___________________________________ ___________________________________ Tolerance, Loyalty to Values and Respect for the Law 1 Herman De Dijn The Liberal-pragmatic Idea of Tolerance The modern idea of the right to freedom of each human being can be briefly described as follows: it is the right to personal judgment in matters of what is true and good and to selfdetermination of one’s life and actions in view of this judgment. Today this right is considered as the most basic, or one of the most basic, unquestionable rights of the individual. At the same time, our present situation is characterized by an undeniable pluralism. We have practically given up the hope that individuals, through their own judgment, will come to an agreement as to what are the central values in life, as to what is the good life. On the contrary, too much unity and agreement immediately raises the suspicion of more or less hidden constraint or indoctrination. In a pluralistic, free society, every defense of what is the good can only be seen as the defense of a particular conception of the good, which is potentially threatening for the self-determination of other individuals. The combination of the stress on freedom and the fact (and supposed value) of pluralism, leads to an extreme importance being given to tolerance. Tolerance, together with the multiplicity of life-styles, seems to be something positive in itself. Within this perspective, the real question does not seem to be whether tolerance is something positive in itself, but whether it has any limitations.2 One limitation seems almost self-evident: my freedom to think and do what I want, must go together with my recognition of the right of others as to their self-determination. This implies, at the very least, that, in exercising my rights, I certainly should not harm others. I should not, in furthering my aims and preferences, kill, injure or in general do real harm to others, because thereby I take away or diminish the very basis of their freedom. Within a liberal-pragmatic perspective, further restrictions of the freedom of individuals can be envisaged, in other words, further limitations as to toleration: those which have to do with the inevitable pragmatic organization of individual freedoms (e.g. traffic-rules, taxation, etc.). Some liberal authors even deny the individual the right to freely engage in acts seriously endangering his own life, if the consequences of these acts are liable to put a heavy burden on the general community (e.g. the obligation to wear safety-belts in cars, etc.). Finally, there are restrictions, even within the law of very liberal states, which it seems impossible to defend from a liberal perspective: certain legal restrictions (on blasphemy, pornography, euthanasia, etc.). Nevertheless, even these restrictions can be upheld within the liberal perspective, not on the ground that anybody engaging in these acts goes against truth or morality, but on the ground that these acts seriously offend deep-seated sensitivities of (large) groups of individuals. The reason invoked is considered as an extension of the noharm principle3 to psychic or moral distress. This whole liberal-pragmatic conception of tolerance, and of its possible restrictions, betrays a certain conception of man4 and of society: what one could call a ‘sentimentalist’ conception of man, and a pragmatic conception of society and of the State. Man is seen here not primarily as a being geared towards goodness and truth, but as a being trying first and foremost to avoid pain, but also to acquire pleasure as much as possible; it is in line with this sensitivity, that man develops all sorts of subjective preferences which he wants to ________________________________________________________________________________________ Ethical Perspectives 1 (1994)1, p. 27 ___________________________________ implement freely. Restrictions on this freedom can only be accepted because of possible harm to another’s sensitivity. Society, more particularly the State, is seen here as a sort of mega-machine which pragmatically organizes the coordination of all these sensitivities with the least possible interference. The consequence of this liberal-pragmatic view and practice is the relegation of fundamental religious and ethical values to the purely private realm. Since nobody can claim possession of the truth and of the criteria of what is morally good, opinions are only the opinions of private individuals, and values can only be taken seriously in terms of subjective preferences and sensibilities. The upshot of this is the by now well-known loss of value-awareness. It is not really astonishing that this liberal mentality also leads to the paradoxical consequences of growing indifference and even intolerance. Indeed, if what others are interested in is simply a question of private opinion or subjective preference, why should one be interested in their interests? If what has to be respected is simply individual sensitivities, why should one attach so much value to them, especially if one regards oneself as superior, exceptional, or invulnerable? Tolerance demands a pragmatic organization of sensibilities. Normally this must lead to an inflation of sensitivity: people will be asked more and more to be tolerant to others and not to impose ‘unreasonable’ demands on others. This inflation in turn may lead to eruptions of intolerance under the stress of the requirements of social adaptation. Finally, if tolerance is reduced to ‘letting everybody think and do as he likes’, it is not astonishing that tolerance as a positive virtue, i.e. as the ability to bear what is really unacceptable, would be lost. Tolerance and Recognition ___________________________________ It has been claimed earlier that there is a close connection between the liberal-pragmatic view on tolerance and a ‘sentimentalist’ conception of man. In this conception, the other is basically considered as a sensibility, first of all characterized by a desire to escape pain, and in the second place by a desire to freely look for whatever sort of satisfaction he prefers. Implied in this is the idea that the only thing which is really and evidently valuable is the absence of pain and, in the second order, the presence of pleasure, and that it is this which is behind all human desire and activity. In this context, the crucial human desire for respect and for recognition by others can only be interpreted in a peculiar way: as respect for and recognition of the rights of individual sensibilities to freedom and to no-harm. So, ultimately, these rights are to be understood in terms of the advantages derived from this respect and recognition, and there is really nothing more to them. The advantages are: not to be harmed by others, and to be able to acquire the pleasures of one’s liking freely. Again it turns out that the only real values are considered to be absence of pain and presence (as much as possible) of pleasure. It is the task of society to ensure that everyone gets this sort of respect and recognition, in other words the advantages related to them, in an equal way. The question is whether the fundamental desire of recognition can be interpreted in this way: whether people will really consider themselves recognized if their equal rights as to no-harm and free acquisition of pleasure are recognized. In the above-mentioned discussions concerning the limitation of tolerance in matters of pornography, blasphemy, etc., something strange happened: precisely those people whose sensitivity was supposed to need protection from interference by the freedom of others, were dissatisfied with the reasons offered for the limitation of freedom of these others. According to certain women-representatives, the ________________________________________________________________________________________ Ethical Perspectives 1 (1994)1, p. 28 ___________________________________ prohibition of pornography was not justified primarily in view of the prevention of nasty consequences, i.e. the psychological harm done to women; pornography was considered as being intrinsically wrong, incompatible with the dignity of women as such. In their view, recognition of the individual is linked with the respect of values with which one identifies or strongly associates oneself, and which one would like to be respected not primarily in view of the advantages or disadvantages for one’s sensibility. These values are such: 1) that recognition related to them cannot be distributed equally and 2) that ‘deep’ conflicts concerning them are practically inevitable. If one desires recognition as a woman, or as a father, or as an excellent sportsman, because one sees this as something intrinsically valuable (and not valuable simply in terms of desirable consequences), one wants a very special form of recognition. It is a form of recognition which cannot be understood only in terms of noninterference with the freedom of action of certain sensibilities; what one wants is not the advantages causally following from such recognition, not even the pleasure through the recognition, but the pleasure of real recognition.5 This, however, is a kind of recognition which cannot be partitioned equally. Such ‘real’ recognition requires a system, or systems, of oppositions (between man and woman, parents and children, good and bad writers, ...) which are such that the positions involved cannot be occupied purely by the effort of the individual, nor can they be assigned purely in view of the possible acquisition of personal satisfaction. A system in which everyone could obtain a certain ‘title’ (and recognition) simply because he wanted so, or in which ‘titles’ are evenly assigned simply in order to satisfy needs or appease sensibilities, would destroy itself as a system of real recognition. The possibility to obtain recognition as an ___________________________________ individual in function of intrinsic values presupposes a context in which real conflict is in principle always possible and in practice unavoidable. It is indeed always possible that these intrinsic values are not seen as intrinsic values by others, or that their interpretation differs, or even that they are seen as evils. The desire to be recognized in terms of a certain title, or to see certain values with which one is associated respected, can be thwarted in many ways. What is valuable to one party can always be unrecognizable as a value by another party; or even worse, it can be seen as evil, as the negation of what is a fundamental value for this other party. It is within the context of real recognition that the idea of moral respect for each human being as a human being is ultimately to be understood. The consideration of each human being as intrinsically valuable and respectable is not reducible to the ‘sentimentalist’ idea that pain must not be inflicted, and that room must be made for the acquisition of as much pleasure as possible. The prohibition of harm must be understood as deriving from the incompatibility of inflicting harm and of paying due respect to human beings. The moral prohibition of harm derives from the obligation to honour each human being as having the special title of ‘human being’. This honour is due even though this human being may appear to us as the most uninteresting or useless being, and even though it may be associated with values which are incomprehensible, ridiculous or even abominable to us. It is as if the less a human being is capable of participating fully in the game of real recognition, the more it is obligatory to respect it simply as a human being. Moral respect is due, as everybody knows, especially to the weak, the prisoner, the foreigner, the dead. But why should a human being be respected in a special, moral, way simply because it is a human being; why especially respect ‘the ________________________________________________________________________________________ Ethical Perspectives 1 (1994)1, p. 29 ___________________________________ widow and the orphan’? And what is the relationship between this peculiar, moral, respect and the game of real recognition? It seems clear that the respect due to human beings, simply because they are human beings, is related to the awareness of a certain boundary which should not be crossed (which, of course, is not to say that it will not be crossed). The ‘sacredness’ of this boundary cannot be accounted for on strictly rational grounds (appealing to elements like the rational nature of man, or the principle of no-harm of conscious sensibilities). Ultimately it can only function as a kind of fundamental taboo. This is probably why it is more easily preserved in the context of, and in association with religion (which is not to say that all sorts of rational arguments cannot play a certain role in upholding the taboo, nor that religion cannot be the cause or reason of transgressing the boundary). The functioning of the taboo of the sacredness of each human being must be related somehow to the game of real recognition itself. I cannot at this moment give a full account of this relationship. I, however, expect the following considerations to be part of such an account. The game of real recognition of values cannot be played unless there is a community of people sharing these values. Such a community cannot exist unless its members are themselves somehow valued for themselves. Things which are valued for themselves do not always shine in their full value (human beings cannot be continuously fully receptive to the shining of their values). This is why we need a sign indicating the value even when this value is not shining, a sign telling us what not to touch, and what to especially care for. In the case of human beings, such a sign is “the naked face of the other.”6 Even when human beings are not yet capable, or even if they will never be capable, of playing the game of real recognition, they must be respected (not ___________________________________ harmed, not dishonoured, but honoured in one or other form of respectful caring).7 Tolerance and Respect for the Law It is within the context of the acceptance of intrinsic values, and the system of recognition and respect related to it, that the real problem of tolerance can be discerned. This problem can be formulated as follows: why and how to tolerate behaviour which jeopardizes, offends or abuses fundamental values (whether this be the honour of a human being as such, or any other fundamental value), especially if one has the power not to tolerate? The real problem is how to tolerate the intolerable.8 Real tolerance, as Gabriel Marcel rightly said, is ‘contra-intolerance’.9 This problem can arise in every society, but inevitably arises in a pluralistic society. Here it is inescapable that what is honourable, intrinsically valuable and good to one party, turns out to be uninteresting, ridiculous or even abominable to another party.10 The problem is a real one, because the conflict will be both fundamental and inevitable. How is it possible to play the game of real recognition with others and of real respect for intrinsic values, and yet to tolerate that these values and the respect due to them are not always safe-guarded because certain groups or individuals do not accept or do not even understand the fundamental values, and therefore feel free to publicly disregard, deny, offend or abuse them? My contention is that the present-day parliamentary democratic system can be interpreted in such a way as to provide the possibility-condition for handling such conflicts, in accordance with the idea of real tolerance (as ‘contra-intolerance’). This is so because it provides a suitable context in which such conflicts can be settled without explicitly or implicitly denying that there is a realm of intrinsic values to be respected in themselves. ________________________________________________________________________________________ Ethical Perspectives 1 (1994)1, p. 30 ___________________________________ The parliamentary system provides the arena in which fundamental conflicts concerning values can be expressed. In this arena the conflicts concerning how different values are to be respected in society can also be settled in a non-violent way. They are fought out in a procedurally organized debate, and settled by majority voting, leading to laws which then are to be enforced effectively. By their prohibitions, the laws establish the public respect due to certain values. (In this way there is a certain partial link between society and its values, and political law). The aim of the parliamentary procedure is not simply to pragmatically organize the highest possible harmony between different sensibilities. The aim is primarily to settle the fundamental conflicts honourably, and in this way to establish the minimal requirements of respect for certain values, so that tolerance of the intolerable becomes, in fact, possible. Of course, within pluralistic society, it is very unlikely that legislation will determine the minimal respect concerning the whole range of fundamental values of all groups or individuals. This implies that certain forms of intolerable behaviour will be legally accepted and will have to be tolerated. On the other hand, certain restrictions on behaviour will be imposed concerning public respect for values which one does not understand or which one cannot accept as values. Nevertheless, within a parliamentary democratic system it is implied that it is always possible, within certain procedural limits, to re-open the debate concerning the (non-)expression of certain values within the Law. Tolerance of the intolerable is closely connected with respect for the Law which makes this tolerance possible. This respect is more than ___________________________________ the appreciation of a pragmatic machinery. This respect for the Law is itself respect for something transcending all pragmatic considerations, for something valuable in itself. (Simone Weil even speaks of “the holy majesty of the laws”).11 This respect is closely related to the awareness which we can and should have, in our toleration of the intolerable, that the value of intrinsic values somehow always transcends all our considerations and endeavours, that we cannot be the self-appointed guardians and interpreters of these values. In and through the allegiance of all to a Law which does not perfectly match each group’s vision of the good, citizens somehow express there acceptance that fundamental values transcend all appropriation. Paradoxically, it is this respect for the Law, and the tolerance made possible by it, which allow for a future in which values, as well as man himself as a value, can survive in unexpected ways. The greatest danger, both for freedom and tolerance, and for the survival of values (and therefore of man as man), is not only to be found in the intolerance of dogmatic fundamentalism which puts itself above the Law; it is equally to be found in the liberal-pragmatic attitude which would, if left to itself, eradicate not only all understanding and practice of values, but also of the Law itself.12 Notes ________________________________________________________________________________________ Ethical Perspectives 1 (1994)1, p. 31 ___________________________________ ___________________________________ 1.This text is a revised and shortened version of: Herman DE DIJN, ‘Trouw, tolerantie en democratie’, in Onze Alma Mater 46 (1992), p. 301-317. It was presented at the Conference on ‘Christian Universities and European Culture’-Antwerp, UFSIA, 11 November 1993. 2.For a discussion of these limitations, see J. HORTON & S. MENDUS (eds.), Aspects of Toleration. (Philosophical Studies). London & New York, Methuen, 1985, especially the papers by Albert Weave, Peter Jones, Susan Mendus and John Horton. 3.Concerning the ‘no-harm principle’, see. Joel FEINBERG, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (Vol. I-IV). Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1984-1988 (especially Vol. I. Harm to Others). 4.[Editor’s note: When the author uses ‘man’ or ‘he’, he means the general concept to include ‘man and woman’ or ‘he and she’.] 5.Cf. Adam Smith: what human beings want is not the pleasure accidentally related to praise, but the pleasure involved in knowing oneself to be really praise-worthy. See Adam SMITH, The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by D.D. Raphael en A.L. Macfie. Indianapolis, Liberty Classics, reprint 1982, p. 114. 6.I borrow this phrase from Levinas. I suspect, however, that my understanding of ethics is not the same as Levinas’s account. 7.On the distinction between caring and recognition, see: Arnold BURMS, ‘Helping and Appreciating’, in: S. GRIFFIOEN (ed.), What Right does Ethics Have? Public Philosophy in a Pluralistic Culture. Amsterdam, VU Univ. Press, p. 67-77. 8.I borrow this expression from D.D. Raphael’s paper with the same title in: Susan MENDUS (ed.), Justifying Toleration. Conceptual and Historical Perspectives. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 137-153. 12 9.See: Gabriël MARCEL, Du refus à l’invocation. Paris, Gallimard, 1956 , p. 270. 10.The party may today even be a party holding a liberal-pragmatic view. 11.See: Simone WEIL, The Need for Roots. Prelude to a Declaration of Duties towards Mankind. Preface by T.S. Eliot. London & New York, Ark Paperbacks, 1987, p. 171-2. 12.With thanks to my colleague Arnold Burms (especially concerning part 2 of this paper) and to the participants of the Antwerp-Conference. ________________________________________________________________________________________ Ethical Perspectives 1 (1994)1, p. 32