (pp. 427-74). Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press.
Ramachandran, V. S. & Hubbard, E. M. (2001). Synaesthesia: a window into perception, thought
and language, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8 (12), 3-34.
Ramadas, J. and Driver, R. (1989). Aspects of secondary students' ideas about light. Leeds: Centre
for Studies in Science and Maths Education, University of Leeds.
Ramadas, J. (1990). Motion in children's drawings, In I. Harel (Ed.) Constructionist learning (pp.
249-280) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ramadas, J. and Shayer, M. (1993). Schematic representations in optics, In P. Black and A. Lucas
(Eds.), Children's informal ideas (pp. 172-189). London: Routledge.
Roskos-Ewoldsen, B., Intons-Peterson, M. J. and Anderson, R. E. (1993). Imagery, creativity and
discovery: Conclusions and implications. In B. Roskos-Ewoldsen, M. J. Intons-Peterson and R. E.
Anderson (Eds.), Imagery, creativity, and discovery: A cognitive perspective (pp. 313-328).
Advances in Psychology, Vol.98, Eds. G. E. Stelmach and and P. A. Vroon. Amsterdam: North
Holland (Elsevier Science Publishers B. V.).
Schnotz, W. (2002). Towards and integrated view of learning from text and visual displays.
Educational Psychology Review, 14 (1), 101-119.
Schwartz, D. L. and Black, J. (1996). Shuttling between depictive models and abstract rules:
Induction and fallback. Cognitive Science, 20 (4), 457-497.
Shank, G. and Cunningham, D. J. (1996). Modeling the six modes of Peircean abduction for
educational purposes. Retrieved on 30 Nov 2006 from
http://www.cs.indiana.edu/event/maics96/Proceedings/shank.html.
Shapin, S. and Schaffer, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the
experimental life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Shepard, R. N. and Metzler, J. (1971). Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science, 171,
701-3.
Shepard, R. N. (1978). Externalization of mental images and the act of creation. In B. Randhawa
and W. E. Coffman (Eds.) Visual learning, thinking and communication (pp.133-189). New York:
Academic Press.
Shepard, R. N. (1988). The imagination of the scientist. In K. Egan and D. Nadaner (Eds.)
Imagination and education (pp. 153-185). New York and London: Teacher's College.
Simon, M. A. (1996). Beyond inductive and deductive reasoning: the search for a sense of
knowing. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 30, 197-209.
Sorby, S. (this issue). Educational research in developing 3-D spatial skills for engineering
students. International Journal of Science Education.
Stieff, M., Bateman, R. C. and Uttal, D. H. (2005). Teaching and learning with three-dimensional
representations. In J. K. Gilbert (Ed.) Visualization in Science Education (pp. 93-118). Dordrecht,
The Netherlands: Springer.
16
Subramaniam, K. (1999). Inscriptions, facts and blackboxes: is modern science radically different?
In I. S. Habib and D. Raina (Eds.) Situating the history of science: Dialogues with Joseph Needham
(pp. 325-348). New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Subramaniam, K. and Padalkar, S. (this issue). Visualisation and reasoning in explaining the phases
of the moon. International Journal of Science Education.
Taylor, P. J. and Blum, A. S. (1991). Pictorial representation in biology. Biology & Philosophy, 6,
125-134.
Thomas, N. J. T. (2003). Mental imagery, philosophical issues about. In L. Nadel (Ed.),
Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science, Vol. 2. London: Nature Publishing / Macmillan. 1147-1153.
Thompson, D'Arcy W. (1961). On growth and form (abridged, Ed. J. T. Bonner). London:
Cambridge University Press.
Topper, D. (1996). Towards an epistemology of scientific illustration. In B. S. Baigrie (Ed.)
Picturing knowledge: Historical and philosophical problems concerning the use of art in science
(pp. 215-249). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Trafton, J. G., Trickett, S. B., and Mintz, F. (2005). Connecting internal and external
representations: spatial transformations of scientific visualizations, Foundations of Science, 10, 89106.
Trickett, S. B. and Trafton, J. G. (2006). Towards a comprehensive model of graph comprehension:
Making the case for spatial cognition. In D. Barker-Plummer et al. (Eds.), Diagrams 2006 (pp. 286300), LNAI 4045, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.
Trumbo, J. (2006). Making science visible: Visual literacy in science communication. In Pauwels,
L. (Ed.), Visual culture of science: Re-thinking representational practices in knowledge building
and science communication (pp. 266-284). Dartmouth College Press, University Press of New
England.
Tversky, B. (1999). What does drawing reveal about thinking? In J. S. Gero \& B. Tversky (Eds.),
Visual and spatial reasoning in design (pp. 93-101). Sydney, Australia: Key Centre of Design
Computing and Cognition.
Tversky, B. (2001). Spatial schemas in depictions. In M. Gattis (Ed.) Spatial schemas and abstract
thought (pp. 79-112). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Tversky, B. (2005). Visuospatial reasoning. In K. Holyoak and R. Morrison (Eds.), The Cambridge
handbook of thinking and reasoning (Chapter 10). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Verstijnen, I. M., van Leeuwen, C., Goldschmidt, G., Hamel, R. and Hennessey, J. M. (1998).
Creative discovery in imagery and perception: Combining is relatively easy, restructuring takes a
sketch. Acta Psychologica, 99, 177-200.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in Society. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Wales, R. (1990). Children's pictures, In R. Grieve and M. Hughes (Eds.), Understanding children:
Essays in honour of Margaret Donaldson (pp. 140-155), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wise, M. N. (1979). The mutual embrace of electricity and magnetism. Science, 203, 1310-1318.,
1310-1318.
17
Download