Philosophy of Science: Scientific Reasoning Kristina Rolin 2012 Scientific knowledge? Put empirical evidence into a large mixing bowl. Add reasoning and rhetorical spices. Mix and pour the filling into a journal paper crust. Bake until the pie is ready for the social practice of epistemic justification. 1 A scientific paper or monograph should include an argument. An argument is not the same as the table of contents in a paper or a monograph (introduction, background, method, data, discussion of data, conclusion). What is an argument? What is a good argument? Argument An argument includes premises and the conclusion (or the main thesis). The premises provide reasons to believe that the conclusion is true (or likely to be true). An argument aims to answer the question: Why should we believe or accept the main thesis? 2 Explanation An explanation includes an explanandum (a description of an event or a state of affairs that is to be explained) and the explanans (an account that provides an explanation). The explanans provides an account of at least some of the causes that have led to the event or the state of affairs to be explained. An explanation aims to answer the question: Why did something happen or why does a certain state of affairs prevail? Esimerkki Kumpi on argumentti, kumpi selitys? Perustele vastaus. (A) Liisa on rikkonut kesämökin ikkunan, koska vain hänen jalanjälkensä näkyvät lumessa. (B) Liisa on rikkonut kesämökin ikkunan, koska hänellä ei ollut avainta mukana, eikä se ollut tavanomaisessa paikassa oven päällä. Kakkuri-Knuuttila, Marja-Liisa (toim.) 1999. Argumentti ja Kritiikki: Lukemisen, Keskustelun ja Vakuuttamisen Taidot. Helsinki: Gaudeamus. 3 Good argument? A good argument should fulfill the following four criteria: (1) Premises are true or acceptable. (2) Premises are relevant to the main thesis. (3) There is a link between the premises and the main thesis. (4) The link is not undermined by further information. Two categories of arguments The link between the premises and the conclusion can be (1) binding or (2) less than binding. If the link is binding, the conclusion follows from the premises (e.g., deductive arguments). If the link is less than binding, the premises support the conclusion (e.g., inductive arguments). 4 Deductive argument: an example Premise #1: If Riitta is a student, then Riitta is intelligent. Premise #2: Riitta is a student. Conclusion: Riitta is intelligent. A deductive argument claims that if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true. A semi-formal representation of the argument If p, then q. p. Therefore, q. The argument is valid in virtue of its logical structure. If the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true (and this is the case for any proposition p and q). 5 Deductive argument: an example All human beings are mortal. Socrates is a human being. Therefore, Socrates is mortal. For every x it is the case that if x is H, then x is M. S is H. Therefore, S is M. Inductive argument: an example Premise #1: Most students at the School of Economics are from the metropolitan area. Premise #2: Matti is a student at the School of Economics. The conclusion: Matti is from the metropolitan area. An inductive argument claims that if the premises are true, then the conclusion is likely to be true. 6 Simple inductive reasoning: an example Swan #1 is white, swan #2 is white, swan # 3 is white…. Therefore, all swans are white. Statistical generalization: an example x is a sample of 1000 randomly chosen Finnish citizens. 12 % of the persons in the sample x are lefthanded. Therefore, 12 % of all Finnish citizens are lefthanded. 7 Validity in logic An argument is valid if and only if it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. A valid deductive argument is necessarily truth-preserving. Validity is all-or-nothing type of property; it does not come in degrees. We can have a valid argument with false premises and a false conclusion. We can also have a valid argument with false premises and a true conclusion. Inductive arguments In an inductive argument it is possible that the premises are true and the conclusion is false. Inductive arguments are not necessarily truthpreserving. Inductive arguments come in different degrees of strength. 8 Good argument? An argument is sound if and only if it is valid and its premises are true. A good argument does not need to be sound. In a good argument, the premises are acceptable and they provide sufficient support to the main thesis. What counts as ”sufficient” depends on the context. Examples of bad arguments Argumentum ad hominem appeals to a premise which concerns the person who presents the argument and which is not relevant to the conclusion. Petitio principii is a circular argument (“begging the question”). Non sequitur is an argument which gives reasons for another conclusion than the intended one. False dilemma includes a false premise of the form: we have to accept either A or B. 9 Scientific reasoning The traditional debate concerns the question of whether scientific reasoning is deductive, inductive or both. If one believes that scientific reasoning includes inductive reasoning, then one has to deal with the problem of induction. The problem of induction David Hume (1711-1776) There is no deductive justification for induction and any inductive justification for induction is circular. We cannot justify inductive reasoning without appealing to inductive reasoning of the form: inductive reasoning has been reliable in the past; therefore, it is likely to be reliable in the future. 10 The new riddle of induction Nelson Goodman (1906-1998): Definition: X is ”grue” = x is examined before year 2020 and is found to be green, or x is not so examined and is found to be blue. All emeralds examined to date have been green as well as grue. On what grounds do we believe that emeralds examined after 2020 are green and not grue? Illustration Suppose that we have a set of data points (x,y), and we want to find a general hypothesis by fitting a function f(x) to the data points. There is an infinite number of different functions that fit the data points. Which function should we prefer and on what grounds? 11 Simplicity Is the principle of simplicity a solution to the problem? y x Karl Popper’s (1902-1994) falsificationism Scientific reasoning is based on deductive logic, not on inductive logic: A general hypothesis H implies an observation statement E. It is not the case that E. Therefore, it is not the case that H. 12 Modus tollens If H, then E. Not E. Therefore, not H. Validity: It is not possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. Truth tables The argument is valid because it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false at the same time (no T-T-F). P Q P T T F F T F T F T F T T Q ¬Q ¬P F T F T F F T T 13 Fallacy: affirming the consequent If H, then E. E. Therefore, H. It is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. Counter-arguments to falsificationism: part I In the actual practice of science, scientists often argue that a hypothesis is to be accepted because relevant evidence supports it (inductive reasoning). Moreover, scientists do not always conclude that a theory or a hypothesis is false when they encounter contradictory evidence. A theory or a hypothesis is often rejected only when there is a plausible alternative to it (Thomas Kuhn). 14 Counter-arguments to falsificationism: part II The holistic nature of falsification: If (H and B1 and B2 and B3), then E. Not E. Therefore, it is not the case that (H and B1 and B2 and B3). So, what is false? H? B1? B2? B3? All of them? Counter-arguments to falsificationism: part III Popper’s falsificationism does not provide grounds to compare different unfalsified hypotheses. Why is it rational to prefer a hypothesis which has survived several attempts to falsify it to another hypothesis which has not been tested yet? 15 The Hypothetico-Deductive Model Problem Discovery Hypothesis is falsified. Hypothesis Deduction Observable Consequences No Consequences correspond to Yes observations? Hypothesis receives support. Living with the problem of induction Quantitative methods enable one to conclude that H is probably true, or H is acceptable with a certain probability of error. Bayesian reasoning Error statistics Qualitative methods in the social sciences: the goal is to understand social phenomena in their context, not to make generalizations. 16 Abductive reasoning? Charles S. Peirce (1839-1914): E. If H, then E. Therefore, H. Interpretation: The inquiry begins with E, not with H. H is not a generalization; it is an attempt to explain why E takes place. Abductive reasoning? Abductive “argument” is an attempt to understand the “logic” of scientific discovery, not the “logic” of epistemic justification. It is not a valid deductive argument. It may be reconstructed as an inductive argument where the conclusion is that H is probably true. 17 Summary Criteria for a good argument: (1) Premises are true or acceptable. (2) Premises are relevant to the main thesis. (3) There is a link between the premises and the main thesis: deductive or inductive. (4) The link is not undermined by further information. The most challenging part to understand is (2): the relevance of data to a hypothesis. The problem of relevance All swans are white. Therefore, the next swan I observe will be white too. In most cases, there is a conceptual gap between evidence and a hypothesis. One needs to argue that a certain body of evidence is relevant to the hypothesis. Contextual empiricism 18 Contextual empiricism Background assumptions are required to establish the relevance of observation reports to a hypothesis or a theory. In most cases an observed state of affairs in itself does not tell for what hypothesis or theory it can be taken as evidence. An observed state of affairs can be taken as evidence for quite different and even conflicting hypotheses given appropriately conflicting background assumptions. Longino, Helen. 1990. Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Today’s message Scientific reasoning includes both deductive and inductive reasoning. The so called abductive reasoning is not a different type of reasoning on its own right. 19