12. Kant and Handedness • "Concerning the Ultimate Foundation of the Differentiation of Regions of Space" (1768). Claim: Absolute space is necessary to explain the existence of incongruent counterparts. Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) [An incongruent counterpart is]...an object which is completely like and similar to another, although it cannot be included exactly within the same limits." • An incongruent counterpart is a certain type of mirror image. • Example 1: (1) (2) • Maps (1) and (2) reproduce the same relations between objects. • A relationist must say they are the same. • An absolutist can say they are different; namely, they differ in their locations with respect to absolute space. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. (2) O' is an incongruent counterpart of O if it cannot be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. (2) O' is an incongruent counterpart of O if it cannot be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. (2) O' is an incongruent counterpart of O if it cannot be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Two types of mirror image Let O be an object and let O' be its mirror image. (1) O' is a congruent counterpart of O if it can be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. (2) O' is an incongruent counterpart of O if it cannot be made to coincide with O by rigid motions. Important Fact: Whether or not a mirror image is an incongruent counterpart depends on the properties of the space it is located in. • If the space is 3-dimensional, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • If the space is 3-dimensional, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • If the space is 3-dimensional, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • If the space is 3-dimensional, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • Obtained by identifying edge points x with x', and y with y' on a 2-dim strip. • Result: A global "twist" that allows the mirror image of F to be rigidly transported around the entire space back onto F. x • • y' y • • x' • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • Obtained by identifying edge points x with x', and y with y' on a 2-dim strip. • Result: A global "twist" that allows the mirror image of F to be rigidly transported around the entire space back onto F. x • • y' y • • x' • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • Obtained by identifying edge points x with x', and y with y' on a 2-dim strip. • Result: A global "twist" that allows the mirror image of F to be rigidly transported around the entire space back onto F. x • • y' y • • x' • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • Obtained by identifying edge points x with x', and y with y' on a 2-dim strip. • Result: A global "twist" that allows the mirror image of F to be rigidly transported around the entire space back onto F. x • • y' y • • x' • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • Obtained by identifying edge points x with x', and y with y' on a 2-dim strip. • Result: A global "twist" that allows the mirror image of F to be rigidly transported around the entire space back onto F. x • • y' y • • x' • If the space is 2-dimensional and non-orientable, then F and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. • Example: A Möbius strip. • Obtained by identifying edge points x with x', and y with y' on a 2-dim strip. • Result: A global "twist" that allows the mirror image of F to be rigidly transported around the entire space back onto F. x • • y' y • • x' • Modified definition: An object is an incongruent counterpart of another if they cannot be made to occupy the same place by rigid motions in a local (closely surrounding) region of space. • An object is said to possess handedness (chirality) just when it and its mirror image are incongruent counterparts. • An object is said to lack handedness (chirality) just when it and its mirror image are congruent counterparts. spherical cow • Kant's Argument for Absolute Space: "Let it be imagined that the first created thing were a human hand, then it must necessarily be either a right hand or a left hand." • But: A relationist cannot determine the handedness of an object in the absence of other objects. • So: Relationalism is not adequate. • Left and right hands agree on all relational properties. • Absolutist: They disagree on their locations with respect to absolute space. • Letter Example Again: • Do F and its mirror image have the same relational properties? • Depends on how many properties one is willing to consider as relational. THE QUICK BROWN FOX JUMPED OVER THE LAZY DOG. THE QUICK BROWN OX JUMPED OVER THE LAZY DOG. • F and its mirror image differ in their relational properties to the other letters in the sentence. • There is no way to make the mirror image of F fit into the sentence in the same way that F does. • Similarly, there is no way to fit a right hand into a left-handed (Freddy Krueger) glove (and vice versa). • But: How can a relationist determine the handedness of an object when there are no other reference objects to define distinguishing relational properties? • Moreover: What if such reference objects themselves have been reflected? • Since F and its mirror image share all relational properties in these sentences, a relationist will not be able to distinguish them. • Absolutist intuition: Aren't F and its mirror image distinct, independent of their relations to other objects? Relationist's Reflection Argument: • Suppose: Absolute space exists. • Then: The following two universes must be possible: absolute space A absolute space A B world 1 (unreflected) Universe 1 world 2 (reflected) Universe 2 • An absolutist must claim the reflection produces distinct worlds: They differ on their values of absolute position. • But: A relationist will claim that the reflection does not produce distinct worlds: Since the relations between material objects are unaffected (and there's no such thing as absolute space), the worlds are not distinct. Possible Absolutist Retort: • Would a reflected world be indiscernible from an unreflected world? • Replace Spock with a decaying Cobalt-60 atom: Spock Co60 → Ni60 + e− + νe e− Mirror Spock e− Co60 νe Co60 decay Co60 νe Mirror Co60 decay • Co60 decay (electron emitted in direction of nuclear spin) is observed more often than Mirror Co60 decay (electron emitted in opposite direction of nuclear spin) (Wu et al. 1957). • Evidence that the weak force (that governs decay) violates mirror symmetry (i.e., "parity"). absolute space absolute space A A B world 1 (unreflected) Universe 1 world 2 (reflected) Universe 2 • Absolutist Claim: The reflected and unreflected worlds are not observationally indiscernible. In world 1, the Co60 atom decay occurs more frequently than in world 2. • Onus is now on the relationist to explain the physical difference between worlds 1 and 2 (recall Clarke's Dynamic Shift, with parity-violating experiments now replacing inertial effects). Chien-Shiung Wu (1912-1997) Let it be imagined that the first created thing were a Co60 decay process, then it must necessarily be either a right-handed Co60 decay process, or a left-handed Co60 decay process... and there's a law-like physical difference between the two! • Can a relationist both ground the distinction between right- and left-handed processes and explain why one is more probable than the other? (a) Claim that the difference is intrinsic: Co60 decay processes possess an intrinsic monadic (non-relational) property that both determines their handedness and their weak-force-governed behavior. (b) Claim the difference is extrinsic: - What determines whether the first created Co60 decay process is rightor left-handed is its relation to all subsequent Co60 decay processes. - And: It is a brute lawlike fact (in need of no further explanation) that one of these decay processes is more probable than the other. A Lingering Concern about Option (b): • First: What explains Newton's First Law? How does a force-free object know to move inertially? - Absolutist: A local interaction between spacetime and the object (local spacetime "feelers"). - Relationist: A nonlocal correlation between the object and other objects (nonlocal inertial antennae). • Similarly: What explains the parity-violating weak force? Why do Co60 atoms prefer decay modes of one chirality rather than another (given chirality is not intrinsic)? - Absolutist: A local interaction between spacetime and the object. - Relationist: A nonlocal correlation between the object and other objects (nonlocal weakforce antennae).