Validations of Proofs Considered as Texts: Can Undergraduates Tell Whether an Argument Proves a Theorem? Author(s): Annie Selden and John Selden Reviewed work(s): Source: Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, Vol. 34, No. 1 (Jan., 2003), pp. 4-36 Published by: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/30034698 . Accessed: 21/08/2012 14:11 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . National Council of Teachers of Mathematics is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal for Research in Mathematics Education. http://www.jstor.org Journalfor Researchin MathematicsEducation 2003, Vol. 34, No. 1,4-36 Validations of Proofs Considered as Texts: Can Undergraduates Tell Whether an Argument Proves a Theorem? Annie Selden, TennesseeTechnological University John Selden, MathematicsEducationResources Company Thisarticlereportson an exploratory and studyof the waythateightmathematics secondaryeducationmathematics majorsreadandreflectedon fourstudent-generto be proofsof a singletheorem.Theresultssuggestthat atedarguments purported suchundergraduates tendto focuson surfacefeaturesof arguments andthattheir whetherarguments areproofsis verylimited-perhapsmoreso abilityto determine thaneithertheyortheirinstructors recognize.Thearticlebeginsby discussingarguments(purported that proofs)regardedas textsandvalidationsof thosearguments, is, reflectionsof individuals checkingwhethersucharguments reallyareproofsof theorems.Itrelatesthemathematics researchcommunity's viewsof proofsandtheir validations to ideasfromreadingcomprehension andliterarytheory.Then,a detailed is givenandtheeightstudents'valianalysisof thefourstudent-generated arguments dationsof themareanalyzed. Key Words:Advancedmathematical thinking;College/university; Languageand mathematics; Proof;Reasoning; Writing/communication. Proofs, that is, arguments'thatprove theorems,have been viewed from a wide variety of perspectives.Previous studies have consideredthe structureof proofs (Leron, 1983), theirexplanatorypower (Hanna,1989), errorsand misconceptions in college students'proofs (Selden & Selden, 1987), the logic involved (Dubinsky & Yiparaki,2000; Selden & Selden, 1995), universitystudents'"proofschemes" (Harel & Sowder, 1998), and generic proofs (Rowland, 2002). In addition, one mightdescribethe genreof proofsor discusstheirrhetoric.Considerablymorecould also be done in examiningthe process of proof construction. 1We areusing argumentthe way it is commonlyused in the English-speakingmathematicalcommunity (Bagchi & Wells, 1998), whereproofis often reservedfor a correctargumentconsistingof a rather special kind of deductivereasoningthatwarrantsthe truthof a theorem(dimonstration,in French).In thatcontext, and in this article,argumentrefersto the same kind of deductivereasoning,except thatit might not be correct.We arenot referringto the moregeneralkindsof argumentsused outsideof mathematics or to argumentation,for example,to discourseintendedto persuadethatmightincludealluding to experiences of the intendedaudience(see Perelman& Olbrechts-Tyteca,1969 or Toulmin, 1958). Thisstudywas supported in partby a FacultyResearchGrantfromTennessee Technological University. Annie Selden and John Selden 5 Herewe focus on proofs as texts thatestablishthe truthof theoremsandon readings of, andreflectionson, proofsto determinetheircorrectness.We call suchreadings and the mentalprocesses associatedwith them validationsofproofs (Selden & Selden, 1995). A validationis often much longer and more complex than the writtenproof and may be difficult to observe because not all of it is conscious. Moreover,even its conscious partmay be conductedsilently using inner speech and vision. Validationcan include asking and answeringquestions, assentingto claims,constructingsubproofs,rememberingor findingandinterpretingothertheorems anddefinitions,complyingwith instructions(e.g., to consideror name something),andconscious (butprobablynonverbal)feelings of rightnessor wrongness. Proof validation can also include the production of a new text-a validatorconstructedmodificationof the writtenargument- thatmight include additional calculations,expansionsof definitions,or constructionsof subproofs.Towardthe end of a validation,in an effort to capturethe essence of the argumentin a single trainof thought,contractionsof the argumentmight be undertaken.An annotated transcriptof a sample (hypothetical)validationof a calculus proof can be found in AppendixI of Selden and Selden (1995, pp. 143-147). In the sections that follow, we discuss a theoreticalperspectiveon arguments, proofs, and validationsand compareit with various20th-centurytheoriesof texts and reading.We then give a detailedtextualanalysis of a single theoremand four brief student-generatedargumentspurportingto prove it. This analysis provides groundingfor the previous theoreticaldiscussion, as well as backgroundfor the subsequentdescriptionand analysis of eight undergraduatestudents'validations of the samefourarguments.In the concludingsections,we offer some implications for teachingand pose some questionsfor futureresearch. VALIDATIONAND OTHERKINDS OF READING Ourview of the natureof validationis reminiscentof late 20th-centuryideasabout readingfoundin workson readingcomprehensionandliterarytheoryandcriticism (as describedin Bogdan & Straw, 1990 and Pearson,2000). In these, the onus for the constructionof meaningis on the readerratherthanon the authoror the written text. Each readeris seen as constructinghis or her own story from personalbackground together with the written text. Different readers, or the same reader at different times, are seen as benefiting differently from a single written text. Validatorsof proofs, too, may benefit in differing ways accordingto their backgrounds.Forexample, some may develop an understandingof a theoremthatgoes well beyondjust knowing it is true, and Hanna(1989) has pointed out that some proofs may be betterfor this than others. Also validationcan sometimes involve emotionally intense reflection resultingin knowledge construction,for example, by forging new links between one's ideas. At the beginning of the 20th century,theorists in reading comprehensionand literary criticism regarded writing as mainly a matter of communication-the authorwas consideredtheultimatearbiterof the meaningof a writtentext.To under- 6 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered standa text, one studiedthe life and times of the author.By midcentury,the locus of meaninghadshiftedto the text itself,2andby the end of the century,the construction of meaningwas viewed as residingwith the reader.The idea thatthe meaning is in the text has been articulatedby Olson (1977); it has been referredto as the "doctrineof autonomoustexts"andwas critiquedby Nystrand,Doyle, andHimley (1986), who includedan examplethatmay shed some light on the uniquecharacter of proofs. They pointedout thatlegal contractsaredocumentsexplicitly meantto be autonomous and independentof context, but nevertheless such documents cause disputesthatcourtsareaskedto settleby calling in expertsto clarifythe original terminology and context. This example supportsthe idea that independence of context is inherentlyunachievable.In contrast,such situationsdo not occurwith proofs; one does not call in experts to find out what an authormeant by, say, "compact"to establishthe truthof a theorem. Like midcentury structuralcritics, mathematicians3seem to treat a proof as being independentfrom its author.If something,perhapsthe author'sreputation, should suggest that a proof is probablycorrect, mathematiciansmay attemptto suspend their credulitysimilar to the way an audience in a classical theaterwas supposedto suspendits disbelief arisingfrom unrealisticcostumes and surroundings. That is, a mathematicianmay believe a theorem assertedby a well-known authorto be true,but may readthe argumentsin its proof as if the statementof the theorem were in question. This predilectionfor separatingauthorsfrom proofs appearsto be reflectedin the way proofs arewritten,for example,in the avoidance of autobiographicalcommentin publishedmathematicalresearch.Indeeda general tendency to impersonalize mathematicaltexts, especially research papers, has been notedin analysesof their"naturallanguage"aspects(Burton& Morgan,2000). By the early 1990s, readingand writing were beginning to be seen as different aspects of one unified process. Similarly,validationandproof constructionmight be seen as differing aspects of a single process. As such, they are probablybest learnedin a dialecticalway. On the one hand, one constructsa proof with an eye toward ultimately validating it and may often validate parts of it during the constructionprocess. In fact, the final portionof a proof constructionis likely to be a validationof that proof. On the other hand, proofs are writtenfor idealized readers,yet there is considerablevariationin what actualmathematiciansknow. Thus, the validationof a proof is likely to requirethe constructionof subproofs. That is, each process, validationand proof construction,entails the other. Validation and proof construction also differ in importantrespects. Proof constructionis much more like mathematicalproblem solving, in the sense of 2 The idea that meaningcan reside in the text was not new to the 20th century.It appearsto go back at least to the time of Plato andbecame a majortenet for MartinLuther,who assertedthatthe meaning of Scripturewas to be found in a deeperreadingof the text (Olson, 1977, p. 263). 3 In the context of this article,when mentioningmathematiciansor the mathematicscommunity,we are referringespecially to those engaged in research in pure mathematics,that is, in finding and proving theorems. Annie Selden and John Selden 7 Schoenfeld(1985), thanis validation.Generallyconstructinga proof requiresthat more diverse ideas come to mind at the "righttime"thanvalidatingit does. Also, like most reading, validationnormallyemphasizes proceedinglinearly from the beginningto the end of a writtenproof-perhaps repeatedseveraltimes.This linear orderis unlikelyto occurin proofconstruction.Given a theoremto prove,one must often attendnot only to the beginningbut also to the end of a proof before developing the middle. In addition,many proofs have a hierarchicalstructurebased on subproofsandsubconstructionsthatemergesduringthe processof proofconstruction. Even assumingan idealized prover(one makingno mistakes or false starts, which is an inherently unrealistic assumption), such an emergent hierarchical structuremay lead to generatingsubargumentsin an ordervery differentfromthat of the final writtentext. Indeed,for the workingmathematician,a theoremand its proofsometimesemergein a dialecticalway over a long periodof time,with adjustments in one alternatingwith adjustmentsin the other. One distinctionbetween currentideas of reading and that of validationis that writtenproofs are still seen as carryingconsiderablemeaning. The proofs themselves (as opposed to theirreadersor authors)are regardedby mathematiciansas the ultimateestablishersof the truthof theorems.4One examines neitherthe life andtimesof a proof s authornorthe sophisticationof its readersin judgingthe truth of a theorem. Perhapsthis is partly because any expanded or altered argument constructedby a validatoris often seen as closely alignedwith the originalwritten proof, so thatthe originalproofis deemedcorrect(in some generalsense) provided the expanded,validator-generatedtext is seen by the validatoras correct. Anotherdistinctionbetween validationandreadingin generalappearsto be the unusualdegree of agreementaboutthe correctnessof argumentsand the truthof theoremsarisingfrom the validationprocess.It is ourexperiencethatif two mathematiciansdisagree on the correctnessof a proof, they will often attempta joint validationof it (or a fragmentof it). Typically, they will either expand the proof and agree on the expandedversion or, failing that, they will find and agree on a mistakethatcannotbe fixed. Occasionally,they may find andcorrectsmall errors thatthey agreeareinsignificantanddo not affectthe overallcorrectnessof the argument.This abilityto reachagreementappearsto dependto some extenton the way that mathematicaldefinitions have come to be treated as more or less unchallengeable in the 20th century. Today, definitionsin mathematicsare typically treatedas analytic,as reducible to undefinedtermsexcept for foundationalconsiderations,such as the meaningof set, element, or integer.Such considerationsare not majorissues for most mathematiciansperhapspartlybecause "normal"foundationsyield a mathematicsthat can be interpretedas parallelingan intuitiveview of the world developed socially 4 This view is supportedby the ability of computersto check the correctnessof many (more formally stated)proofs. For example, a large numberof proofs have been machineverified after conversionto the Mizarlanguageand are publishedonline in the Journal of Formalized Mathematics(see mizar.org/JFM/). 8 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered from an early age. Withboth "normal"foundationsand an intuitiveview one can consider several objects together,count them, add, measurethings, and so on.' In contrastwith analyticdefinitions,syntheticdefinitions6arethe everydaydefinitions thatare commonly found in dictionaries-they areoften ill-specified descriptions of thingsthatalreadyexist. It may be unclearwhen such everydaydefinitions(e.g., of democracy)are "complete"or whetherattentionto all aspectsof them is essential for their properuse. Analytic definitions, however, bring concepts into existence-the concept (e.g., of group as used in mathematics)is whateverthe definition says it is, nothing more and nothing less. One cannot safely ignore any aspects of such definitions.There is a sense in which syntheticdefinitions can be "wrong," that is, they can be inaccurate descriptions, but analytic definitions cannot, since nothingis being described.' For example, our syntheticdefinition of validation could be wrong; we might have inaccurately described what we claimed is a recurringphenomenon. In contrast, few mathematicianswould say the analytic definition of "group"was wrong-uninteresting, tasteless,lackingapplications,or inaccuratelyremembered perhaps,butnot wrong.Today'suse of analyticdefinitionsrendersvalidations(and proofs andtheorems)very reliable,whereasthe earlieruse of syntheticdefinitions sometimes left them problematic. This situation can be seen in Proofs and Refutations(Lakatos, 1976) where validationsappearinherentlyunreliable,that is, unreliableeven if there are no errors.There, theoremshave proofs and refutations (counterexamples)apparentlydueto treatingdefinitionsas syntheticandhence challengeable. Given some literary license, Proofs and Refutationsprovides a fairlyaccuratedescriptionof the way thatsome mathematicsdevelopedhistorically. It illustrateshow definitionsandresultscan coevolve, but the compressionof time involved in its fictional narration,togetherwith its synthetictreatmentof definitions, may suggest thatvalidations,proofs, and theoremsarefar less reliable than they really are today. Roles Played by Validation Althoughwe arefocusing here on the validationabilitiesandpracticesof undergraduates who are in at least their 2nd year of mathematics study, validation 5 However, nothingin principlerestrictsmathematiciansto particularfoundations.For example, in intuitionist/constructivistmathematics,one forgoes mathematicalinductionand the logical law of the excluded middle, resultingin a more limited mathematicswithout proofs by inductionor contradiction. 6 Our distinction between analytic and synthetic follows that made by Sierpinska, Defence, Khatcherian,and Saldanha(1997) in discussing linear algebra.Similar distinctionshave been made by Edwards(1997) using lexical andlogical andby Freudenthal(1973) using constructiveanddescriptive. In consideringdefining as a mathematicalactivity in geometry,Rasmussenand Zandieh(2000) and de Villiers (1998) adoptedFreudenthal'sterminology. 7 Analytic definitionscan, however, be inspiredby regularitiesin the physical world, in which case a mathematicalstructuremay be metaphoricallyrepresentedin a physical situation.Vectors areuseful in navigationbecause the motion of a sailboat(in part)"workslike" vector addition. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 9 appearsto have a role to play throughoutmathematicsstudents'education,in mathematicians'practice,and in examinationsof the natureof mathematics. Validationin mathematicseducation.Holdersof bachelor's degrees in mathematics arenormallyexpected not only to know considerablemathematicscontent but also to be able to constructmoderatelycomplex proofsandto solve moderately nonroutineproblems. Indeed, one major way that an individual's mathematical knowledge of a theorem is sometimes taken to be warrantedis by the ability to "produce"a proof,not in a roteway butin the way a mathematicianwould produce it and with understanding(Rodd, 2000). However, constructing or producing proofsis inextricablylinkedto the abilityto validatethemreliably,and a proofthat couldnotbe reliablyvalidatedwouldnotprovidemuchof a warrant.Solvingmoderately nonroutineproblems also appears to call for abilities akin to validation, because one must ascertainwhethera proposedsolution is correct.In ourongoing investigationof mathematicians'views, we arefindingthatmanymathematicians believe thatchecking the correctnessof solutionsultimatelydependson the same kind of deductivereasoningthatis used in proofs and their validations. Preservicesecondarymathematicseducationmajorsand mathematicsteachers also needto be ableto validateproofsreliablybecauseschool mathematicscurricula are likely to place increasingemphasis on proofs and problem solving (NCTM, 2000). In this regard,Cuoco has observed informallybut on the basis of considerableexperiencethat"Thebest high school teachersarethosewho have a researchlike experiencein mathematics"(2001, p. 171).And in an articlein theMathematics Teacher,Thompson(1996) suggeststeachingindirectproofto high school students using number-theoreticstatementsthatare similarto, althoughperhapssomewhat less complex than,the theoremused with undergraduatesin ourexploratorystudy. Validationin thepractice of mathematicians.In additionto being importantfor mathematicsmajorsandmathematicsteachers,validationappearsto play a fundamentalrole in the productionof new mathematics.A mathematician'sbelief in the reliabilityand unproblematicnatureof validationprovides the assuranceneeded to use a theoremin laterworkwithoutrepeatedlycheckingits correctness.Thatis, when a theoremis proved "it stays proved."This reliabilityseems to have been a majorcontributorto the rapidgrowththathas characterized20th-centurymathematics. Furthermore,many mathematiciansseem to rely mainly on validation, sometimescarriedout individuallyand sometimesin seminars,to learnnew mathematics from the publishedresearchof others. Validationwithinsocial constructivist(and other)perspectives. Ourcomments aboutthe truthof theoremsmight suggest that we are taking a Platonistperspective, with its timeless abstractobjects and absolutetruthindependentfrom human considerations.However, in this article, we are not favoring any single perspective on mathematics.Validationis a largelymentalprocess with social originsand social consequences thatbears examining relative to any of several views on the nature of mathematics. Furthermore,for many mathematicians,the truth of a theorem appearsto be functionally just the existence of an argumentthat they 10 Validationsof Proofs Consideredas Texts personally(or theirpresumedsurrogates)have validatedanddeemedto be a proof of thattheorem.In particular,a furtherinvestigationof validationmightbe helpful in viewing mathematicsfrom a social constructivistperspective-where mathematics is seen as an entirely social, fallible' phenomenonwith the idea of truth replaced by social agreementand where abstractPlatonic objects have no role (Ernest,1998).An accuratedescriptionof how new mathematicsis createdis crucial from this perspective because, in a sense, how it is done is mathematics.We suspect that, if analyzed together, proofs and validations thereof might in the future play a larger role within a social constructivist perspective. In such an analysis, foundationsandthe kind of logic used could be treatedas hidden,thatis, tacitly assumed,premisesof theorems.By examiningthe extent of agreementand the way it arises from the validationprocess, one might find a way to see mathematics as locally9infallibleand therebyreconcile this philosophicalview with the more-or-less Platonic working views of most researchmathematicians.Indeed, those workingviews may have emergedmainlyfromexperiencewith the reliability of validation,ratherthanfrom any priorphilosophicalcommitment. Regardless of one's perspectiveon the natureof mathematicsor its knowing, investigations of validation as a form of reading (and of the argumentsbeing read),with emphasison what validatorsdo, could informmathematicseducation. Ourexploratorystudyis a startin this direction.We begin with an analysisof some specific arguments. A TEXTUAL ANALYSIS OF A THEOREMAND FOUR "PROOFS" In this section, we analyze a theoremandfour undergraduatestudent-generated argumentspurportedto prove it. This analysiswill provideconcretegroundingfor the above theoreticaldiscussion of argument,proof, and validation,as well as for the subsequentdescriptionof ourexploratorystudyof otherundergraduate students' validationsof these same four arguments.It may also expose aspectsof these texts thatmight otherwisebe missed. For example, we point out thatcertainportionsof the first argumentare extraneousand as such have no effect on its correctnessas a proof. Nevertheless,errorsin these extraneousportionswere noted and thought to be importantby some of our studentvalidators. The theoremand the four argumentsare treatedhere primarilyas texts, that is, as independentof specific authorsand validators.We will, however, commentin generalon how aspectsof these texts may have come to be writtenor might affect readers,occasionallyillustratingthis pointwith commentsfromourstudentvalidators. The theoremis true and one of the argumentsis a proof of it, whereasthree 8 Here, following Ernest (1998), we mean by fallible something more than just the (generally accepted)humantendencyto make mistakes. 9 By locally we mean the mathematicsvaries according to the foundationsand logic used. For example, a mathematicalconstructivistwould not accept the law of the excluded middle and, consequently, obtain different theorems than a mathematicianwho did accept the law of the excluded middle. We are not referringto geographicor social variations. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 11 arenot;thatis, as proofsthey areincorrect.These characterizations-true,correct, proof-are widely regardedby mathematiciansas globalfeaturesof texts alonethat canbe determinedwithoutknowingwho the authorsor readersare.Mathematicians say thatan argumentproves a theorem,not thatit proves it for Smith and possibly not for Jones, who are readersof the argument.This view is held despite the fact that the texts are the productsof humanactivities, that their physical representations could not exist without authors,and that validatorsare requiredfor anyone to know the theoremis true.Perhapssuch assignmentsof proof, truth,andcorrectness (or their opposites) to texts is due to mathematicians'remarkablyuniform agreementon whetherthese propertiesareassociatedwith particulartexts-at least at the level of the mathematicsdiscussed here and modulo modest concernsabout style or completeness. Texts (and, more generally,language and communication)have been analyzed fromseveralperspectives:syntacticstructure(e.g., Chomsky,1957), semanticstructure (e.g., Fillmore, 1968; Kintsch, 1974), and language in use (Halliday, 1977; Vachek, 1966). Relevant ideas emphasizing language in use that are especially applicableto mathematicaltexts have been summarizedandillustratedby Morgan (1996). These ideas include such featuresas the ways reasoningis expressed(e.g., because, so), the symmetryor asymmetryof the relationshipbetween authorsand readers,andwhattextsmightsuggestaboutthe natureof mathematics.Mostof these features,for example the use of "we" in mathematicaltexts (Pimm, 1984), have no bearingon whetheran argumentprovesa theorem;andin ourexperience,undergraduatestudents realize this and concentrateon the underlying mathematical concepts and inferences. Thus, we provide a differentkind of textual analysis, one that is a kind of lineby-line gloss, or elaboration,of the theoremand the four student-generatedarguments emphasizing mathematicaland logical points that a validator might, or might not, notice. For example, in consideringthe statementof the theorem,we discuss both its logical structureand other, more informal,ways that it could be written.For the four student-generatedarguments,we discuss such mattersas the use of alternativeterms(e.g., assume for suppose, divides insteadof multiple),the role of individualsentences in furtheringthe argument,properand improperuses of symbols, implicit assumptions(e.g., that a division of the argumentinto cases is exhaustive), the correctness of inferences, computationalerrors, extraneous statements, and structuralaspects of the argument.Global properties, such as whetheran argumentproves the theorem,as opposed to some othertheorem,are also discussed. In the following analyses, the names of the four arguments(e.g., "Proof(a)": Errors Galore) and the numberingof their parts are for the convenience of the reader;the names and numberingwere not shown to the eight studentvalidators in our study. The theoremto be proved was this: THEOREM: For any positive integer n, if n2 is a multipleof 3, then n is a multiple of 3. 12 as Texts Validations of ProofsConsidered Both the studentauthorsof the four argumentsandthe studentvalidatorsin our empirical study were given this statementof the theorem.It is a formalstatement in that the variable n, the set to which it refers (the positive integers), and the universalquantification,any, areexplicitly stated,andthe conditionalis expressed in its most common form, if. ..., then. However, other, less formal statementsof this theoremconvey the same logical information;theirequivalencecan be established using logic andlittle or no additionalmathematicalcontent.Often,theorems that undergraduatestudentsat this level consider are stated in a less formal way. For example, one informal statementof this theorem is A positive integer is a multipleof 3 wheneverits square is. Undergraduatestudentssimilarto the ones in our empiricalstudyappearto have considerabledifficultyinterpretinginformalstatementsof theoremsandconverting themto formalones (Selden& Selden, 1995). In ourexperience,formalstatements appearto be the ones most easily interpretedin validations;they correspondto what we have called proof frameworks.These consist of the beginning and end of a proof-the partthatcanbe writtenwithoutknowingthe meaningsof all of the mathematical terms and from which the theoremcan be reconstructed.It is an understanding(usuallytacit)of the relationshipbetweenstatementsof theoremsandtheir proofframeworksthatallows validatorsto decideif an argumentprovesthe theorem at handas opposedto some othertheorem.A proof framework'" for this theoremis this: PROOF. Let n be a positive integerand supposen2 is a multipleof 3. ... Then n is a multipleof 3. Often the introductionof a variable,for example, "Letn be a positive integer,"is omittedbutunderstood.This omissionusuallyoccurswhen the variableappearsin the statementof the theorem,as it does here. Ourearlierwork (Selden & Selden, 1995) suggests that,amongthe variouspossible ways to statea theorem, studentvalidatorsshould find the more formal statementused here the easiest to correctlyconnect with argumentspurportingto prove it. In what follows, we state each student-generatedargumentverbatimand then give our line-by-line analysis of it. "Proof (a)": Errors Galore PROOF. Assume thatn2 is an odd positive integerthat is divisible by 3. That is n2 = (3n +1)2 = 9n2+6n +1 = 3n(n + 2) + 1. Therefore,n2 is divisible by 3. Assume thatn2 is even and a multipleof 3. That is, n2 = (3n)2 = 9n2 = 3n(3n). Therefore, n2 is a multipleof 3. If we factorn2 = 9n2, we get 3n(3n); which means thatn is a multiple of 3. U Analysis of "Proof (a)" [1] Assume that n2 is an odd positive integer that is divisible by 3. This partof the argumentis not wrong. In this context one can take assume to mean suppose, 10Proof frameworksare often more complex thanthis. For examples from calculus and semigroup theory, see Selden and Selden (1995, pp. 129-130). AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 13 and an authorof a proof can suppose any reasonablenon-selfcontradictorystatement which might aid the progressof the argument.But, as some of our student validatorsnoted, this division into odd and even cases is a peculiarway to structure a proof of this particulartheorem.It is peculiarbecause odd and even appear to be unrelatedto multiplesof 3. That the phrase "n2 is divisible by 3" is an equivalent way of saying "n2 is a multipleof 3" is somethinga validatorwould need to assent to (by noting thatthe definitionsof divisibilityandmultiplearemathematicallyequivalent).One student validator,whom we refer to in this articleas SW, briefly noted (and assentedto) the fact that "divisible by 3" was used here; subsequently, in the even case, "multipleof 3" was used. [2] Thatis n2 = (3n + 1)2 = 9n2 + 6n + 1 = 3n(n + 2) + 1. There are four errors here.First,the assumptionof oddnesswas aboutn2, not n, to which it is apparently being applied (i.e., n = 3n + 1). Second, n is being used in two places with two differentmeaningswithinone equation;in effect, the authoris mistakenlyasserting thatn = 3n + 1. In the genre of mathematicalproofs, it is not permissibleto let the samesymbolrepresenttwo differentnumbersexceptacrossindependentsubproofs. Doing so would be very likely to cause validatorsconfusion. Indeed, studentST remarkedthat "all those n's tryingto equal each other"misled her. Third,an odd integern can be representedas n = 2m + 1, not as 3m + 1, where m is a different integerfromn. Fourth,the last equationis incorrect;3n times n yields 3n2,not 9n2. We would like to commentfurtheron the author'sapparentidea that3n + 1 can representa generalodd number.We doubt that this idea indicatesa more-or-less fixed misconceptionin the author'sknowledgebase,butrathersuspectit is an incorrect,partialrecollectionof the idea that2n + 1 is odd for integervalues of n. There appearsto be a more subtle lack in the author'sknowledge, and we will offer a conjectureof its natureandhow it occurs.Studentsof mathematicsprobablyrecognize (mostlytacitly)manykindsof problemsandtasks,andeach kindmay be associatedwith manyotherideas, forminga mentalstructurelike a conceptimage(Tall & Vinner, 1981) for thatproblemor task-what we have called a problem-situation image. When a kind of problemor task is recognized,an associatedproblemsituationimage may be activated(broughtto mind) or partlyactivated(Baddeley, 1995). In particular,accomplishedstudentsmightassociatethe taskof representing a generaloddnumberwith a feeling of cautionaboutgettingtherepresentation right. As they execute the task,this feeling of cautionmay engenderchecking.In the case at hand,thatmight mean substitutingsome numbersfor n: substituting1 for n (in 3n + 1) yields4 andindicatesthat3n + 1 neednotbe odd.We suspectthatthe author's problem-situationimage(s) for this task did not include an appropriatefeeling of caution.A mechanismfor bringingsomethingto mind similarto the one sketched here, concerninghow to startsolving a recognizedkindof problem,has been more fully describedin Selden, Selden, Hauk,& Mason (2000). [3] Therefore,n2 is divisible by 3. It was assumedin [1] thatn2 is divisible by 3. Thus,this statementcannotbe wrongdespitethe interveningerrorsin [2]; however, it cannotbe of use either.Furthermore,this statementcompletes one of two inde- 14 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered pendentsubproofs,one for n2 odd andone for n2 even, and shouldhave endedwith n as a multiple of 3, not n2. The errorsin [2] might be called extraneouserrors.Because they do not affect the correctnessof [3], they cannot affect whetheror not the argumentis a proof. Such errors are nevertheless undesirable because they can make arguments confusing and more difficult to validate. In our empirical study, most student validatorsspent considerabletime trying to decipher [2], making comments like "3n + 1 doesn't make sense [for odd],"but did not seem to notice its irrelevance. [4] Assumethatn2 is even and a multipleof 3. This assumptionis an appropriate beginning of the second independentsubproof(case). However, as alreadynoted under [1], this division into cases, althoughnot wrong, is unlikely to be useful. [5] Thatis n2 = (3n)2 = 9n2 = 3n(3n). In the first equationn2 = (3n)2, it appears thatthe assumptionthatn2 is a multiple of 3 is incorrectlyappliedto n insteadof n2. Also, in the implicitequationn = 3n, once againthe right-handn does not have the same meaningas the left-handn. To indicatethatn is a multipleof 3, one represents n as 3m, wherem is anotherpositive integer.The second and thirdequations are correct. [6] Therefore,n2is a multipleof 3. This conclusionis not incorrect;it does follow from [5] (if one replaces all but the first "n"with "m's"). But it also just repeats the assumptionin [4], which is not likely to be useful. [7] Ifwefactor n2 = 9n2,we get 3n(3n).Here the authorappearsto be attempting to restateinformationfrom [5], which could not introduceany new errors.Since the word "factor"refersto expressions,not equations,we take it that[7] is a shortened form of "Now n2 = 9n2, and if we factor9n2, we get 3n(3n)." [8] whichmeans thatn is a multipleof 3. U This inferencefrom [7] is not correct even if we change3n(3n)to 3m(3m).To concludethatn is a multipleof 3, one would expect to see 3 as a factorof n, not as a factorof n2.The symbol "N" is one of those customarilyused to indicatethe end of a proof. In summary,this argumentis not a proof. It consists of two independentsubargumentseach of which should end with "n is a multipleof 3" or its equivalent, "nis divisible by 3." However,the odd case did not end this way, andthe even case made this claim but did not properlyjustify it. It is left implicit thatthe two cases are exhaustive, thatis, thatevery integeris eithereven or odd, but it is customary to leave such a well-known fact implicit. We would like to mention two kinds of global errorsthat this argumentdoes not contain. First, although the argumenthas a high density of errors,they are not what one might call mathematically syntactical errors (Selden & Selden, 1987). The mathematicaltermsand symbols fit togetherin a meaningfulway (i.e., one canjudge whethereach individualstatementis corrector incorrect).Second, the two subargumentsreally are independent. Occasionally, one finds arguments in which an inference in one subargumentimproperlydepends on information from inside anothersupposedly independentsubargument,and thaterror did not occur here. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 15 Last, we have taken this argumentat face value; that is, we have assumed that the authormeantto write a proof andhad some more-or-lessclear (althoughincorrect) conception of how the argument would proceed. However, because the studentauthorsubmittedthis "proof' as partof a take-hometest, it is possible that he or she was merely seeking some (partial)credit and was thus workingin what Vinner(1997) has called a pseudoconceptualmode," mimickingsome previously encounteredargumentaboutmultiplesof 2. One possible similarargumentmight have been the following proof of the statement:For any integern, n2 is a multiple of 2 if and only if n is a multipleof 2. PROOF.If n is odd, then n2 = (2k + 1)2 = 4k2 + 4k+1 = 2(2k2 + 2k) + 1, which is odd. Therefore, if n2 is a multiple of 2, then n is a multiple of 2. Now, if n is a multiple of 2, that is, if n is even, then n2 = (2k)2 = 4k2 = 2(2k2), which is a multiple of 2. M "Proof(b)": TheReal Thing PROOF. Suppose to the contrarythatn is not a multipleof 3. We will let 3k be a positive integer that is a multiple of 3, so that 3k + 1 and 3k + 2 are integersthat are not multiples of 3. Now n2 = (3k + 1)2 = 9k2 + 6k + 1 = 3(3k2 + 2k) + 1. Since 3(3k2+ 2k) is a multipleof 3, 3(3k2+ 2k) + 1 is not.Now we will do the otherpossibility, 3k + 2. So, n2 = (3k + 2)2 = 9k2 + 12k + 4 = 3(3k2 + 4k + 1) + 1 is not a multipleof 3. Because n2 is not a multipleof 3, we have a contradiction.E Analysis of "Proof(b)" [1] Suppose to the contrary that n is not a multiple of 3. The phrase "to the contrary"may indicatethatthis argumentis meantto be a proof by contradiction. It mightalso indicatethatthe argumentwill provethe contrapositiveof the theorem, thatis, thatthe negationof the conclusion implies the negation of the hypothesis, which is logically equivalentto the theorem.The studentauthormay not be clear aboutthe distinction.If the proofis reallyby contradiction,it is implicitthatn represents a positive integerand n2 is assumedto be a multipleof 3. The argumentcan end with any contradiction,but thatcontradictioncould be to the hypothesis,that is, n2 is not a multipleof 3. If the contrapositiveof the theoremis being proved, it is implicitonly thatn representsa positive integer,andthe argumentmustend with n2 is not a multipleof 3. Forboth methodsof proof it is appropriateto supposethe negation of the conclusion, that is, n is not a multipleof 3, as is done here. [2] Wewill let 3k be a positive integer that is a multipleof 3, so that 3k + 1 and 3k + 2 are integersthatare not multiplesof 3. This representationanddivision into cases correctlyfollows from the fact thatany positive integercan be represented as exactly one of 3k, 3k + 1, or 3k + 2 for some positive integerk. It is implicit that 11 Indeed, one student validator,ST, seems to have concluded that the authorof "Proof (a)" was workingpseudoconceptuallyor at least had no clear conceptionof a proof. After finding severalerrors and noticing thatcertainpartsdid not make sense, she stated,"Basically,it's a bunch of nothing." 16 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered the positive integerbeing representedis n andthat,accordingto [1], n cannotequal 3k; thus, n must equal 3k + 1 or 3k + 2. A validatorwould need to check that this statement is correct. To comprehend [2], it would not be essential to see the implicitrepresentationof n as one of the threeexpressions,but it would be in order to comprehend[3]. [3] Now n2 = (3k + 1)2= 9k2 + 6k + 1 = 3(3k2 + 2k) + 1. This statementbegins the first of two independent,"parallel"subarguments.Assuming that n = 3k + 1, all of the equationsare correct. [4] Since 3(3k2 + 2k) is a multipleof 3, 3(3k2 + 2k) + 1 is not. It follows from considerationssimilarto those under[2] thatonly every thirdpositive integeris a multiple of 3. So if an integer is a multiple of 3, then one more than it is not. A validatorwould need to assent to this. It is then implicit in [4] that3(3k2+ 2k) + 1 is the n2 mentionedin [3]. A validatorwould not have to notice this to comprehend [4], but would need to see it to comprehend[5]. By a validatorassentingto something,in this case that 3(3k2 + 2k) + 1 is not a multiple of 3, we mean that the validatoris conscious of agreeing with it. This conscious agreementmay be fleetingandnot focusedon, butit is distinctfrommere passive readingin inner speech. It may be the only conscious phenomenonassociated with a fairly complex inference.In this case, the validatormust have some knowledge of the relationshipbetweenmultiplesandmultiplesplus one to see that 3(3k2+ 2k) + 1 fits thatrelationshipandinfer that3(3k2+ 2k) + 1 is not a multiple of 3. While the assentingis conscious, the inferenceleading to it may occur very quickly and outsideof consciousness. It would be a validationerrorfor a validator to passively read, ratherthan assent to or reject, a portionof a proof, even if the proof were correct and the validatoragreed that it was correct. Such a validator would not have tested thatportionof the proof and could not really know that the proof was correct. [5] Now we will do the otherpossibility, 3k + 2. This assertionindicatesthatthe first subargumentis finished and that the second subargumentis beginning with the correct,but implicit, assumptionthatn = 3k + 2. [6] So, n2 = (3k + 2)2 = 9k2 + 12k + 4 = 3(3k2 + 4k + 1) + 1 is not a multipleof 3. All of the equationsare correct.The final assertiondependson the same informationused to justify [4] and should be assentedto by a validator.This statement concludes the second subargument. [7] Because n2 is not a multipleof 3, we have a contradiction.MThis statement is correct, assuming that it is a proof by contradiction.The implicit reasoningis that, according to [2], one of the two subarguments(cases) must apply to n2. Because both subargumentsyield that n2 is not a multiple of 3, there is a contradiction to the implicit assumptionthatn2 is a multipleof 3. If this argumentwere treated as a proof of the contrapositive, it would be peculiar to mention "the this final stepcould be omitted contrary"in [1]. However,underthatinterpretation, entirelyor replacedby "Thus,in eithercase, n2 is not a multipleof 3." We regard this argumentas a proof of the theorem,althoughit mightbe writtenmore clearly. If the role of n2 and the division into two independentsubarguments(cases) were AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 17 made explicit ratherthanimplicit in [2], [3], [4], [5], and [6], this proof would be less confusing for a validator,especially an inexperiencedone. "Proof(c)": The Gap PROOF. Let n be an integer such thatn2 = 3x wherex is an integer.Then 31n2 Since n2 = 3x, nn = 3x. Thus, 31n.Thereforeif n2 is a multiple of 3, then n is a multipleof 3. E Analysis of "Proof(c)" [1] Let n be an integer such that n2 = 3x where x is an integer. Except for the omission of the word "positive,"this representationis an appropriateway to begin a proof of this theorem.However, it is very abbreviated,and for mathematicsat this level, the argumentwould be more clearlylinkedto the theoremby supposing thatn2 is a multipleof 3 before claiming n2 = 3x, wherex is an integer. [2] Then31n2. This inferenceis correct,but not likely to be useful. It is read"3 divides n2"and is just anotherway of saying n2 = 3x, wherex is an integer,which was the suppositionin [1]. [3] Since n2= 3x, nn = 3x. The inferenceis not wrong,but it is stilljust the informationof [1] writtenin a slightly differentform. [4] Thus,31n.Read "3 divides n," this statementmeans thatn is a multipleof 3. Nothing in [1], [2], or [3] indicateswhy [4] should be true.Indeed,to fill the gap would amountto proving the theorem. [5] Thereforeifn2 is a multipleof 3, thenn is a multipleof 3. U This conclusion is just a restatementof the theorem. The argumentreally ends with [4]. If the reasoningfrom [1] to [4] were correct(which it is not), [5] would be true. In the genre of mathematicalproofs at and beyond the collegiate level, a theoremis not normallyrestatedat the end of an argumentpurportingto prove it. However, this sort of summarysentence can be found in sampleproofs in transitioncourse textbooks, especially when an argument for the contrapositive has been given (Velleman, 1994). "Proof(d)": The Converse PROOF. Let n be a positive integer such that n2 is a multiple of 3. Then n = 3m where m e Z+. So n2= (3m)2= 9m2= 3(3m2).This breaksdown into 3m times 3m which shows thatm is a multiple of 3. 0 Analysis of "Proof(d)" [ 1] Let n be a positive integersuch thatn2 is a multipleof 3. This representation andsuppositionis an appropriateway to begin provingthe theorem.Beginningthis way, the theoremwould be proved if the argumentled to n is a multipleof 3. [2] Thenn = 3m where m e Z+. Here Z+ representsthe set of positive integers. Statement[2] is incorrect.The meaningof multipleand [1] yields n2 = 3m, where 18 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered m e Z+, but [2] does not follow directlyfrom [1] (except by an applicationof the theorembeing proved). [3] So n2 = (3m)2= 9m2= 3(3m2).All threeequationsare correct,given [2]. [4] This breaksdown into 3m times 3m This statementfollows from [3]. [5] which shows thatm is a multipleof 3.E This inferencedoes not follow from [4] or anythingelse in the argument.The authorprobably"meant"thatn2, rather thanm, is a multipleof 3. When changed, [3] yields thatn2, not n, is a multipleof 3, which means the conversehas been proved(by [2], [3], [4], andthe altered[5]). All four of the undergraduatestudent-generatedargumentsabove correctly use a logical andrhetoricaldevice thatis particularlycommonin the genreof mathematical proofs. That is, to prove a theorem claiming some propertyabout all (each) of the elements in some set, for example, about all positive integers, it is sufficient to argue about a particular,but arbitrary,element of the set. In the language of secondary school algebra, one might say that the argumentis made about an unknown constant rather than a variable. Typically, the element is namedvery earlyin the argumentto avoid the possibilityof inadvertentlycompromising its arbitrariness.At the conclusion of the argument, it is implicit that whichever element of the set might be of interest,the argumentcould have been about that element. Although this rhetoricaldevice is simple, it is very powerful and simplifies the logic requiredof validators, thereby perhaps avoiding some errors.In the historical development of calculus, this device together with carefully formulated,analytic definitions (like the epsilon-delta definition of limit) allowed theoremsabout motion (for centuries a difficult concept) and, in particular, about rate of change, to have proofs in which nothing changes and motion is not mentioned. The textual analysis above differs from a descriptionof actual validations. It providesbackgroundinformationaboutthe theoremand the four "proofs"useful for understandingvalidationsof them. However, it does not include descriptions of actual validators' mental processes, abilities, missteps, and so on, in their attemptsto determinewhich of the argumentsarereally proofs. We now describe how some undergraduatemathematicsand mathematicseducationmajorsjudged whetherthese same four argumentswere proofs. THE EXPLORATORYSTUDY OF VALIDATION Eight undergraduates(four secondaryeducationmathematicsmajorsand four mathematicsmajors)at a comprehensivestateuniversityin the United Stateswere interviewed individually outside of class in the 4th and 5th weeks of a 15-week "bridge" or "transition to proofs" course. Although this course is normally studied in the 2nd or 3rd year at university, three of the eight students were in their4th year. The eight formed the entire cohort of this learning-to-prove-theorems course requiredof all mathematicsand secondary mathematicseducation majors at the institution.The goal of such courses, offered by many U.S. mathematics departments,is to help students make the transition from an earlier AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 19 traditionalcalculus sequence to later, more proof-basedcourses, such as abstract algebra and real analysis. They typically cover various aspects of logic; a little aboutsets, relations,andfunctions;proofby mathematicalinduction;andperhaps a few additionaltopics, such as elementarynumbertheory or introductorygraph theory, about which students are asked to prove theorems. The emphasis is on having studentslearnto make theirown proofs as opposedto the amountof mathematics covered. Kurtz'sFoundationsofAbstract Mathematics(1992), a typical textbook, was used in the course. In addition, students were to spend much of their class time, in pairs, proving theorems at the chalkboard.All eight students had taken single-variable calculus; some had also taken multivariablecalculus, differentialequations,matrixalgebra,or discretestructures.One student(referred to as BH) was concurrently enrolled in a dual-listed graduate/undergraduate numbertheory course. TheStructureof the Interviews Each studentwas interviewedindividuallyfor about 1 hourin a semistructured mannerusing an interview scriptconsisting of four phases. Phase 1. During this phase, which could be termed the warm-upphase, each studentwas given a brief fact sheet (see Appendix 1) and this writtenstatement: Forany positive integern, if n2 is divisible by 3, thenn is divisible by 3. They were asked to explain in their own words what the statementsaid, to give some examples of it, and to decide whetherit was true and how they would know. Finally, they were asked to give a proof of the statementif they could. Two successfully did so. After some time had elapsed, those who could not complete a proof were advisedthatthey need not continue,becauseprovingthe theoremwas not the point of the interview; rather,they were to judge the correctness of other students' "proofs"of the statement.Studentswere told thatsince some of the "proofs"they would see might seem a bit unusual,having attempteda proof would help them appreciatethe variety of approachestaken. Phase 2. Eachstudentwas shownthe four"proofs,"one afterthe other,andasked to think out loud as they read each one and decided whetherit was, or was not, a proof. If it was not a proof, they were to point out which part(s)were problematic. If theycould, they were to say where,or in whatways, the purportedproofhadgone wrong.They were also informedthatthese "proofs"had been submittedas partof a take-hometest in a previousyear by transition-coursestudentslike themselves. The four "proofs"were presentedto the studentsas they appearin Appendix2. They were told to take as long as they liked and seemed not to be hurried.For example,one student(JB) spent 15 minutesreadingandrereadingthe first"proof' before deciding (incorrectly)that it was indeed a proof, except for a minornotational error.Several of the studentsdid not want to commit themselves and were allowed duringthis phase to say thatthey were unsurewhethera given argument was, or was not, a proof. 20 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered Phase 3. Having seen andthoughtaboutall four "proofs"one afterthe other,the studentswere thengiven an opportunityto rereadthemall togetherandrethinktheir earlierdecisions with an opportunityto change theirminds, and some did. At the end of this phase,they werenot allowedto say thatthey wereunsure,butwere asked to make a decision and declarewhethereach argumentwas, or was not, a proof. Phase 4. Finally, the studentswere asked eight generalquestions aboutproofs and how they read,understand,and validateproofs. The data collected consisted of the audiotapedinterviews, the interviewer's notes, andthe students'workon the "proof' sheetsprovidedduringthe interview. (See Appendix 2 for details.) The Conductof the Interviews The interviews were treatedas "teachinginterviews."Not only was the interviewer the instructorfor the transitioncourse thatthe studentswere taking,it also seemed appropriateand opportuneto the interviewer-instructorto answer their implicit andexplicit questions.The interviewerwould respondgenerallyaboutthe structureor style of writtenproofsbutneverindicatewhetherthe fourspecific arguments thatthe studentswere examining were actuallyproofs of the theorem.This procedurekeptthe tone of the interviewsas relaxedandconversationalas possible. In addition, as the interviews proceeded, the students sometimes seemed to need encouragementto keep readingand thinkingaboutthe four "proofs."Thus, to obtain as much informationas possible, the interviewerintermittentlymade comments and answered or asked questions to keep students on task. All the studentsseemed to take the interviews seriously and seemed genuinely engaged with the task at hand. Informingstudentsof mathematicalpractices and norms.Keeping the students on task occasionally had the effect of suggesting to them practices and norms of the wider mathematicscommunity.In the following excerpt,studentMM hasjust begun to consider"Proof(a)"for the first time. She examines it silently for 1 minute, then asks whetheranother3 should be in the expression 3n(n + 2) + 1. With encouragementfromthe interviewer,she makesher suggestedcorrection,writing 9n2 + 6n + 1 = 3n(3n + 2) + 1. She then continues reading silently for an additional 30 seconds. Then, the following interchangeoccurs. MM. I don'tlikethisone 'causeit's confusing[laughs]. L OK,youdon'tlikeit.Inadditionto beingconfusingandnotlikingit-whichis a very goodreasonnotto likeit andwhichis whyI'mgoingto insistyouall [meaningthe studentsin thetransition class]writenonconfusing proofs[bothlaugh].OK? MM. There'sanerror. I: Ahh,there'sanerrorthere..... Let'spretendthe studentmeantto writethat[indi9n2+ 6n + 1 = 3n(3n+ 2) + 1].... catingMM'scorrection MM: OK. I: ... andsee if thatmakesa proof. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 21 The norm12 being suggestedhere is that stylistic clarity(i.e., writingproofs in a nonconfusingway) is valued,butthatlack of clarityin itself does not makean argument incorrect.In addition,it is impliedthroughthe overtact of correctingan algebraic errorthat small errorsin writtenproofs (e.g., those similarto misprints)can be fixed duringthe validationprocess. In the following example, studentST is in the midst of considering"Proof(a)." ST: Theyalsohaven2= (3n)2.Theyuse the samevariableforeverythingso it kindof throws(?) everythingtogether. [STandtheinterviewer agreeto fix thisby writingn2= (3m)2.] ST: I thinkthat'swhat,... that'swhat,... threwmeoff atthebeginningbecauseI was lookingat all thosen's tryingto equaleachother. intherethatyoudon't,uh,usethesame I: That'sreallyhard,isn'tit?There'sa principle letterto meantwo differentthingsin one proof.Youcanfinisha proof-and then the idea is finished-and thenuse the letterto meansomethingnew, but that's becausethere'sa breakin theideas. In this excerpt, ST comments on the confusion caused by using n in several differentways. The interviewercorroboratesthisandgives an additionalbit of informationregardingwhen it is permissibleto use the sameletter,suchas n, again.This, andothersimilarcommentsmadeduringthe interviews,hadtheeffect of introducing these studentsto some stylistic featuresof writtenproofs at the same time as the studentssaw (for themselves) a rationalefor those bits of mathematicalpractice. Furtherreflectionencouragedby the interviewer'sremarks.All studentswere kept on task by the interviewer'sdeliberateattemptsto probe their thinking.We illustratethis procedurewith comments from KC, a particularlyexpressive and responsivestudent.She told the interviewerthatshe ordinarilylikes to readproofs aloud to herself, that is, she had no problem converting inner speech to regular speech duringthe interview.Below is a condensed version of her first attemptat validating "Proof (d)." It proceeded along a tortuous sequence of meandering stages, numbered 1-8 below, apparentlyassisted by the interviewer's probing questions. (For the entiretranscript,see Appendix 3.) 1. KC readsthe entireproof aloud slowly once and remarksthat"Proof(d)"looks a lot like "Proof(a)" and says, "I thinkthat's a proof." 2. On being questioned by the interviewer who is genuinely surprisedby this analogy, she explains somethingabout 3(3m2) and tries to rewritethatportionof the proof, concentratingon the form she wants to see, "threetimes some integer." 3. After some time, the interviewerasks whetherthat is good enough for a proof 12This kind of norm (of the wider mathematical community)is reminiscentof sociomathematical norms,the negotiationof which has been investigatedin classroomsettings,for example, at the undergraduatelevel by Yackel, Rasmussen,andKing (2000). It would be interestingto investigatehow such normsaremaintainedand,in particular,adoptedby novices in the widermathematicalcommunity.The kinds of discussions associatedwith these interviewsmay not occuroften enough in universitycourses to explain the maintenanceof such norms. 22 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered now, andKC commentsthather wordingmay not be right.She andthe interviewer discuss this at some length and agree there are lots of equivalent ways to word things. 4. The interviewerthen asks whethershe has finished, and KC respondswith an explanation,". .. Let's see, they showed thatm was a multipleof 3 but they didn't show n was a multipleof 3." 5. She triesto substitutebackin andthen suddenlyblurtsout, "OK,wait, wait ...," followed by 30 secondsof intensesilentconcentration.She thenthumpsherpencil twice emphaticallyon the desk and asserts,"I don't thinkthat's a proof." 6. The interviewerasks why she changedher mind, and KC says, '"Theyshowed that m was a multipleof 3, but they didn't show n was a multipleof 3." 7. The interviewerthen asks, "Wheredid that m come from anyhow?"to which KC responds, ". .. they let n = 3m right up here.. ." [looking back to the beginning of the argument],and notes that they did not startin the right place, that is, n2 = 3m. 8. She reiterates,"I don't thinkthat's a proof." In respondingto the interviewerat stages (2), (3), (4), (6), and(7), KC is encouraged to reflectfurtheron "Proof(d)"andnotices featuresof the argumentthatwent undetected earlier. However, it is not easy to conjecturewhat happenedto KC during the 30 seconds of intense silent concentrationat stage (5). Her insight cannot reasonablybe attributedto anythingspecific that the interviewerdid; she appearsto have had somethinglike a genuine "Aha!"experience (Barnes,2000). It would be very interestingto know whatKC was consciousof duringthis experience. We suspect such an experience might be described immediatelyafter its occurrence,but is often not well rememberedlater.The interviewerdid question KC immediatelyaboutwhy she changed her mind, but not aboutthe contents of her conscious experience. To have done so might have considerablyalteredthe overall validationprocess. Overall Results On analyzing the data, it became clear that most students made a judgment regardingthecorrectnessof each"proof"atfourdifferenttimes,namely,atthebeginning and at the end of each of two readings(in Phases 2 and 3). These times were labeled Time 1 throughTime 4. All students,except JB, maintainedor increased the numberof theircorrectjudgmentsfromTime 1 to Time 4. (See Figure 1, which displays the changingnumberof correctjudgmentsby each studentacross time.) For example, KC graduallyimprovedfrom one correctjudgmentat Time 1 to four correctjudgmentsat Time 4. This improvementappearsto be the resultof further reflection. Eight studentswere interviewedregardingthe four "proofs,"making a total of 32 person-proofjudgments.Table 1 gives thepercentageof correctjudgmentsmade at the varioustimes. Annie Selden and John Selden 4 3 2 1 0 SD ' ST 23 JB BH I KC 1 RC ' MM ' SW Figure1. Thenumberof eachstudent'scorrectjudgmentsacrosstime(Time1 to Time4) Table1 Percentage and Numberof JudgmentsOver Time Correct Incorrect Unsure Time1 46%(15) 25%(8) 28%(9) Time2 56%(18) 28%(9) 16%(5) Time3 72%(23) 22%(7) 6%(2) Time4 81%(26) 18%(6) 0%(0) Note.Thetotalnumber ofjudgments was32. What happened over time that might have caused students to change their minds?Duringthe second phaseof the interview,betweenTime 1 andTime 2, the interviewerasked and answeredquestions,encouragingthe studentvalidatorsto reflect further.By the beginningof the thirdphase of the interview,they had seen and ponderedall four "proofs"and were more experienced.At Time 4, the interviewer would no longer accept "unsure,"and the studentsmade their final judgment for each "proof." At Time 1, less than half (46%) of the students'judgmentswere correct.This remarkablefact suggests that given this task on a test, where no one would have been encouragingthem to reflect further,the studentswould probablyhave done about as well by chance.3 They initially made the most correct judgments on "Proof(b)," with five correctlystatingthatit was a proof and threebeing unsure. They also initially made the fewest correctjudgments on "Proof(d)," with only two makingthe correctjudgmentand four incorrectlystatingit was a proof. This difficulty with "Proof(d)" supportsour observationbelow thatthe studentswere difficulties. primarilycheckinglocal detailsinsteadof looking for global/structural After the first sentence, "Proof (d)" can be regarded as an argument for the converse, modulo one notationalerror.The studentsalso seemed to be relying on theirfeelings of understandingin a way thatsometimesmisled them. StudentMM 13 Althoughthe students' ability to determinewhetherthese argumentswere proofs appearedto be very limited,we arenot claimingthis is unchangeable.Indeed,we saw some evidenceof improvedjudgments even duringthe course of the interviews and conjecturethatthe students'initial lack of ability was largely due to a lack of appropriateexperiences. 24 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered commentedabout "Proof(d)" that she "liked it" and could "see it betterthan the rest."Table 2 shows how the aggregatedstudents'judgmentson the fourpurported proofs changedover time. The entriesrepresentnumbersof students. Table2 Changes in the Patternof Judgments "Proof(a)" "Proof(b)" "Proof(c)" "Proof(d)" Correct Incorrect Unsure 4355 3433 1100 5678 0100 3110 4466 1112 3310 2557 4331 2000 Note. Entriesgive the numberof studentsresponding"correct,""incorrect,"or "unsure"at each of the four times. For example, under"Proof(a)" for Correct,therewere 4, 3, 5, and 5 correctjudgmentsat Time 1, Time 2, Time 3, and Time 4, respectively. A cleartrendcan be seen for "Proof(b)"and "Proof(d)";when comparingTime with Time 4, all students'judgmentsimprovedor stayedthe same. However,the 1 datafor "Proof(a)"and"Proof(c)" aremorecomplex. Forexample,on "Proof(a)" the improvementfrom four correctjudgmentsat Time 1 to five at Time 4 resulted from two studentschangingto correctjudgmentsand one studentchangingto an incorrectjudgment. In general,the studentsconsiderablyimprovedtheirjudgmentsover time (even though this was neither the purpose nor the expectation of the interviewer). Furthermore,this improvementseems largelyto have been due to interactionswith the interviewer that somehow enhanced the way that these students used the experiences and knowledge that they brought to the task. This phenomenon appears similar to occurrences in the zone of proximal development that were describedby Vygotsky (1978) in studyingthe sociocognitivedevelopmentof children. It would be interestingto know more about such student-interviewerinteractions when the interviewer'spurposewas to enhancea student'smathematical practices.Forexample, small portionsof these interviewsmightbe seen as dialectical situationsthatallowed the interviewerto suggest certainaspects of the practices and norms of the wider mathematicalcommunity. In other portions of the interviews, a small comment or question apparentlyinduced a studentto refocus his or her attentionon anotherpart of the task (i.e., on anotherpartof the argument being validated). Whatthe StudentsSaid as TheyCarriedOut Their Validations Most of the errors detected were of a local/detailed nature rather than a global/structuralnature.For example, in validating"Proof(a)," five students(JB, KC, SD, BH, ST) commentedon notationalerrorslike n2 = 9n2. Four (KC, SD, MM, ST) noted that odd/even was not correctlyexpressed in the symbolism, for example, 3n + 1 for odd. And two (BH, ST) observedthat divisibility by 3 could not be concluded in the odd case from the expression 3n(n + 2) + 1. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 25 Three students(KC, RC, MM) queriedthe interviewerregardingthe use of odd and even cases in "Proof(a)," but they were willing to continue their validation efforts aftermutuallyagreeingthat,althoughthis particularbreakdowninto cases might be peculiar,nothing was wrong with it logically. For example, studentRC read"Proof(a)" silently for 1 minuteandthenthe following interchangeoccurred. is howcantheysay RC: I didn't.... Itlookslikea proof.TheonlythingI'mquestioning it's oddor even.Canyou do that?[It]wouldseemthat..... It seemslike it would takecareof bothcases.... Thepositiveintegers.... I: Wewerejustbeginning to talkaboutthatinclass.... If youfeelyouwanttodosomeit's OK. thingby casesin a proof,as longas thecasescovereverything, RC: OK. But I: Sometimeslikethis,they[meaningtheoddandevencases]arenonoverlapping. Itdoesn'thurtto provesomethingtwiceaslongasthe theycanevenbe overlapping. unionof thecasescoverseverything. RC: It'skindof tricky.I wouldneverhavethoughtof that.Whatever's givenme,I tryto proveit. [RCcontinuesto considertheproofforsometime.] I: OKso, uh,if it's OKto do oddandeven,do youagreewithwhatthey'vedone?Is thata proof? RC: It lookslikeone. [Hethenexamines"Proof(b)."] StudentBH, who had successfully proved the theoremearlierin the interview aftera false start,thoughtthatthe conclusion in "Proof(a)" was being assumedin the even case. That is, she apparentlyignored [4] and wrongly interpreted[5] to includethe implicitsuppositionthatn = 3m. On readingfurther,she concludedthat the conversehad been proved.She stated" ... [they're]doing it the way I wanted to," suggesting thather initial failed attemptto prove the result influencedher to incorrectlysee her own misstep in the argument.Only BH and ST had succeeded in proving the theoremearlierin the interview;they were also the only students who correctlystatedthatthe converse had been shown in "Proof(d)."These sorts of structuralcomments were rare. Thus, as one might expect, the experience of provinga theoremcan havepositiveeffects on subsequentvalidationsof otherarguments for the same theorem.And, perhapscounterintuitively,such earlierexperiences can sometimeshave negativeeffects on validations,as describedabove when BH seems to have been more influencedby an early false starton a proof thanby her later success. Whatthe StudentsSaid TheyDid WhenReading Proofs Most students seemed content to attempt a careful line-by-line check to see whether each mathematicalassertion followed from previous assertions.When queried (in Phase 4) about what they do when readinga proof, the studentssaid they did manythings:They made sureall steps were logical andlooked to see that everythingwas supported.They checked the computationsand whetheranything was left out. They said, "[I] take it step by step; [I] like to read it real slow" and "I go throughmore than once. ... See if from step to step, it follows." Several 26 as Texts Validations of ProofsConsidered studentssaid thatthey would try to go througha proof with an example, but few gave evidence of doing so duringtheir validations. KC, whose validationof "Proof(d)"was paraphrasedabove, said, "[It's]not like readinga newspaper;moreunderstandingis involved.I go throughmorethanonce. Somethingwill come out at me thatdidn'tthe firsttime."Whenqueriedabouthow she tells thata proof is not correct,KC explained,"becausethey didn't show it and they didn't say it [meaningthe conclusion]."She added,"PlusI expect to see the steps thatsay, thatlead you up to n is ... or whatever."She furtherexplained,"And also if you find somethingthatgoes, ... that,that, .... that is definitely wrong in the stepsabove.Like the one up here [pointingto one of the four"proofs"].So that's not ... [a proof]."Given KC's limitedexperiencewith validatingproofs,otherthan those in textbooks, this final remarkaboutfinding somethingdefinitely wrong in just one step seems quitereasonable.However,in the odd case of "Proof(a),"there are four mistakes thatare extraneousto obtainingn2 is divisible by 3 from itself. (See the textualanalysisabove.)In general,the students'self-descriptionssounded thoroughand competent. MakingSense as a Criterionfor DeterminingCorrectnessof Proofs In general,for these students,a feeling of understanding or not-that is, of making sense or not-seemed to be an importantcriterionwhen makingajudgment about the correctnessof these four "proofs."For them, it seemed a questionof whether the writtentext, togetherwiththeireffortsat comprehension,engendereda personal feeling of understanding.For example, afterinitially readingthrough"Proof(a)" slowly, JB concentratedon the last statement,n2 = 9n2, reiteratingseveral times that it did not make sense. Then he said, "I'm saying I don't think this is a proof because it [n2 = 9n2] doesn't make sense." After the interviewersuggested that perhapsthe authorhad meant to write n2 = 9m2,JB concurredand continuedhis validationattemptfor some time, finally deciding incorrectlyit was a proof "after variablerenaming."Althoughthejudgmentwas incorrect,it is clearthatJB's main focus was on making sense, perhapsresiding in the form of some conscious, but unarticulated,feeling of understanding. When KC first came to the gap in "Proof(c)," she rereadthe argumentseveral times and tried to expandon it (on paper).When she could not, she explainedher thinkingto the interviewer,as follows. KC: MaybeI just don'tunderstand theconceptof... I ... ,I understand 3 dividesn2 I understand all thatstuff,butI don't... I don't... I understand gettingfromhere ... [from]there[n2= 3x]to there[nn= 3x],but fromhere[nn= 3x]to here[31n].... I: Uh,huh.So whenyoutriedto fill it outyoucouldn'tbasically? [KCagreesandsaysshecouldprobablygive anexample,butthatis nota proof.] KC: I stilldon'tthinkthat,... thatis... [aproof].I don'tknow.I don'tthinkthatis... [aproof]. I: So that'snota proof? KC: ButI maydecidelater... [reserving therightto rethinktheargument]. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 27 At this point, a sense of not understandingmakes KC cautious about whether the argumentis a proof.Anotherstudent,MM, in summingup herfinaljudgments, wrote under "Proof (c)" that it was not a proof and "I don't understandthe reasoning."Then, under"Proof(d)," she wrote an asteriskfollowed by "Proofthis one is the easiest for me to understand."However,this argumentis not a proof of the theorem,but rathera proof of its converse. In her case, a feeling of understandingdid not mean the argumentwas correctlylinked (via a proof framework) to the theorem. The studentsalso indicated(in Phase 4) thatthey usually readproofsfor understanding.StudentBH, who was takingnumbertheoryconcurrently,said "It's got to be truebut got to make sense. Lastnight I was lost 20 minutesin numbertheory. I found somebody's thesis in the library.Just one step [was missing].... " This comment suggests that the feeling of making sense, or of understanding,is a matterof considerableimportanceto BH-important enough to search through theses in the library.StudentKC, commentingon her previouscalculustextbook, said, "Someof the proofs in the calc book were 'off the wall.' I had to sit andwrite them up; [I had to] go home and see where the things were coming from." For these students,understandingwas requiredof them when readingproofs. When given a proof by an instructoror in a textbook, they quite reasonably assumed that it was correct.Indeed, they probablyhad very little previouspractice in decidingwhether"proofs"arecorrect,thatis, in validation.Thus,theyappear to have dependedon theirwiderpersonalexperiencesof understanding,which did not always serve them well in validation.This unreliabilitymay occur because a feeling of understandingitself and one's tendencyto rely on it are influencedand sharpenedby experiencesin validation-experiences these studentslargelylacked. Also, althoughthe studentsspoke of understandingquite freely, they apparently did not always mean more or less the same thing by it. Their responses to questionsin Phase4, togetherwiththeirvalidationattempts,suggestthattheyhada range of meanings for understandingfrom verifying shortcomputationsin a text using their own proceduralknowledge to a feeling of understandingassociated with a gestalt view of an entireargument.Perhapsthis variationis due to a generaldifficulty in negotiatingmeaningfor conceptssuchas understanding,which do not refer to underlyingphysical objects (e.g., cars or basketballs). CONCLUSIONSAND IMPLICATIONSFOR TEACHING What studentssay about how they read proofs seems to be a poor indicatorof whetherthey can actuallyvalidateproofs with reasonablereliability.They tendto "talka good line." They say thatthey check proofs step by step, follow arguments logically, generate examples, and make sure the ideas in a proof make sense. However, their first readingjudgments(see Table 1, Time 1) yield no betterthan chance results, suggesting thatthey cannotreliably implementtheir intentions. On the other hand, even without explicit instruction,the reflection and reconsiderationengenderedby the interview process eventually yielded 81% correct 28 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered judgments (see Table 1, Time 4). This improvementsuggests that instructionin validationcould be effective. The interviewsalso suggest that studentsshouldbe errors,forexample,proving encouragedto attendmoreto possibleglobal/structural the converseof the statement.In particular,studentsneedto devoteattentionto what we have called proof frameworks(Selden & Selden, 1995), a topic thatwe suspect is relatively easy to masterbecause it does not dependon a deep understandingof the mathematicalconcepts involved in the statementof a theorem. Validationof proofs is partof the implicit curriculum,but it is a largely invisible mentalprocess.Few universityteacherstryto teachit explicitly,althoughsome may admonishstudentsto "readwith pencil and paperin hand"or the like. This advice is at best descriptive,butcertainlynot usefullyprescriptive,so studentstend to interpretsuchvaguedirectionsidiosyncratically,spottingmainlylocal notational and computationaldifficulties. They appear to be substitutingtheir feeling of overall understanding,plus a focus on surfacefeatures,for validation.We suspect such a feeling of overall understandingis useful and reliable for mathematicians who will have includedin it theirnotionof correctness,but is often unreliableand misleading for students. "Bridge"courses in the United States tend to give students some idea of the logical structureof theorems,coveringsuch topics as directandindirectproofsand indicatingthatthe converseis not logically equivalentto a theorem.These courses also cover some logic, set theory, functions, and assortedothertopics. Often, the materialon logic precedes studentwork with proofs, and perhapsfor thatreason, tends to be presentedin an abstract,decontextualizedway that may not be very effective. Textbooks for such courses have from none to just a few to a moderate numberof exercises that involve the critiquingof "proofs."The directionsvary; studentsmay be askedto (a) find the fallacy in a "proof';(b) tell whethera "proof' is correct;(c) gradea "proof,"A for correct,C for partiallycorrect,or F; or (d) evaluatebotha "proof'anda "counterexample." Most of these "proofs"havebeen carefully constructedby textbook authors so there is just one error to detect. For example,in Smith,Eggen, andSt. Andre(1990; p. 39) we find the following "proof to grade": Suppose m is an integer. Claim. If m2 is odd, then m is odd. "Proof." Assume m is odd. Then m = 2k + 1 for some integerk. Therefore,m2 = (2k + 1)2= 4k2+ 4k + 1 = 2(2k2+ 2k) + 1, which is odd. Therefore,if m2is odd, then m is odd. E The "proof'above does not presenta studentwith anywherenearthe complexity or kindsof difficultiesseen in our student-generated Considerationof arguments.'4 such contrived"proofs"is no doubtvaluablepracticefor those beginningto learn validation.However, we suggest that additionalpracticein validatingsuch actual 14The Smith, Eggen, and St. Andretextbook (1990), and subsequenteditions thereof,does contain more complex "proofsto grade,"however, many transitioncourse textbooksdo not. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 29 student"proofs"as those in this study,togetherwith small-groupdiscussion,could be beneficial,especially for preservicesecondaryteacherswho one day may need tojudge the correctnessof theirown students'proofsor novel solutionsto problems. FUTURERESEARCHQUESTIONS One might consider the studentsin our empiricalstudy as novices at validation and ask what experts-advanced undergraduates,graduatestudents,and mathematicians-would do. The studentsin our study could not reliably validaterelatively shortpurportedproofsof a simpletheorem,but mathematicianscan. At some point, therefore,mathematicsstudentslearnto do so. When does this happen,and throughwhat kinds of experiences is the process of validationlearned? Proofs of the theorem used in this study do not seem to have a very complex structure.What would happen if one considered a theorem whose proof was inherentlymorecomplex or wherethe potentialfor moresubtleerrorswas greater? Studentsoften have views of proof (Harel & Sowder, 1998) thatdiffer markedly from mathematicians'views. How would such views be influenced by attempts to increase students' ability to validate proofs? How does the ability to validate proofs relate to the ability to constructthem? How does it relate to a knowledge of logic, especially when taught in the rather formal,symbolic, decontextualizedway thatis found in many transitioncourses? What are students' perceived and actual criteria for correctness, for example, thatthey agree the calculations are legitimate, thatthey can follow the argument line by line, that they can see why the argumentbegins where it does, and so on? The students in this study were sometimes misled by a feeling of overall understanding, whereas mathematicians can use such feelings beneficially. What accounts for the difference? How does one learn to have a feeling at the "righttime" and not otherwise?Whatpartsof validationsconsist of readingplus assent, without additionalconscious experiences, such as inner speech or vision or feeling? What kind of teaching might promote a correct use of assent during validation? Here, after introducingthe idea of validation,we discussed its naturein a way thatdependedon informationwe taketo be commonknowledgeamongmost mathematicians.However, withoutadditionalinvestigations,thereis no way to be sure that we are right about what is common knowledge or that the common knowledge itself is correct.Taking much of this discussion as partlyconjecturalyields a numberof additionalresearchquestions. For example, suppose one recorded what was being attendedto during the constructionof a proof and extracted,in order, those parts that appearedin its final form. Would this order, as we have suggested, differ greatly from the orderof the final proof? In teaching, one of us has sometimesencouragedstudentsto write a proof framework,thatis, the beginning andending few lines of a proof, before attemptingthe middle. Some students resist this advice, and it would be interestingto investigatewhethersuch students have more difficulty constructingproofs than others. 30 Validations as Texts of ProofsConsidered We have also alludedto mathematicians'ability to agree on the correctnessof proofs and the truthof theoremsand that they can often decide this individually and believe "you do not vote on the truthof theorems."It would be interestingto investigatethe degreeto which these arethe perceptionsof mathematiciansas well as the degree to which those perceptions are accurate.Informationabout such perceptions and abilities might enhance the role played by validation in social constructivistviews of mathematics. Last, what is a good way to teach validation?Is it a concept like proof or definition, which is perhaps best learned through experiences, such as finding and discussing errorsin actualstudent"proofs"? REFERENCES Baddeley, A. (1995). Workingmemory. In M. S. Gazzaniga(Ed.), Thecognitive neurosciences (pp. 755-764). Cambridge,MA: MIT Press. Bagchi, A., & Wells, C. (1998). Varietiesof mathematicalprose. PRIMUS,8, 116-136. Barnes, M. (2000). 'Magical' momentsin mathematics:Insightsinto the process of coming to know. For the Learningof Mathematics,20(1), 33-43. Bogdan,D., & Straw,S. B., (Eds.). (1990). Beyondcommunication:Readingcomprehensionand criticism. Portsmouth,NH: Heinemann. Burton, L., & Morgan, C. (2000). Mathematicianswriting. Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education,31, 429-453. Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntacticstructures.The Hague, Netherlands:Mouton. Cuoco, A. (2001). Mathematicsfor teaching. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 48, 168-174. De Villiers, M. (1998). To teach definitions in geometry or teach to define? In A. Olivier & K. Newstead (Eds.), Proceedingsof the 22nd conferenceof the InternationalGroupfor thePsychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 2, pp. 248-255). Stellenbosch, South Africa: University of Stellenbosch. Dubinsky, E., & Yiparaki,O. (2000). On studentunderstandingof AE and EA quantification.In E. Dubinsky,A. H. Schoenfeld, & J. Kaput(Eds.), Issues in mathematicseducation: Vol. 8. Research in collegiate mathematicseducation. IV (pp. 239-289). Providence,RI: AmericanMathematical Society. Edwards,B. (1997). An undergraduatestudent'sunderstandinganduse of mathematicaldefinitionsin real analysis. In J. A. Dossey, J. O. Swafford, M. Parmantie,& A. E. Dossey (Eds.), Proceedings of the nineteenthannual meetingof the NorthAmericanChapterof theInternationalGroupfor the PsychologyofMathematicsEducation(Vol. 1, pp. 17-22). Columbus,OH:The ERICClearinghouse for Science, Mathematics,and EnvironmentalEducation. Ernest,P. (1998). Social constructivismas a philosophy ofmathematics.Albany,NY: StateUniversity of New York Press. Fillmore,C. J. (1968). The case for case. In E. Bach & R. T. Harms(Eds.), Universalsof linguistictheory (pp. 1-88). New York:Holt, Rinehart,and Winston. Freudenthal,H. (1973). Mathematicsas an educational task. Dordrecht,The Netherlands:D. Reidel. Halliday,M. A. K. (1977). Explorationsin thefunctions of language. New York:Elsevier. Hanna, G. (1989). Proofs that prove and proofs that explain. In G. Vergnaud, J. Rogalski, & M. Artigue(Eds.),Proceedingsof the thirteenthconferenceof theInternationalGroupforthePsychology of MathematicsEducation(Vol. 2, pp. 45-51). Paris:CNRS-Paris V. Harel, G., & Sowder, L. (1998). Students'proof schemes: Results from exploratorystudies. In A. H. Schoenfeld, J. Kaput,& E. Dubinsky(Eds.), Issues in mathematicseducation: Vol. 7. Research in collegiate mathematics education. III (pp. 234-283). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society. Kintsch,W. (1974). The representationof meaning in memory.Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Annie Selden and John Selden 31 Kurtz,D.C. (1992). Foundationsof abstractmathematics.New York:McGraw-Hill. Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematicaldiscovery. Cambridge,UK: CambridgeUniversityPress. Leron,U. (1983). Structuringmathematicalproofs. TheAmericanMathematicalMonthly,90, 174-184. Morgan, C. (1996). The language of mathematics:Towards a critical analysis of mathematicstexts. For the Learningof Mathematics,16(3), 2-10. NationalCouncilof Teachersof Mathematics.(2000). Principlesand standardsforschool mathematics. Reston, VA: Author. Nystrand,M., Doyle, A., & Himley, M. (1986). A criticalexaminationof the doctrineof autonomous texts. In M. Nystrandwith M. Himley & A. Doyle (Eds.), Thestructureof writtencommunication: Studiesin the reciprocitybetweenwritersand readers (pp. 81-109). Orlando,FL: AcademicPress. Olson, D. R. (1977). From utteranceto text: The bias of language in speech and writing. Harvard EducationalReview, 47, 257-281. Pearson,P. D. (2000). Reading in the twentiethcentury.In T. L. Good & M. Early (Eds.), American education: Yesterday,today, and tomorrow(Ninety-ninthyearbookof the NationalSociety for the Study of Education,Part2, pp. 152-208). Chicago: Universityof Chicago Press. Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca,L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation(J. Wilkinson& P. Weaver,Trans.).Notre Dame, IN: Universityof Notre Dame Press. (Originalwork published 1958) Pimm, D. (1984). Who is 'we'? MathematicsTeaching, 107, 39-42. Rasmussen,C., & Zandieh,M. (2000). Defining as a mathematicalactivity: A realistic mathematics analysis. In M. L. Fern4ndez(Ed.), Proceedings of the 22nd annual meetingof the NorthAmerican Chapter of the International Groupfor the Psychology of MathematicsEducation (Vol. 1, pp. 301-305). Columbus,OH:The ERICClearinghousefor Science, Mathematics,andEnvironmental Education. Rodd,M. (2000). On mathematicalwarrants:Proofdoes not always warrant,anda warrantmay be other than a proof. MathematicalThinkingand Learning,2, 221-244. Rowland,T. (2002). Genericproofs in numbertheory.In S. R. Campbell& R. Zazkis (Eds.), Learning and teaching numbertheory:Research in cognition and instruction(pp. 157-183). Westport,CT: Ablex Publishing. Schoenfeld, A. H. (1985). Mathematicalproblem solving. Orlando,FL: Academic Press. Selden, A., & Selden, J. (1987). Errorsand misconceptionsin college level theoremproving.In J. D. Novak (Ed.), Proceedings of the second internationalseminar on misconceptionsand educational strategies in science and mathematics(Vol. III, pp. 457-470). Ithaca,NY: CornellUniversity. Selden, J., & Selden, A. (1995). Unpackingthe logic of mathematicalstatements.EducationalStudies in Mathematics,29, 123-151. Selden, A., Selden, J., Hauk,S., & Mason, A. (2000). Why can't calculus studentsaccess theirknowledge to solve non-routineproblems?In A. H. Schoenfeld., J. Kaput,& E. Dubinsky, (Eds.), Issues in mathematicseducation: Vol. 8. Research in collegiate mathematicseducation.IV (pp. 128-153). Providence,RI: AmericanMathematicalSociety. Sierpinska,A., Defence, A., Khatcherian,T., & Saldanha,L. (1997). A proposde troismodes de raisonnement en alghbrelindaire [Three modes of reasoning in linear algebra]. In J.-L. Dorier (Ed.), L'enseignementde l'alghbre lindaire en question (pp. 259-268). Grenoble, France: La Pens6e Sauvage. Smith,D., Eggen, M., & St. Andre,R. (1990). A transitionto advancedmathematics(3rded.). Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole. Tall, D., & Vinner,S. (1981). Conceptimage andconcept definitionwith particularreferenceto limits and continuity.EducationalStudies in Mathematics,12, 151-169. Thompson,D. R. (1996). Learningand teachingindirectproof. MathematicsTeacher,89, 474-482. Toulmin, S. (1958). The uses of argument.Cambridge,UK: CambridgeUniversityPress. Vachek, J. (1966). The linguistic school of Prague: An introduction to its theory and practice. Bloomington, IN: IndianaUniversityPress. Validationsof Proofs Consideredas Texts 32 Velleman,D. J. (1994). How toprove it:A structuredapproach.Cambridge,UK: CambridgeUniversity Press. Vinner,S. (1997). Fromintuitionto inhibition-Mathematics, education,andotherendangeredspecies. In E. Pehkonen (Ed.), Proceedings of the 21st conference of the International Groupfor the PsychologyofMathematicsEducation(Vol. 1, pp.63-78). Helsinki,Finland:Universityof Helsinki, Departmentof TeacherEducation. Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mindin society: Thedevelopmentofhigherpsychological processes (M. Cole, V. John-Steiner,S. Scribner,& E. Souberman,Eds.). Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversityPress. Yackel, E., Rasmussen,C., & King, K. (2000). Social and sociomathematicalnorms in an advanced undergraduatemathematicscourse. Journal of MathematicalBehavior, 19, 275-287. Authors Annie Selden, TennesseeTechnologicalUniversity,MathematicsDepartment,Box 5054, Cookeville, TN 38505; selden@tntech.edu John Selden, MathematicsEducation Resources Company, 1015 Melrose Drive, Cookeville, TN 38501; js9484@usit.net APPENDIX 1 Facts Aboutthe Positive Integers FACT 1. The positive integers,B can be dividedup into threekindsof integersthose of the form 3n for some integern, those of the form 3n + 1 for some integer n, and those of the form 3n + 2 for some integern. For example, 1, 2, 3, 4, 3n 3n+1 where n = 1 6, 5, 7, 3n+2 3n 3n+1 where n = 2 8, 3n+2 9, 10, 11... FACT 2. Integersof the form3n (thatis, 3, 6, 9, 12, .. .) arecalled multiplesof 3. FACT 3. No integercan be of two of these kinds simultaneously.So m is not a multipleof 3 means the same as m is of the form 3n + 1 or 3n + 2. APPENDIX 2 InterviewData Collection Phases PHASE 1: Warm-UpExercises For any positive integer n, if n2 is a multipleof 3, then n is a multipleof 3. 1. Explain, in your own words, what the above statementsays. 2. Give some examples of the above statement. AnnieSeldenandJohnSelden 33 3. Does the above statementseem to be true?How do you tell? 4. Do you thinkyou could give a proof of the above statement? PHASE2: Sequentialconsiderationof 'Proofs' (a), (b), (c), (d). PHASE3: 'Recap' on the 'Proofs' Below are several purportedproofs of the following statement: For any positive integer n, if n2 is a multipleof 3, then n is a multipleof 3. For each one, decide whetheror not it is a proof. Try to "thinkout loud" so you can let me in on your decision process. If it is not a proof, point out which part(s) are problematic.If you can, say where, or in what ways, the purportedproof has gone wrong. Assume thatn2 is an odd positive integerthatis divisible by 3. Thatis (a). PROOF: n2= (3n + 1)2= 9n2+ 6n + 1 = 3n(n+ 2) + 1. Therefore,n2is divisibleby 3. Assume that n2 is even and a multiple of 3. That is n2 = (3n)2 = 9n2 = 3n(3n). Therefore, n2 is a multipleof 3. If we factorn2 = 9n2, we get 3n(3n); which means thatn is a multipleof 3. E (b). PROOF: Suppose to the contrarythatn is not a multipleof 3. We will let 3k be a positive integerthatis a multipleof 3, so that3k + 1 and 3k + 2 are integersthat are not multiplesof 3. Now n2 = (3k + 1)2= 9k2+ 6k + 1 = 3(3k2+ 2k) + 1. Since 3(3k2+ 2k) is a multipleof 3, 3(3k2+ 2k) + 1 is not. Now we will do the otherpossibility, 3k+ 2. So, n2= (3k+ 2)2 = 9k2+ 12k+ 4 = 3(3k2+ 4k + 1) + 1 is not a multiple of 3. Because n2 is not a multipleof 3, we have a contradiction.U Let n be an integersuch thatn2 = 3x wherex is any integer.Then 31n2 (c). PROOF: Since n2= 3x, nn = 3x. Thus3In.Thereforeif n2is a multipleof 3, thenn is a multiple of 3. M Let n be a positive integersuch thatn2 is a multipleof 3. Then n = 3m (d). PROOF: where m e Z+. So n2= (3m)2= 9m2= 3(3m2).This breaksdown into 3m times 3m which shows thatm is a multipleof 3. M PHASE4. Final Questions 1. When you read a proof is there anythingdifferentyou do, say, than in reading a newspaper? 2. Specifically, what do you do when you read a proof? 3. Do you check every step? 4. Do you read it more thanonce? How many times? 5. Do you make small subproofsor expand steps? 6. How do you tell when a proof is corrector incorrect? 7. How do you know a proof proves this theoreminsteadof some othertheorem? 8. Why do we have proofs? Validationsof Proofs Consideredas Texts 34 APPENDIX 3 Transcript of KC Validating "Proof (d)" [Note: Segmentation into stages is our own. Emphases in boldface indicate portions of the transcript discussed earlier in the condensed version.] Initial validation attempt in Phase 2 Stage 1 I: OK, this is the last one. We have four of these. KC: OK. [Reads theorem aloud slowly once. There's a pause at the end of the first sentence, after which she says "OK"and goes on reading.]Yah. That, that looks a lot like the one thatwe just did. I: Ahh, which means it's good or it's not good? KC: Yah. No, notjust did. I mean this one over here [pointingto the paperwith (a)]. I: Oh, it looks like. ... [Spreadsout the fourpaperswith the 'proofs'on them.] We had (a), (b), (c), (d). KC: Like thatone. Like thatone. [Pointingto (a).] It looks like.... It looks a lot like the, ah, (a) one. I: KC: Yah.Yah,I thinkthat'sa proof. Stage 2 OK.OK.You thinkthisone's a proof.Ookay. I: KC: 'Cause,see, 'causethis is whatI was talkingaboutby 3 times3m2. I: KC: I: KC: Ah, OK. Then you could let this 3m2be some integerk. OK. So you want to see this displayedlike that? Yah. I: OK. KC: Then you could say thatlike... I: Well, I don't want to have it upside down [turnspaperaround]. KC: You could also ... say ... this breaksdown. Well, this one. ... WhatI would do, is say, uhm, uhm 3 ... then, 3m2equals to k, some integerk such that3k, or something like, equals to 3k, uhm.... I: [Interrupting]Why don't you write thatdown? Your talkinghere. KC: OK. You need your pencil then. I: KC: Like here, I probablywould say [writes and talks more slowly]. Let 3m2equal to k, for some positive integerk... [pause] ... integerk. OK. Uhm. [long pause] Then 3 times 3m would equal to 3k... [pause] which ... [pause]makes, uhm, or I don't know the wordingmay have to be wrong,uhm, which makes,uhm ... [pause]which is ... ,I don't know how to say it, but that's.... That's what you wantedto say. I: KC: See that's whatI wantto say, andthen, like, insertit in here.Then you could say that this, by proving that it's three times some integer, some .... Then you could say that it's now ... I: It's now a multipleof 3. [Finishes sentence for KC.] Annie Selden and John Selden 35 Yah, it's now a multipleof 3, OK. [Says and writes] Now n2 is a multiple of 3. Uh, huh. I don't know if I'd word it in thatway, but that's what I'm thinking. Thatn2 is a multiple of 3? I don't know if I'd word it in thatway. 'Cause then you have it in the form three times something else.... Because this breakingdown to 3m times 3m, uh that,thatkindof... becauseyou have this already. I: Uh, hmm. KC: Do you understandwhat, what I'm saying? KC: I: KC: I: KC: KC: Stage 3 I: Yah. Yah. I understandyou want to get it displayedlike that.Uhm, and that's good enough for a proof now? KC: Now, my wordingrighthere probablyis wrong , I mean it could be.... I: There's lots of differentways you can word things .... [Continuesfor some time.] KC: I mean.I mean.I could. ... A lot of this could be like... Even this could be reworded. You don't have to say "let"orjust say, you know, k, uhm, for some integerk equals, or something,orjust let this be somethingelse. So you could have it in the form.... Or even that's fine. But, this 3m times 3m stuff, that's gotta go. Stage 4 I: Then, how do you know you're finished with? I mean.... KC: [Interrupts] Because,becauseyou have it now, now you have it. ... [Longpause]Let's see. They showed that m was a multiple of 3, but they didn't show that n was a multiple of 3. [Long pause] 'Cause you have to show thatn is a multipleof 3. Stage 5 I: Uh, huh. KC: Uhmmm.[Longpause] Hmmm.[Longpause] So you'd have to go back and you'd have to substitute back in here. [Writes(3m)(3m)= (3m)n = 3(mn).] I: Uh, huh. KC: Anyway that .... [Longpause]Well, it would. ... OK, wait. OK, wait, wait. .... Then you'd have .... Let's see ... [long silence, lasting 30 seconds]. Well, [taps pencil quicklytwice, andagainquicklytwice] ... [pause]I don't think that's a proof [said definitely]. Stage6 I: Oh! [surprised]Oh, OK. [KC laughs.] Now why did you change your mind? KC: Well, because they didn't, they didn't say ... thatn was ... they didn't say n was a multiple of 3. They didn't figure that out. They showed that m was a multiple of 3, but they didn't show that n was ... and.... Stage I: KC: I: 7 [Interrupting]Where'd that m come from anyhow? Well, the m came from.., they let n = 3m right up here [pointingto top of proof]. Yah. KC: Justto, just to to... I: That'sjust like your using k, as far as I can tell. 36 Validationsof Proofs Consideredas Texts KC: See, you're, and ... they're supposedto have let n2 be a multipleof 3, so it should have been "let n2 = 3m." Stage 8 I. Uh, hmm. KC: So. ... So, at leastI showedyou how I was, ... I wouldhave worded.... [Bothlaugh.] I don't think that's a proof. I: OK this one's not a proof. OK, that's one's not a proof. OK, we can come back and change our minds. Subsequent "recap" validation attempt in Phase 3 KC: [Reads "proof' aloud, followed by a pause of 18 seconds.] No. I: Not a proof? KC: No, because they still, I mean, they didn't define ... they didn't prove what the n was, which is what they were supposedto prove. I: So they didn't prove what they were supposedto prove. Which was what? KC: That,thatn is a multipleof 3. I: Uh, hmm.. . . OK.