StudentPortfoliosandthe CollegeAdmissionsProblem* †HectorChad GregoryLewis §LonesSmit e ‡ h Firstversion: July2003 * Thisversion: March9,2013 Abstract We develop a decentralized Bayesian model of college admissions with two rankedcolleges,heterogeneousstudentsandtworealisticmatchfrictions: students find it costly to apply to college, and college evaluations of their applications is uncertain. Students thus face a portfolio choice problem in their application decision,whilecollegeschooseadmissionsstandardsthatactlikemarket-clearing prices. Enrollmentateachcollegeisaffectedbythestandardsattheothercollege throughstudentportfolioreallocation. Inequilibrium,student-collegesortingmay fail: weaker students sometimes apply more aggressively, and the weaker college mightimposehigherstandards. Applyingourframework,weanalyzeaffirmative action,showinghowitinducesminorityapplicantstoconstructtheirapplication portfoliosasiftheyweremajoritystudentsofhighercaliber. Earlierversionswere called “The College Admissions Problemwith Uncertainty”and “A Supply andDemandModeloftheCollegeAdmissionsProblem”. WewouldliketothankPhilippKircher(CoEditor)andthreeanonymousrefereesfortheirhelpfulcommentsands uggestions. GregLewisandLones Smith are grateful for the financial support of the National Science Foundation. We have benefited from seminars at BU, UCLA, Georgetown, HBS, the 2006 Two-Sided Matching Conference (Bonn), 2006SED(Vancouver),2006LatinAmericanEconometricSocietyMeetings(Mexico City),and2007 AmericanEconometricSociety Meetings (New Orleans),IowaState, Harvard/MIT,the 2009Atlanta NBER Conference, and Concordia. ParagPathak and Philipp Kircher provideduseful discussions of our paper. We are also grateful to John Bound and Brad Hershbein for providing us with student collegeapplicationsdata. †ArizonaStateUniversity,DepartmentofEconomics,Tempe,AZ85287. ‡HarvardUniversity,DepartmentofEconomics,Cambridge,MA02138. §UniversityofWisconsin,DepartmentofEconomics,Madison,WI53706. 1 Introduction Thecollegeadmissions processhaslatelybeentheobjectofmuchscrutiny, bothfrom academicsandinthepopularpress. Thisinterestowesinparttothecompetitivenature ofcollegeadmissions. Schoolssetadmissionsstandardstoattractthebeststudents,and students in turn respond most judiciously in making their application decisions. This paperexaminesthejointbehaviorofstudentsandcollegesinequilibrium. 1We introduce anequilibrium model ofcollege admissions thatanalyzes the impact oftwopreviouslyunexploredfrictionsintheapplicationprocess: studentsfinditcostly to apply to college, and college evaluations of their applications is uncertain. As evidence ofthenoiseintheprocess, observe thatadmissions ratesarewellbelow50%at themostselective colleges, andbelow 75%atthemedian 4year college.This uncertainty prevails conditional on the SAT. Even applicants with perfect SAT scores have nobetter than a50%chance ofgetting into schools like Harvard, MIT and Princeton (Avery,Glickman,Hoxby,andMetrick, 2004). So itis notsurprising thatmost applicantsconstructthoughtfulportfoliosthatincludeboth“safety”and“stretch”schools. 2Despite this uncertainty, the costly nature of applications substantially limits the numberofapplicationssent—threeforthemedianstudent.3Afastgrowingempirical literature confirms the impact of this friction: for instance, Pallais (2009) finds that when the ACT allowed students to send an extra free application, 20% of ACT testtakerstookadvantageofthisoption.-4Smallcostscanhavelargeeffectsonapplication behavior because the marginal benefit of applying falls geometrically in the number of applications. A student applying to identical four-year colleges with a typical 75% acceptancerateseesthemarginalbenefittoher5thapplicationscaledby4=1/256: Evenifattendingcollegethisyearisworth$20000,themarginalbenefitisonly$59. 4Figure 1 illustrates some motivating patterns in the application data. The right panel demonstrates the importance of the applications frictions — for the chance of matriculating at a private elite school is significantly higher for students who apply widely.TheleftpanelplotsthenumberofapplicationsasafunctionoftheSATscore, 1Source: Table329,DigestofEducationStatistics,NationalCenterforEducationStatistics. HigherEducationResearchInstitute(HERI),usingalargenationallyrepresentativesurvey ofcollegefreshmansince1966(dataalsousedtoconstructFigure1;seeonlineappendixfordetails). 3Steinberg(2010)reportedthatcollegeswhowaivedapplicationfeessawapplicationsskyrocket. 4AveryandKane(2004)studyaBostonprogramgivinglow-incomestudentsadviceonhow/where to apply; these students matriculated at a higher rate than comparable students elsewhere. Similar results have later been found in field experiments where students received application help: see Bettinger,Long,Oreopoulos,andSanbonmatsu(2009)andCarrellandSacerdote(2012). 2Source: 1 Prob. Enrolls at Top Private University 0 .05 .1 .15 Number of Applications 23456 600 800 1000 1200 1400 1600 SAT Score Applied in ’85-’89 Applied in ’90-’94 Applied in ’95-’98 1200 1300 1400 1500 1600 SAT Score < Median Income, Apps <= 3 < Median Income, Apps > 3 > Median Income, Apps <= 3 > Median Income, Apps > 3 Fig ure1: ApplicationsandMatriculationbySAT.Th eleftpanelshowstheestimated relationshipbetweenSATscoreandnumberofapplications. Therightpanelshowsthechance ofmatriculatingatatopprivateuniversity,bynumberofapplicationsandhouseholdincome. Estimationisbylocallinearregression;95%confidenceintervalsareshownasdottedlines. smallbutlargerthanoneconsistentwithourtwofrictions.5 Anymodelthatfocusesonthesetwofrictions—costlyportfoliochoiceswithincompleteinf ormation—mustdivergefromtheapproachofthecentralizedcollegematching literature (GaleandShapley, 1962), for it expressly sidesteps such matching frictions. Rather,weanalyzeanentirelydecentralizedmodelthatparallelstheactualprocess. It affords sharp conclusions about two key decision margins: how colleges set admission standardsandhowstudentsformulatetheirapplicationportfolios. 6Weassumethataheterogeneouspopulationofstudents,andtworankedcolleges— one better and one worse, respectively, called 1 and 2. Like the decentralized model ofAveryandLevin(2010),thereisacontinuumofstudents;thisavoidscollegesfacing aggregateuncertainty —otherwise, wait-listing isneeded, forinstance.Colleges seek tofilltheircapacitywiththebeststudentspossible,butstudentcalibersareonlyimperfectlyobs erved. Thetandemofcostlyapplicationsandyetnoisyevaluationsfeedsthe intriguingconflictattheheartofthestudentchoiceproblem: shootfortheIvyLeague, settleforthelocalstateschool,orapplytoboth. Asweshallsee,ourpaperformalizes the critical roles played by stretch and safety schools. Meanwhile, college enrollments areinterdependent,sincethestudents’portfoliosdependonthejointcollegeadmissions 5Data fromUS News and World Reportshows that admissions ratesfall as college rank rises. So largerportfoliosareparticularlyvaluableforhighSATstudentsapplyingtotopcolleges. 6Weomitmanyreal-worldelementslikefinancialaidandpeereffects,butthesearetypicallyruledout incentralizedmatchingmodelstoo. Inanewpaper,AzevedoandLeshno(2012)assumeacontinuum of students in a centralizedpaper in the spirit of GaleandShapley (1962), and find that it affordsa characterizationofequilibriumintermsofsupplyanddemand—oneofourobservationstoo. 2 standards, and students accepted at the better college will not attend the lesser one. Thisasymmetricinterdependenceleadstomanysurprisingresults. Central toourpaper isaBayesian theorem characterizing how student acceptance chancesatthecollegescovarywithstudentcaliber. Wededucethatasastudent’scaliberrises,theratioofhisadmissionchancesatcollege1tocolle ge2risesmonotonically. Wearethusabletosolvetheequilibriuminthreestages,firstdeducinghowacceptance chancestranslateintoapplicationportfolios,andthenseeinghowportfoliochoicesacross studentcalibersrelate,foranypairofcollegeadmissionstandards;finally,wecompute thederiveddemandforcollegeslots. Weanalyzetheequilibriumoftheinducedadmissionsstandardsgameamongcollegesthrough thelensofsupplyanddemand: Whena collegeraisesitsstandards,itsenrollmentfallsbothbecausefewerstudentsmakethecut —thestandards effect—andfewerwillapplyexante —theportfolioeffect. Treating admissions standards as prices, these effects reinforce each other. In equilibrium, we uncover a “law ofdemand”, in which a college’s enrollment falls in its standard. The portfolioeffectincreasestheelasticityofthisdemandcurve. AnalogoustoBertrandcompetitionwithdifferentiatedproducts,collegeswillchoose admissions standards to fill their desired enrollment, taking rival standards and the student portfolios as given. An equilibrium occurs when both markets clear and studentsbehaveoptimally. Themodelfrictionsyieldsomenovelcomparativestatics. For instance, the admissions standards at both colleges fall if college 2 raises its capacity, whilelowerapplicationcostsateither schoolincreasetheadmissions standardsatthe bettercollege. Wewillarguethatourequilibriumframeworkrationalizesthepatternof changingcollegestandardsandadmissionratesrecentlydocumentedbyHoxby(2009). Inamajorthrustofthepaper,weaskwhethersortingoccursinequilibrium: First, dothebetterstudentsapplymore“aggressively”? Precisely,thebeststudentsapplyjust tocollege1;weakerstudentsinsurebyapplyingtobothcolleges;evenweakeronesapply just tocollege 2; and finally, theweakest apply nowhere. Such anapplication pattern rationalizesthegeneralriseandfallthatweobserveintheleftpanelofFigure1. Second, does the better college impose higher admissions standards? The answer to this latter questionisnowhenthelessercollegeissufficientlysmall,forbyour“lawofdemand”, college2continuestoraiseitsstandardsasitscapacityfalls. Failuresofstudentsorting aremoresubtle: Thewillingnessofstudentseitherto(i)gambleonastretchschoolor(ii) insurethemselveswithasafetyschoolmaynotbemonotoneintheirtypes. Conversely, allequilibriaentailsortingwhenthecollegesdiffersufficientlyinqualityandthelower 3 rankedschoolisnottoosmall. Alltold,sortingproveselusivewithfrictions.7Thecollege sortingfailuresthatweidentifyhaveproblematicimplicationsforrankingsbasedonthe characteristics of matriculants, such as their SAT scores: Colleges that substantially increasetheircapacityarepenalized,sincetheymustlowertheiradmissionstandards. This paper takes very seriously the uncertainty that clouds the student admission process. Students apply tocolleges, perhaps knowing their types, orperhaps ignorant ofthem. Equallywell, colleges evaluatestudents tryingtogaugethefuturestars, and often do not succeed. The best framework for analyzing this world therefore involves two-sided incomplete information. In fact, we later formulate such a richer Bayesian model, and argue that its predictions are well-approximated by ours where students know their types, andcolleges observe noisy signals. The sortingfailures we claim, as wellasthepositivetheoryofhowstudentsandcollegesreact,areinfactrobustfindings. We conclude the paper with a topical foray into “affirmative action” for in-state applicants,orotherpreferredapplicantgroups. Weshowthatcollegesimposedifferent admissions standards so astoequate the “shadow values” ofapplicants fromdifferent groups—aformofthirddegreepricediscrimination. This,inturn,affectshowstudents behave: inasimple case, lowercaliberapplicants ofafavoredgroupbehave asifthey were higher caliber applicants from a non-favored group. This is consistent with the reductioninless-qualifiedminorityapplicationstoselectivepublicschoolsaftertheend ofaffirmativeactioninCaliforniaandTexas,documentedinCardandKrueger(2005). 2 TheModel A.AnOverview. Thepaperintroducesthreekeyfeatures—heterogeneousstudents, portfolio choices with unit application costs, and noisy evaluations by colleges. We impose little additional structure. Forinstance, we ignore the important and realistic considerationofheterogeneousstudentpreferencesovercolleges,aswellaspeereffects. 8Acentralfeatureofouranalysisismodelingcollegeportfolioapplications. Student choiceistrivialifitiscostless,andinpractice,suchcostscanbequitehigh. Indeed,the solepurposeoftheCommonApplicationistolowerthecostofmultipleapplications. 7Thisaddstotheliteratureondecentralizedfrictionalmatching—e.g.,ShimerandSmith(2000), Smith (2006), Chade (2006), and AndersonandSmith (2010). The student portfolio problem in the model is a special case of ChadeandSmith (2006). In this sense, our paper also contributes to the directed search literature. See BurdettandJudd (1983), Burdett,Shi,andWright (2001), Albrecht,Gautier,andVroman(2003)andKircherandGalenianos(2006)). 8Thisgeneralapplicationformisusedbyalmost400colleges,andsimplifiescollegeapplications. It 4 Next, we assume noisy signals of student calibers. This informational friction createsuncertaintyforstudents,andaBayesianfilteringproblemforcolleges. Itcaptures thedifficultyfacedbymarketparticipants,withstudentschoosing“safetyschools”and “stretchschools”,andcollegestryingtoinferthebeststudentsfromnoisysignals. Without noise, sorting would be trivial: Better students would apply and be admitted to bettercolleges,fortheircaliberwouldbecorrectlyinferredandtheywouldbeaccepted. 9Wealsomaketwootherkeymodelingchoices. First,weassumejusttwocolleges,for thesakeoftractability. Butasweargueintheconclusion,thisisthemostparsimonious framework that captures all of our key findings. We also fix the capacity of the two colleges. Thisisdefensibleintheshortrun,andsoitisbesttointerpretourmodelas focusingonthe“shortrun”analysisofcollegeadmissions. Weexplorethesimultaneous gameinwhichstudentsapplytocollege,andcollegesdecidewhomtoadmit. In the interest of tractability, our analysis assumes that the colleges’ evaluations of students are conditionally independent. This captures the case where students are apprisedofallvariables(suchastheACT/SATortheirGPA)commontotheirapplicationsbefo re applyingtocollege. Studentsareuncertainastohowtheseidiosyncratic elements such as college-specific essays and interviews will be evaluated, but believe thattheresultingsignalsareconditionallyindependentacrosscolleges. Werevisitthis restrictioninSection6,andarguethatourmainresultsonsortingarerobust,andthat wehaveanalyzedarepresentativecase. and κ2 B. The Model. There are two colleges 1 and 2 with capacities κ1 1+κ2 9 5 , and a unitmassofstudentswithcalibersxwhosedistributionhasapositivedensityf(x)over [0,8). Non-trivialitydemands thatcollegecapacitybeinsufficient forallstudents, as κ<1. Toavoidmanysubscripts,weshallalmostalwaysassumethatstudentspay aseparatebutcommonapplicationcostc>0forthetwocolleges. Resultsaresimilar withdifferentcosts. Allstudents prefercollege1. Everyone receives payoffv>0for attending college 1, u∈ (0,v) for college 2, and zero payoff for not attending college. Studentsmaximizeexpectedcollegepayofflessapplicationcosts. Collegesmaximizethe totalcaliberoftheirstudentbodiessubjecttocapacityconstraints. eliminatesidiosyncraticcollegerequirements,butretainsseparatecollegeapplicationfees. Epple,Romano,andSieg (2006) analyze an equilibrium model that includes tuition as a choice variable,peereffects,andstudentsthatdifferinabilityandincome. Undersinglecrossingconditions, they obtainpositive sorting onability for eachincome level. Their model, however,does not include costly applications or noise, thus precluding the portfolio effects we focus on and their implications forsorting. While wedonotallowcollegestochoosetheirtuitionlevels,wedonotignorethe roleof tuition,foronecansimplyinterpretthebenefitsofattendingcollegeasnetbenefits. Students know their caliber, and colleges do not. Colleges 1 and 2 each just observesanoisyconditionallyindependentsignalofeachapplicant’scaliber. Inparticular, theydonotknowwhereelsestudentshaveapplied. Signalssaredrawnfromaconditionaldensityfunctiong(s|x)onasubintervalofR,withcdfG(s|x). Weassumethat g(s|x)iscontinuousandobeysthestrict monotonelikelihoodratioproperty(MLRP). Sog(t|x)/g(s|x)isincreasinginthestudent’stypexforallsignalst>s. Students applysimultaneously toeither, both,orneithercollege,choosingforeach caliberx,acollegeapplicationmenuS(x)in{Ø,{1},{2},{1,2}}. Collegeschoosethe set of acceptable student signals. They intuitively should use admission standards to maximizetheirobjectivefunctions,sothatcollegeiadmitsstudentsaboveathreshold signals i. AppendixA.1provesthisgiventheMLRPproperty—despiteanacceptance curse thatcollege2faces(asitmayacceptarejectofcollege1). -s/xForafixed admission standard, we want toensure thatvery high quality students arealmostneverrejected,andverypoorstudentsarealmostalwaysrejected. Forthis, we assume thatforafixed signals, we have G(s|x)→0asx→8 andG(s|x)→1 asx→0. Forinstance, exponentially distributed signalshavethispropertyG(s|x)= 1-e'. Moregenerally,thisobtainsforsignalsdrawnfromany“locationfamily”,in whichtheconditionalcdfofsignalssisgivenbyG((s-x)/µ),foranysmoothcdfG andµ>0—e.g.normal,logistic,Cauchy,oruniformlydistributedsignals. Thestrict MLRPthenholdsifthedensityisstrictlylog-concave,i.e.,logGisstrictlyconcave. C.Equilibrium. Weconsiderasimultaneousmovegamebycollegesandstudents. 10This yields the same equilibrium prediction as when students move first, as they are atomless.Anequilibriumisatriple(S*(·),s* 1,s* 2)suchthat: (a) Given(s* 1,s* 2),S*(x)is anoptimalcollegeapplicationportfolioforeachx, (b) Given(S*(·),s* j),collegei’spayoffismaximizedbyadmissionsstandards* i. Wea lsowishtoprecludetrivialequilibriainourmodelinwhichoneorbothcolleges rejecteverybodywithaveryhighadmissionsthresholdandstudentsdonotapplythere. Arobustequilibrium alsorequiresthatanycollegethatexpectstohaveexcesscapacity setthelowestadmissionsthreshold. Sinceκ1+κ2<1,bothcollegeswillhaveapplicants. 10SeeAppendixA.2. Alternatively,collegescouldmovefirst,committingtoanadmissionstandard. Thisisarguablynotthecase,butregardless,ittooyieldsthesameequilibriauntilwestudyaffirmative action(proofomitted). Intheinterestsofaunifiedtreatmentthroughoutthepaper,weproceedinthe simultaneousmoveworld. 6 Inarobustsortingequilibrium,colleges’andstudents’strategiesaremonotone. This means thatthe better college is more selective (s* 1>s* 2) and higher caliber students areincreasinglyaggressiveintheirportfoliochoice: Theweakestapplynowhere;better studentsapplytothe“easier”college2;evenbetterones“gamble”byapplyingalsoto college1;thenexttierupshootan“insurance”applicationtocollege2;finally,thetop students confidently just apply to college 1. Monotone strategies ensure the intuitive result that the distribution of student calibers at college 1 first-order stochastically dominates that of college 2 (see Claim 4 in Appendix A.7), so that all top student quantilesarelargeratcollege1. Thisisthemostcompellingnotionofstudentsorting inourenvironmentwithnoise(Chade,2006). Ourconcernwitharobustsortingequilibriummaybemotivatedonefficiencygrounds. Iftherearecomplementaritiesbetweenstudentcaliberandcollegequality,sothatwelfareismaxi mizedbyassigningthebeststudentstothebestcolleges,anydecentralized matching system must necessarily satisfy sorting to be (constrained) efficient. Since formalizingthisideawouldaddnotationandofferlittleadditionalinsight,wehaveabstractedfrom thesenormativeissuesandfocusedonthepositiveanalysisofthemodel. D.CommonversusPrivateValues. Noticethatinourmodelcollegescareabout thetruecaliberofastudentandnotaboutthesignalperse. Inotherwords,themodel exhibitscommonvaluesonthesideofthecolleges. AppendixA.1showscollegesbehave inexactlythesamewayiftheydonotcareaboutcaliberbutcareonlyaboutthesignal i.e. theprivatevaluescase. Inthisinterpretation,studentsdifferintheirobservablesx (knowntobothstudentsandcolleges),andalsointheir“fit”foreachcollegeo(known only to the college). College payoffs depend on both observables and fit through the signalsi=si(x,oii). UntiltheaffirmativeactionapplicationinSection7,all theresults applytotheprivatevaluescaseaswell,albeitwithadifferentinterpretation. 3 EquilibriumAnalysisforStudents 3.1 TheStudentOptimization Problem Webeginbysolvingfortheoptimalcollegeapplicationsetforagivenpairofadmission chances at the two colleges. Consider the portfolio choice problem for a student with admission chances 0 = a1,a= 1. The expected payoff of applying to both colleges is a1v+(1-a1)a22u. The marginal benefit MBijofadding college itoaportfolioof 7 1.0 MB12 c Α1v Α2u MB21 0.8 c 1.0 0.8 SafetyStretch 0.6 C B 2 0.6 0.4 0.4 0.2 0 . 2 C1 0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 0.0 Α1 x 0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 0.0 Α1 x Figure 2: Optimal Decision Regions. The left panel depicts (i) a dashed box, inside which applying anywhere is dominated; (ii) the indifference line for solo applications to colleges 1 and 2; and (iii) the marginal benefit curves MB12= cand MB21= cfor adding colleges1or2. Therightpanelshowstheoptimalapplicationregions. Astudentintheblank regionFdoesnotapplytocollege. Heappliestocollege2onlyintheverticalshadedregion C2; tobothcollegesinthehashedregionB,andtocollege1o nlyinthehorizontalshadedregionC1. = [a1v+(1-a1)a2u]-a1v=(1-a1)a2 = [a1v+(1-a1)a2u]-a2u=a1(v-a2u) (2) 1 2 collegejisthen: MB21 u (1) MB v= a2 u= a1 21 1v=c),andtobothcolleges(MB21 2u=c),andtobothcolleges(MB12 12 1 v>MB12 21=canda2u>MB21 8 =c,a1v=a2 12 Α2x Α 2x Theoptimalapplicationstrategyisthengivenbythefollowingrule: (a) Applynowhereifcostsareprohibitive: c>au. (b) Apply just to college 1, if it beats applying just to college 2 (a TheleftpanelofFigure2depictsthreecriticalcurves: MB 2 =MB12,whena1v=a2u. 1 u. Allthreecurvesshareacrossingpoint,sinceMB =c,MB u), and nowhere(a<c,i.e.addingco it beats applying just to college 1 nowhere(a<c,i.e.addingcollege1is beats applying just to college 1 (M justtocollege2(MB=c),forthen,thes beatapplyingtonowhere,asa=cby( illuminating and rigorous graphica 1.0 C2 0.8 0.6 0.4 B C 1 0.2 0 . 0 0 . 2 0 . 4 0 . 6 0 . 8 1 . 0 0 . 0 Α 1 x Figure3: TheAcceptanceFunctionwithE xponentialSignals. Thefiguredepicts theacceptance functionψ(a1)for thecase of exponential signals. As their caliber increases, studentsapplytonowhere(F),colle ge2only(C),bothcolleges(B)—spe cifically,firstusing college 1 as a stretch school, and later college 2 as a safety school — and finally college 1 only(C12). Studentbehavioristhereforemonot onefortheacceptancefunctiondepi cted. Cases (a)–(d) partition the unit square into (a1,a) regions corresponding to the portfolio choices (a)–(d), denoted F,C2,B,C12, shaded in the right panel of Figure 2. Thissummarizestheportfolioch oiceofastudentwithanyadmissi onschances(a1,a2). Inthemarginalimprovement algorithmofChadeandSmith(20 06),astudentfirst decides whether she should apply anywhere. If so, she asks which college is the best singleton. In Figure 2 at the left, college 1 is best right of the line a1v = au, and college 2 is best left of it. Next, she asks whether she should apply anywhere else. Intuitively,therearetwodistinctr easonsforapplyingtobothcolleg esthatwecannow parse: Either college1 is a stretch school — i.e., a gamble, added as a lower-chance higherpayoffoption—orcollege 2isasafetyschool,addedforinsu rance. InFigure2, thesearethepartsofregionBabo veandbelowthelinea1v=a22u,re spectively. The choice regions obey some natural comparative statics. The application region Cito either college increases in Α2x its payoff, in light of expressions (1) and (2), and the region B shifts right in the college 2 payoff u, and left in the college 1 payoff v. In particular,ifastudentenjoysfixe dacceptanceratesatthetwocoll eges,acollegegrows less attractive as the payoff of its rival rises. Also, as the application cost crises, the jointapplicationregionBshrinks andtheemptysetFgrows. Althoughoutsideourmodel,l etusbrieflyconsidernon-linearc osts—forinstance, the second application costs may be less than c, possibly due to some duplication of 9 forms, essays, etc. Weanalyze thisintheonline appendix, andshow thatregionBis biggerandtheremainingregionssmallerthanwithconstantcosts. Interestingly,some typeswhowouldsendnosingletonapplicationswouldnonethelessapplytobothcolleges. 3.2 Admission Chances and StudentCalibers Wehavesolvedtheoptimizationforknownacceptancechances. Butwewishtopredict theportfoliodecisionsofthestudents, despitetheendogenousacceptancechances. To thisend,wenowderiveamappingfromstudenttypestostudentapplicationportfolios. Fix the thresholds s1and s2set by college 1 and college 2. Student x’s acceptance chance at college iis given by ai(x) = 1-G(s|x). Since a higher caliber student generates stochastically higher signals, aii(x) increases in x. In fact, it is a smoothly monotoneonto function—namely,itisstrictlyincreasinganddifferentiable,with0< a1(x)<1,andthelimitbehaviorlimx→0a1(x)=0andlimx→8a1(x)=1. Takingtheacceptancechancesasgiven,eachstudentofcaliberxfacestheportfolio optimizationproblemof§3.1. She mustchoose asetS(x)ofcollegestoapply to,and accepttheofferofthebestschoolthatadmitsher. WenowtranslatethesetsF,C2,B,C1 ofacceptancechancevectorsintocorrespondingsetsofcalibers,namely,F,C 2,B,C1. Keytoourgraphicalanalysisisaquantile-quantilefunctionrelatingstudentadmissionchancesatthecolleges: Sincea(x)strictlyrisesinthestudent’stypex,astudent’s admission chance a2ito college 2 is strictly increasing in his admission chance a1to college 1. Inverting the admission chance in the type x, the inverse function ξ(a,s) is the student type accepted with chance agiven the admission standard s, namely a=1-G(s|ξ(a,s)). Thisyieldsanimplieddifferentiableacceptancefunction a2 =ψ(a1,s 1,s 2)=1-G(s 2|ξ(a1,s 1)) (3) 1 Weproveintheappendixthattheacceptancefunctionrisesincollege1’sstandards 2 10 ndfallsincollege2’sstandards a ,andtendsto0and1asthresholdsnearextremes. ByFigure3,secantlinesdrawnfromtheoriginor(1,1)tosuccessivepoints acceptancefunctiondecreaseinslope. Tothisend,saythatafunctionh:[0,1 the double secant property if h(a) is weakly increasing on [0,1] with h(0 h(1)=1,andthetwosecantslopesh(a)/aand(1-h(a))/(1-a)aremonotoneina Thisdescriptionfullycaptureshowouracceptancechancesrelatetooneano Theorem 1(The AcceptanceFunction) Theacceptancefunctiona2 =ψ(a1 1 2 1,s 1(x)andh(a1(x)). 2/s 1 1 1 -s/x 1) = as1 13 14 =c an dM B12 12 21 =1,thenMB21 =candMB12 2 1=crespectivelyforcea1 =1-(c/u)anda1 11 1 12 13Forifa2 14ForMB )has thedoublesecantproperty. Conversely,foranysmoothmonotoneontofunctiona(x), andanyhwiththedoublesecantproperty,thereexistsacontinuoussignaldensityg(s|x) withthestrictMLRP,andthresholdss,forwhichadmissionchancesofstudentx tocolleges1and2area Thisresultgivesacompletecharacterizationofhowstudent admissionchances attwo ranked universities should compare. It says that if a student is so good that he is guaranteed to get intocollege 1, then he is alsoa sure bet at college 2; likewise, ifhe issobadthatcollege2surelyrejectshim,thencollege1followssuit. Moresubtly,we arriveatthefollowingtestableimplicationaboutcollegeacceptancechances: Corollary 1 Asastudent’scaliberrises,theratioofhisacceptancechancesatcollege1 tocollege2rises,asdoestheratioofhisrejectionchancesatcollege2tocollege1. Foranexample,supposethatcalibersignalshavetheexponentialdensityg(s|x)= (1/x)e. The acceptance function is then given by the increasing and concave geometric function ψ(a, as seen in Figure 3 (as long as college 2 has a lower admission standard). The acceptance function is closer to the diagonal when signals are noisier, and farther from it with more accurate signals.For an extreme case, as we approach the noiseless case, a student is either acceptable to neither college, both colleges, or just college 2 (assuming that it has a lower admission standard). The ψ functiontendstoafunctionpassingthrough(0,0),(0,1),and(1,1). Sinceastudent’sdecisionproblemisunchangedbyaffinetransformationsofcostsand benefits,wehenceforthassumeapayoffv=1ofcollege1; so,college2paysu∈(0,1). Throughoutthepaper,wealsorealisticallyassumethatapplicationcostsarenottoohigh relativetothecollegepayoffs—specifically,c<u(v-u)/v=u(1-u)andc<u/4. The firstinequalityguaranteesthatthecurvesMB=cdonotcrosstwice insidetheunitsquare.ThesecondinequalityensuresthattheMB21=ccurvecrosses below the diagonal.If either inequality fails, the analysis trivializes since multiple collegeapplicationsareimpossibleforsomeacceptancefunctions,astheyaretoocostly. Specifically,fortheearlierlocation-scalefamily,ψ(a)risesinthesignalaccuracy1/µ(seePersico (2000)). Easily, the acceptance function tends to the top of the box in Figure 3 as µ → 0, since ψ(a)=1-G(-8)=1,andtothediagonalψ(a11-1)=1-G(0+G(1-a1))=a1asµ→8. Thelimitfunctionisnotwell-defined: Ifastudent’stypeisknown,justthesethreepointsremain. =c/(v-u). Now,1-(c/u)>c/(v-u)exactlywhenc<u(1-u)/v. 21 =chasnorootsonthediagonala =a ifc>u/4. 11 4 EquilibriumAnalysisforColleges 4.1 A SupplyandDemand Approach Each college imust choose an admission standard sas a best response to its rival’s threshold sjiand the student portfolios. With a continuum of students, the resulting enrollment Eiatcollegesi=1,2isanon-stochasticnumber: E2( 1,s 2(x)f(x)dx+ B a2(x)(1-a1(x))f(x)dx, (5) s E1( 1,s 22) = B∪C) a1(x)f(x)dx (4) s = C21a onthestudentapplicationstrategy. s Tounderstand(4)and(5),observethatcaliberxstudentisadmitte uppressingthedependenceofthesetsB,C1 chancea1(x),tocollege2withchancea(x),andfinallytocollege2b a2(x)(1-a12(x)). Also, anyone thatcollege 1admits will enrolla whilecollege2onlyenrollsthosewhoeitherdidnotapplyorgotreje 15If we substitute optimal student portfolios into the enrollme thentheybehavelikedemandcurveswheretheadmissionsstand framework affordsanalogues tothe substitution and income e Theadmissionrateofanycollegeobviouslyfallsinitsanticipateda thestandardseffect. Butthereisacompoundingportfolioeffect — fallsduetoanapplicationportfolioshift. Eachcollege’sapplicant admissionsthreshold. Wethendeduceintheappendixthe“lawo raisesitsadmissionstandard,thenitsenrollmentfalls. Becauseo acollegefacesamoreelasticdemandforslotsthanpredicted pur Aloweradmissionbarwillinviteapplicationsfromnewstudents. Thelawofdemandappliesoutsidethetwocollegesetting. Fo theadmissionsstandardatacollegerises. Absentanystudentpo studentsmeetitstougheradmissionthreshold(thestandardseff Theportfolioadjustmentreinforcesthiseffect. Thosewhohadm toaddthiscollegetotheirportfoliosnowexciseit(theportfolioeffec In consumer demand theory, the “price” of one good affe 15Theportfolioeffectmayactwithalag—forinstance,acollegemayunexpecte standardsoneyear,andseetheirapplicantpoolexpandthenextyearwhenthis 12 16other, and in the two goodworld, they are substitutes. Analogously, we prove in the appendix,thatacollege’senrollmentrisesinitsrival’sadmissionstandard. Thisowes to a portfolio spillover effect. If it grows tougher to gain admission to college i, then thosewhoonlyappliedtoitsrivalcontinuetodoso,somewhowereapplyingtoboth nowapplyjusttoj(which helps collegejwhenitisthelesser school),andalsosome atthemarginwhoappliedjusttoinowalsoaddcollegejtotheirportfolios. Since capacities imply vertical supply curves, we have justified a supply and demandanalysis,inwhichthecollegesaresellingdifferentiatedproducts. Ignoringfornow thepossibility thatsomecollegemightnotfillitscapacity, equilibrium withoutexcess capacityrequiresthatbothmarketsclear: κ1 =E1(s 1,s 2) and κ2 =E2(s 1,s 2) (6) Sinceeachenrollment(demand)functionisfallinginitsownthreshold,wemayinvert theseequations. Thisyieldsforeachschoolithethresholdthat“bestresponds”toits rival’sadmissionsthresholdsjsoastofilltheircapacityκi: 2 =S2(s 1,κ2) (7) s 1 =S1(s 2,κ1) and s Given the discussion of the enrollment functions, we can treat Sias a “best response function”ofcollegei. Itrises initsrival’sadmission standardandfallsinitsowncapacity. Thatis,theadmissionsstandardsatthetwocollegesarestrategiccomplements. Figure4depictsarobustequilibriumasacrossingoftheseincreasingfunctions. By way of contrast, observe that without noise or without application costs, the bettercollegeiscompletelyinsulatedfromtheactionsofitslesserrival—S1isvertical. The equilibrium analysis is straightforward, and there is a unique robust equilibrium. Ineithercase,theapplicantpoolofcollege1isindependentofwhatcollege2does. For when the applicationsignal isnoiseless, just thetopstudents apply tocollege 1. And whenapplicationsarefree,allstudentsapplytocollege1,andwillenrollifaccepted. Withapplicationcostsandnoise,S1isupward-sloping,asapplicationpoolsdepend onbothcollegethresholds. Whencollege2adjustsitsadmissionstandard,thestudent incentivestogambleoncollege1areaffected. Thisfeedbackiscriticalinourpaper. It 16As in consumer theory, complementarity may emerge with three or more goods available. With rankedcolleges1,2,and3,college3maybeharmedbytougheradmissionsatcollege1,ifthisencourages enoughapplicationsatcollege2. 13 S2 2 S2 E1 1 E0 2 E2 1 S1 E0 S 1 Figure4: College Responses and Equilibria. Inbothpanels,thefunctionsS1(solid) andS2(dashed)givepairsofthresholdssothatcolleges1and2filltheircapacitiesinequilibrium. Theleftpaneldepictsauniquerobuststableequilibrium,whiletherightpanelshowsa casewithmultiplerobustequilibria. E0andE2arestable,whileE1isunstable. leadstoaricherinteractionamongthecolleges,andperhapstomultiplerobustequilibria. InFigure4,thefunctionS1issteeperthanS2atthecrossingpoint. Letuscallany suchrobustequilibriumstable. Itisstableinthefollowingsense: Supposethatwhenever enrollmentfallsbelowcapacity,thecollegeeasesitsadmissionstandards,andviceversa. Then thisdynamic adjustment process pushes us back towardsthe equilibrium. Then atthistheoreticallevel,admissionthresholdsactaspricesinaWalrasiantatonnement. Unstable robust equilibria should be rare: They require that a college’s enrollment respondsmoretotheotherschool’sadmissionstandardthanitsown. 17We show in the appendix that a robust stable equilibrium exists, and in any such equilibrium,college1fillsitscapacity,whilecollege2hasexcesscapacityifcollege1is bigenough. Surprisingly,collegespacescangounfilleddespiteinsufficientcapacityfor theapplicantpool. Ifcollege1is“toobig”relativetocollege2,thencollege2isleftwith excesscapacity. Thereisexcessdemandforcollegeslots,andyetduetotheinformational frictions,thereisalsoexcesssupplyofslotsatcollege2,evenat“zeroprice”. Whencollege2hasexcesscapacity,itoptimallyacceptsallapplicants. Sincecollege1 maintainsanadmissionsstandard,collegebehaviorismonotone. Butthisforcesa 2=1 forallstudents,andsotheacceptancefunctiontraversesthetopsideoftheunitsquarein Figure3. Inotherwords,asstudentcaliberrises,theloweststudentsapplytocollege{2}, higherstudentstobothcolleges,andthebeststudentsjustapplytocollege{1}. Letus observeinpassingthatthisisarobustsortingequilibrium. 17College1cannothaveexcesscapacityinarobustequilibrium. Forthenitmustsetthelowestpossiblestandards,whereuponallstudentswouldapplyandbeaccepted,violatingit scapacityconstraint. 14 S2 S2 1 2 1' 1 2' S1 E0 2 E0 E1 S1 E 1 Figure 5: Equilibrium Comparative Statics. The figure shows how the robust equilibriumis affected by changing capacities κ1,κ2. ThebestresponsefunctionsS(solid) and S2(dashed)aredrawn. Theleftpanelconsidersariseinκ1,shiftingS11left,therebylowering bothcollegethresholds. Therightpaneldepictstheanalogousriseinκ2andshiftinS2. 18Sinceadmissionsstandardsarestrategiccomplements,multiplerobustequilibriaare possible(rightpanelofFigure4).Insuchascenario,bothcollegesraisetheirstandards, andyetstudentssendevenmoreapplications,andanotherrobustequilibriumarises. 4.2 Comparative Statics We now continue toexplore the supply anddemand metaphor, andderive some basic comparativestatics. Thepotentialmultiplicityofrobustequilibriamakesacomparative staticsexercisedifficult. Butfortunately,ouranalysisappliestoall robuststableequilibria. Indeed,greatercapacityateithercollegelowersbothcollegeadmissionsthresholds. Thisresultspeakstotheequilibriumeffectsatplay. Greatercapacityatoneschool,or anexogenousdownwardshiftinthe“demand”forslots,reducesthe“price”(admission standard)atbothschools. ThegraphinFigure5provesthisassertion. Forintuition,considerarobustsortingequilibrium,wherestudentsapplyasinFigure3. Letcollege2raiseitscapacityκ(asintherightpanelofFigure5). Fixingthe admission standard s12, this depresses s. The marginal student that was indifferent between applyingtocollege2only(C22)andbothcolleges(B)nowpreferstoapplyto college2only. Sofewerapplytocollege1. Giventhisportfolioshift,college1dropsits admissionstandards. Theleftpaneldepictsthesamecomparativestaticforcollege1. Unlikecollegecapacity,collegepayoffsorapplicationcostsaffectbothbestresponse functions S1and S2. As a result, the comparative statics are not unambiguous, and 18Theonlineappendixcontainsasolvedexamplewithmultiplicity. 15 counter-intuitive resultsmayemerge. Supposethatthepayoffuofcollege2rises, and assume fixed admission standards. Then as we have argued, region Bshifts right in Figure3,therebyincreasingthedemandforcollege2. Atthesametime,thedemandfor college1decreases,assomestudentsceasetosendstretchapplicationstothatcollege. These forces lead to new best reply admission standards, namely an upward shift in the S2locus and a leftward shift in S1. Depending on the strength of these shifts, the new equilibrium admissions thresholds are either both higher, or both lower, or loweratcollege1andhigheratcollege2higherthanbeforetheuincrease; wecannot unambiguouslyascertainwhichcaseistrue. Next,assumethattheapplicationcostcrises, perhapsduetoariseintheSATor ACTcost,orthecommonapplicationfee. ThenS1shiftsleft—forcollege1mustdrop its standards to counter the loss of stretch applications, since we have seen that the regionBshrinks inFigure3. Ontheotherhand, S2shiftsambiguously inthecostc. Forwithfixedstandards,wehaveseenthatcollege2losessafetyandsoloapplications, butnolongerlosesasmanystudentswhosendstretchapplicationstocollege1. Considerinsteadariseinjustonecollege’sapplicationcost,suchasacollegerequiring alongeressayorimposingagreaterfee. Wearguethatinarobustsortingequilibrium,if theapplicationcostateithercollegeslightlyfalls,thentheadmissionstandardatcollege1 rises and its student caliber distribution stochastically worsens. Ifthe applicationcost at college 2 falls, then more students apply, and it is forced to raise its standards. The marginal benefit of a stretch application to college 1 thus rises. To counter this, college1respondswithahigherstandard,butitstillgainsmoreapplicantsatitslower end,anditscaliberdistributionstochasticallyworsens. Bycontrast,college2losesnot onlyitsworststudents,butalsotoponesforwhomitwasinsurance;itscaliberchange isambiguous. Graphically,afallintheapplicationcostatcollege2shiftsSupwards withoutaffectingS12—astheapplicantpoolatcollege1dependsonlyindirectlyonthe college2applicationcostviaportfolioeffectsasthecollege2standardchanges. Theargumentismorecomplexwhentheapplicationcostatcollege1falls,sincethe applicant pools at both colleges depend on it. The direct impact is an expansion in the applicant poolatcollege 1—consisting ofthose who send stretch applications to it—andacontractionintheapplicantpoolofcollege2,triggeringanincreaseinthe admissionstandardatcollege1andadecreaseinthatofcollege2. Thechangesinthe admissions thresholds lead to further portfoliostudent reallocation, and the net effect isaprioriambiguous. Graphically,alowerapplicationcostatcollege1simultaneously 16 s h i f t s S (rightwards)andS2 1 1(1-a2 17 (downwards). Weshowintheappendixthattheportfolio effects at both colleges cancel out for those calibers who send stretch applications to college1;onbalance,itsadmissionstandardrises,andyetitsapplicantpoolwors ens. Thelogicunderlyingthissectiondoesnotessentiallydependontheassumpti onthat therearetwocolleges. Forinstance,whenevercollegeshaveoverlappingapplicantpools, ariseincapacityateitherdepressestheadmissionstandardsatboth. ConsiderthepositivetheoryofthissectioninlightofHoxby(2009). Sheshowsthat during 1962-2007, the median college has become significantly less selective, while at the same time, admissions have become more competitive at the top 10% of colleges. Her explanation for the fall in standards hinges on capacity: the number of freshman placesperhigh-schoolgraduatehasbeenrisingsteadily. ButasweillustrateinFigure5, highercapacity atallschools shoulddepress standards atallschools, viaourspillover effect. Asacountervailingforce,shearguesthatstudentshavesimultaneously become more willing to enroll far from home, raising the relative payoff of selective colleges. Proposition 7 of our online appendix speaks to this insight: starting at a robust and stable sorting equilibrium, a perceived increase in the value of an education at a top schoolleadsittoraiseitsstandardsinsomenewrobustandstableequilibrium. 5 DoCollegesandStudentsSortinEquilibrium? Casualempiricismsuggeststhatthebeststudentsapplytothebestcolleges,and those collegesareinturnthemostselective. Thislogicjustifiesrankingcollegesbasedontheir admissions standards. Curiously, these claims arefalse without stronger assumptions. Weidentifyandexplorethetwopossibletypesofsortingviolationsbystudents. The first violation is seen in the left panel of Figure 6. By Corollary 1, along the acceptancefunction,highertypesenjoyahigherratioofadmissionschancesatc ollege1 tocollege2. Butthisdoesnotimplyahighermarginalbenefitau)ofapplying tocollege1. Sotheacceptancefunctionmaymultiplyslicethroughthecurve(2),where students are indifferent between a stretch application to college 2. This yields a nonmonotonesequenceofapplicationsetsF,{2},{1,2},{2},{1,2},{1}asthecalibe rrises. Thesecondviolationoccurswhencollegeadmissionsstandardsaresufficient lyclose. Forintheextremecase,whenstudentsentertainthesameadmissionchances aatthe twocolleges, themarginalbenefitofaddingasafetyapplication,namely(1-a)au,is notmonotoneina(andthusnotincaliber,either). TherightpanelofFigure6depicts 1.0 1.0 C2 0.8 0.6 B 0.8 B 0.4 0.2 C2 0.6 0.4 P Q C1 Α1 x C1 Α1 x 0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 0.0 0.2 0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 0.0 Figure 6: Non-Monotone Behavior. In the left panel, the signal structure induces a piecewiselinearacceptancefunction. Studentbehaviorisnon-monotone,sincethereareboth lowandhighcaliberstudentswhoapplytocollege2only(C ),whileintermediateonesinsure byapplyingtoboth. Intherightpanel,equalthresholdsatbothcollegesinduce anacceptance function along the diagonal, a1= a22. Student behavior is non-monotone, as both low and high caliber students apply to college 1 only (C1), while middling caliber students apply to both. Suchanacceptancefunctionalsoariseswhencalibersig nalsareverynoisy. onesuchcase—wheretheapplicationsetsareF,{1}, {1,2},{1}ascaliberrises. This violationcanevenoccurwhencollege2setsahigher admissionsstandardthancollege1. To rule out the first sorting violations, it suffices that college 2 offer a low payoff (u<0.5). We show in the Appendix that this ensures that the marginal benefit of additionally applying to college is increasing in caliber. The second sort of violation cannotoccurwhencollege1setsasufficientlyhigher admissionstandardthancollege2. This in particular happens when college 1 is sufficiently smaller than college 2. The thresholdcapacitywillingeneraldependonallthepri mitivesoftheproblem: therival capacity,applicationscost,payoffdifferentialandsi gnalstructure. Α2x Α2x Theorem 2(Non-Sorting and Sorting inEquilibrium) (a)Ifcollege2is“toogood”(i.e.,u>0.5),thenthereexis tsacontinuousMLRPdensity g(s|x)thatyieldsarobuststableequilibriumwithnonmonotonestudentbehavior. (b)Ifcollege2issmallenoughrelativetocollege1,the ncollege2setsahigheradmissions standardthancollege1insomerobustequilibrium. (c)Ifcollege1issmallenoughrelativetocollege2,and college2isnottoogood(namely, u=0.5),thenthereareonlyrobustsortingequilibriaan dnocollegehasexcesscapacity. Thechallengeinprovingthistheoremistoshowth atallofnon-monotonebehavior 18 outlined above can happen in equilibrium. For part (a), we construct a robust nonmonotoneequilibriumbystartingwiththeacceptancefunctiondepictedintheleftpanel ofFigure6,whichconstrainstherelationshipsbetweenadmissionschancesacrosscolleges to be some mapping a2(x) = h(a(x)). We then construct a particular acceptance chancea11(x)sothattheinducedstudentbehaviorandacceptanceratesgiven(a 1,h(a)) equate college capacities and enrollments. Finally, we show that these two mappings satisfytherequirementsofTheorem1andthereforecanbegeneratedbyMLRPsignals and monotone standards. For part (b), we show that that by perturbing a robust equilibriumwithequaladmissionschancesbymakingcollege2smaller,wegetarobust equilibriumwithnon-monotonestandards. Finally,part(c)turnsonshowingthatwhen κ11isrelativelysmall,thecrossingofthebest-responsefunctionsmustoccuratapoint wherecollege1setshighenoughstandardsthatlowcaliberstudentsdon’tapplythere. 19,20All told, parts (a) and (b) show that sorting fails in some robust equilibria, which is surprising given how well behaved the signal structure is. The take-away is that in simultaneoussearchproblems,themarginalbenefitsbothofgamblingupandofinsuring neednotbemonotoneintype,eveninequilibrium. Sortingcanfailinamorestriking sense that undercuts how colleges are ranked: While colleges are often ranked based onobservablecharacteristicsofmatriculatingstudents,suchastheaverageSATscore, studentsattheworsecollegecaninfacthaveahighermeancaliber. The sorting failures in this section exploit some but not allofthe structure ofour simple two college world. In particular, assume two tiers of colleges, a top tier 1 and alesser tier 2. We prove in the online appendix thatstudent non-monotonicity result still persists in the tiered college world. But college standards must be monotone, as essentially arguedin ChadeandSmith (2006). Forifnot, then no student would ever applytotier2,sinceitwouldofferalowerexpectedpayoff. 21For an insightful counterpoint, consider what happens when students are limited to just a single application, as it is sometimes the case.Recalling the left panel in Figure2,weseethatthediagonallinea1u=a2,andtheindividualrationalequalities 19ThewidelyreadUSNewsandWorldReportcollegerankingsusessuchstatistics. 20ThiscanbeillustratedusingtherightpanelofFigure6. Considerarobustequilibriumwithequal admissionsstandardsatthetwocolleges. Iff(x)concentratesmostofits massontheintervaloflow calibers who apply just to college1, then the averagecaliber ofstudents enrolledatcollege1 will be strictlysmallerthanthatatcollege2. Thisexamplecanbeadjustedslightlysothatcollege2ismore selectivethancollege1. (Seeouronlineappendixforafleshedoutexampleofthisphenomenon.) 21InBritain,allcollegeapplicationsgothroughUCAS,acentralizedclearinghouse. Amaximumof fiveapplicationsisallowed. 19 a2u= a1= c, jointly partition the application space into three relevant parts. But withanyacceptancefunctionwiththefallingsecantproperty,lowtypesapplynowhere, middle types apply tocollege 2, and high types apply tocollege 1. It should come as nosurprise thatthere isaunique robustequilibrium. Soitturns outthatthesorting failuresinTheorem2(a)and(b)requireportfolioapplications. 6 GeneralIncompleteInformationAboutCalibers A.WhenStudentsDoNotKnowtheirCalibers. Wehaveassumedthatcolleges observe conditionally independent evaluations of the students’ true calibers. At the oppositeextreme,onemightenvisionahypotheticalworldwherecollegesknowstudent calibers,andstudentsseenoisyconditionallyindependentsignalsofthem. Yetobserve thatthisisinformationallyequivalenttoaworldinwhichstudentsknowtheircalibers, andcollegesobserveperfectlycorrelatedsignals. Foranystudentseesasignalequalto t+“noise”,whilebothcollegesseethestudentcalibert. This embedding suggests how we might capture the world in which students and collegesalikeonlyseenoisyconditionallyiidsignalsofcalibers. Weargueintheappendix thatthisisaspecialcaseofthefollowingworld: (⋆)Studentsknowtheircalibersandcollegesobserveaffiliatednoisysignalsofthem. Thus,wecanwithoutlossofgeneralityassumethatstudentsknowtheircalibersand collegesvarybytheirsignalaffiliation. Observethatinthisworld,Theorem1remainsa validdescriptionofhowtheunconditionalacceptancechancesatthetwocollegesrelate. B.PerfectlyCorrelatedSignals. Thisbenchmarkishighlyinstructive. Suppose first that the two colleges observe perfectly correlated signals of student calibers. As we mentioned above, this is akin to observing the caliber of each applicant. The key (counterfactual)featurehereisthatifastudentisacceptedbythemoreselectivecollege, then so is he at the less selective one. This immediately implies that s1> s2in equilibrium, forotherwisenoonewouldapplytocollege2. SocontrarytoTheorem2, collegebehaviormustbemonotoneinanyequilibrium. The analysis of this case differs in a few dimensions from §3.1. Since s 1 > s 2 1 +(a2 -a1 22)u-2c. Unlikebefore, MB21 =(a2 -a1)u=c and MB12 =a1(1-u)=c (8) , applyingtobothcollegesnowyieldspayoffa Wes uppressthecaliberxargumentoftheunconditionalacceptancechanceai(x)atcollegei=1,2. 20 22 becauseadmissiontocollege1guaranteesadmissiontocollege2. Inthisinformational world,bothoptimalityequationsarelinear,andthelatterisvertical(seeFigure7). Assume thatcollege1issufficiently moreselective thancollege2. Thenthelowest caliberapplicantsapplytocollege2—namely, thosewhoseadmissionchanceexceeds c/u. Studentssogoodthattheiradmissionchanceatcollege1isatleastc/(1-u)add astretchapplication,providedcollege2admitsthemwithchancec/u(1-u)ormore. In Figure 7, this occurs when the acceptance function crosses above the intersection point of the curves MB21= cand MB12= c.23Since the marginal benefit MBis independentoftheadmissionchanceatcollege2,MB1212>cforallhighercalibers. But monotone behavior for stronger caliber students requires another assumption. Considerthemarginbetweenapplyingjusttocollege1,oraddingasafetyapplication. Thetopcaliberstudentswillapplytocollege1only,sincetheiradmissionchanceisso high. Butthe behavior ofslightly lesser student calibers is trickier, asthe acceptance functioncanmultiplycrossthelineMB21=c.2425Underslightlystrongerassumptions, theacceptancefunctionisconcave;thisprecludessuchperversemultiple-crossings,and impliesmonotonestudentbehavior. Consider now thepossibility ofnon-monotonestudent behavior. Absent aconcave acceptancefunction,theprevioussortingfailureowingtomultiple-crossingsarises. But evenwithaconcaveacceptancefunction,asortingfailurearisesifcollege1isnotsufficientlycho osierthancollege2. Forthenasuitablydrawnconcaveacceptancefunction couldconsecutivelyhitregionsC1,B,thenC1,andasortingfailureensues. Having explored the impact of correlation on college-student sorting, we now flesh outitseffectoncollegefeedbacks. SinceMB12isindependentoftheadmissionthreshold at college 2 in (8), the pool of applicants to college 1 is unaffected by changes in s. Hence,theS126locusisverticalovermostofitsdomain.2Thebettercollegeisinsulated from the decisions of its weaker rival, and the setting is not as rich as our baseline conditionallyiidcase. ItisobviousfromFigure7thattherobustequilibriumisunique. C.AffiliatedCollegeEvaluations. Wenowturntothegeneralcaseofassumption 23Namely, atthe mutualintersectionofregionsC 1,C2,andBinFigure7. Byinequality(13), this holdsunderourhypothesisthatcollege1issufficientlychoosierthancollege2. 24ForasseeninFigure7,thatlinealsohasastrictlyfallingsecant. 25Concavityholdswhenever-Gx(s|x)islog-supermodular. Thisistruewhenwefurtherrestrictto locationfamilies(liketheNormal)orscalefamilies(suchasexponential). 26ThelocusS12verticalifcollege1issufficientlymoreselectivethancollege2. Forthentheacceptance functionishighenoughthatittraversesregionB,andsomestudentssendmultipleapplications. Ifnot, thentheacceptancefunctioncouldhitCandthenC,bipassingregionB. Inthatcase,themarginal applicanttocollege1dependsons2,an dhenceS11isnotvertical. 21 1.0 C2 0.8 0.6 S2 1 2 E0 B C1 0.4 0.2 0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 0.0 Α1 x Figure7: StudentBe haviorwith PerfectlyC orrelatedSi gnals. Theshadedr egions depict the optimal portfolio choices for students when colleges observe perfectly correlated signals. UnlikeFigur e2,theMB12 =ccurvesep aratingregio nsBandC2is vertical. TheS1 curveattheri ghtisvertical (uptoapoint) ,sincecolleg e 2nolongerim posesanext ernality oncollege1 whentheset S 1 ofcalibersse ndingmultipl eapplication sisnonempt y. (⋆). Eachstud entknows hiscaliber x,andcoll egessee signalss1 ,softhem, withan affiliatedj ointdensi tyg(s1,s2| x).272Sinc eaccepta nceandre jectionby college1i sgood andbadn ews,resp ectively,it intuitively followsth at aA 2=a2 and aR 2 A =aR 2 2 (9) H e r e , a A 2 A 2 >aare the respectiv e acceptan M B 2 1 =aR 2 2 2 A2 ce chances at college 2 given acceptan ce andreject ionatcolle ge1. Forinstan ce, 1=a2>aR 2withperf ectlycorr elation. Butinthec onditiona llyiidcase ,college2i sunaffect edbythed ecisionof college1, and soa=a. Since these areintuiti vely opposite ends ofanaffili ationspe ctrum, wecallev aluations moreaffili ated ifthecond itionalacc eptancec hanceaat college2 ishigherf oranygiv enuncon Α2x ditionalac ceptance chancea. Let’sfirsts eehowa ffiliationa ffectsstu dentappli cations. Inthismor egeneral setting, =(1-a1)aR 2u and MB12 This subsumes the marginal analysis forour conditionall y iid and perfectly correlated cases: (1)–(2) and (8). Relative to these benchmark s, the acceptanc e curse (or the 27Asisstan dard,thism eansthatg obeysthe monotonel ikelihoodr atioproper tyforevery fixedx. 22 =a1(1-aA 2u). (10) “acceptanceblessing”)conferredbycollege1’stwopossibledecisionslessensthemarginal gainofanextraapplicationtoeithercollege—duetoinequality(9). Moreintuitively, double admission is more likely when signals are more affiliated. In our graph, this is reflectedbyarightshiftofthecurveMB12=c,andaleftshiftofMB21=c. Inother words, foranygiven collegeadmission standards, students send both fewer stretch and safetyapplicationswhencollegeevaluationsaremoreaffiliated. Wenextexplorehowaffiliatedevaluationsaffectscollegebehavior. Considerthebest replylocusS1ofcollege1. Itisupward-slopingwithconditionallyiidcollegeevaluations, and vertical with perfectly correlated evaluations. We argue that it is upward-sloping with affiliated evaluations, and grows steeper as evaluations grow more affiliated. In otherwords,ourbenchmarkconditionallyiidcasedeliversrobustresultsabouttwo-way collegefeedbacks. Perfectlycorrelatedevaluationsthereforeignorestheeffectofthelesser onthebettercollege,andsoislessreflectiveoftheaffiliatedcase. We first show that the best response curve Sslopes upward with imperfect affiliation. Forletcollege1’sadmissionstandards11rise. Thenitsunconditionalacceptance chance a1falls for every student. The marginal student pondering a stretch applicationmust thenfallinorderforcollege1tofillitscapacity(6). Optimality MB=c in(10)nextrequiresthatthisstudent’sconditionalacceptancechanceaA 212fall. Thisonly happensifhisunconditionalchancea2fallstoo—i.e.thestandardsrises. Next, college 1’s best response curve S12slopes up more steeply when college evaluations are more strongly affiliated. For as affiliation rises, the marginal student sees a greater fall in his admission chance aA 2. So his unconditional chance afalls more too, and college 2’s admission standard s22drops more than before (see Figure 7), as claimed. Asanaside,sincerobustequilibriumisuniquewithperfectlycorrelatedcollege evaluations,uniquenessintuitivelyholdsmoreoftenwhenweareclosertothisextreme. Finally,weconsiderhowtheequilibriumsortingresultTheorem2changeswithaffiliation. Byexamining(10),weseethataswetransitionfromconditionallyiidtoperfectly correlated signals with increasing affiliation, the region of multiple applicationsshrinks monotonically. Thissimpleinsighthasimportantimplicationsforsortingbehavior. By standard continuity logic, forvery low orhigh affiliation, sorting obtains and fails exactly as in the respective conditional independent or perfectly correlated cases. More strongly, thenegativeresultinTheorem2(b)failsformoderatelyhighaffiliation: For then nonmonotone college behavior is impossible since the locus MB21=cin (8) lies strictlyabovethediagonal,andthusthesameholdsfor(10)withsufficientlyaffiliated 23 signals. Sotheacceptancefunctionwouldliebelowthediagonalifadmissionstandards were inverted, and no student would ever apply to college 2. Lastly, the logic for the positive sorting result of Theorem 2(c)is still valid: bothstudent and college behavioraremonotoneifcollege2isnottoosmall andnottoogood,andiftheacceptance functionisconcave—appealingtothelogicforperfectlycorrelatedsignals. 7 TheSpilloverEffectsof Affirmative Action We now explore the effects of an affirmative action policy.28Slightly enriching our model,wefirstassumethatafractionfoftheapplicantpoolbelongstoatargetgroup. Thismaybeanunder-represented minority, butitmayalsobeamajoritygroup. For instance, many states favor their own students at state colleges — Wisconsin public collegescanhaveatmost25%out-of-statestudents. Justaswell,somecollegesstrongly valueathletesorstudentsfromlow-incomebackgrounds. Weassumeacommoncaliber distribution,sothatthereisnootherreasonfordifferentialtreatmentoftheapplicants. Assume thatstudents honestly reporttheir“targetgroup”statusontheirapplications. Reflectingthecolleges’desireforamorediversestudentbody,letcollegeiearna bonuspi=0foreachenrolledtargetstudent. Collegesmaysetdifferentthresholdsfor thetwogroups. Ifcollegeioffera“discount”∆itotargetapplicants,thentherespective standardsfornon-targetandtargetgroupsare(s1,s2)and(s1-∆1,s2-∆2). Akinto thirddegreepricediscrimination,nowcollegesequatetheshadowcostofcapacityacross groupsforthemarginallyadmittedstudent. Soateachcollege,theexpectedpayoffof themarginaladmitsfromthetwogroupsshouldcoincide—exceptatacornersolution, whenacollegeadmitsallstudentsfromagroup. Thisyieldstwonewequilibriumconditionsthataccountforthefactthatexpost,collegesbehaver ationally,andequatetheir expectedvaluesoftargetandnon-targetapplicants. Alongwithcollegemarketclearing (6),equilibriumentailssolvingfourequationsinfourunknowns. Theanalysisissimplerifweassumeprivatevalues,andwethusfocusonthiscase, andlaterrevisitcommonvalues. Sincecollegescaredirectlyaboutthesignalobserved withprivatevalues,equalizationofthemarginaladmitsofthetwogroupsi=1,2reduces tosi=si-∆i+pi,andso∆i=pi. Thatis,the‘discount’affordedtoastudentfrom thetargetgroupequalstheadditionalpayoffacollegeenjoysfromadmittingastudent 28For recent treatment of complementary affirmative action issues, see Epple,Romano,andSieg (2008),Hickman(2010),GroenandWhite(2004),andCursandSingell(2002). 24 fromthetargetversusthenon-targetgroup. Thus,collegepreferencesfortargetgroup studentstranslatedirectlyintoadmissionstandarddiscountsforthatgroup. Theorem 3(Affirmative Action) Assume private values, a robust stable equilibrium, and p1= p2= 0. As the preference for a target group at one college rises, that college favors those students and penalizes non-target students. As the preference fortargetstudentsatbothcollegesrise,bothfavorthemandpenalizenon-targetstudents. Observetheindirecteffectofstudentpreferences: Nontargetstudentsfacestifferadmissionstandardssincetheshadowvalueofcapacityisnowhi gher. Theassumptionthat p1= p2= 0 is important, as it precludes some complex feedback effects that emerge whenthereisalreadyapreferencefortargetstudentsattheoutset. Forasharperinsight,specializethesignaldistributiontothelocationfamilyG(s-x). Suppose that both colleges exhibit identical preference pfor the target group. Since ∆=pforbothcolleges,theacceptancerelationisidentical forbothgroupsandgiven by ψ(a1)=1-G(s2-s1+G-1(1-a1))(thediscounts cancel outin theargument of Gfor the target group). This implies that caliber xfrom the target group applies exactlyasiftheywereatypex+pfromthenon-targetgroup: atestableclaim. If instead only one college, say 1, has a preference pforthe target group, then it setsadiscount∆1=p11. Theacceptancerelationforthetargetgroupisthenψ(a)= 1-G(s2-s1+∆1+G-1(1-a12)),whichiseverywherebelowthatofthenon-target groupψ(a2)=1-G(s2-s1+G-1(1-a1)). Asaresult,inarobustsortingequilibrium, target-groupstudentswillgambleupandapplytocollege1moreoften,andinsurewith anapplicationtocollege2lessoften,thannon-targetgroupstudents. We have focused in this section on private values as it leads to a simpler analysis. Consider the common values benchmark. Equalization of the expected payoff of the marginaladmitsfromthetwogroupsateachcollegethenyieldsthericherconditions: 1 -∆1,target] = E[X|s 1 E[X+p1|s=s 2 -∆2,target,accepts] = E[X|s i 2,non-target,accepts] 2|s=s i i i 25 ,non-target] E[X+p =p Here,Xisthestudentcaliber. Noticethatnolongerdowehave∆ nowdependsonp ;rather,thediscount ∆inanonlinearfashionviatheconditionalexpectations. As before,alongwith(6),equilibriumamountstosolvingfourequationsinfourunknowns. Let us explore how the first result in Theorem 3 changes for the common values settingofthepaper. Assumearobustsortingequilibrium,aswellasanaturalstability requirementonshadowvaluesofthegroupsofstudents(seeonlineappendix). Thenas thepreferenceforatargetgroupatcollege1risesfromthenopreferencecasep 1=p2= 0,itfavorsthosetargetstudents, butnowcollege2insteadpenalizesthem. Butwhen thepreferencefortargetstudentsattheworsecollege2rises,bothcollegesfavorthem. 29Inotherwords,anasymmetry emergesundercommonvalues. Whenonlycollege1 favorsatargetgroupofstudents, college2mustcounterthiswithapenalty, owingto two effects. First, the best favored students that previously applied to college 2 now justapplytocollege1,andthusthepooloftargetapplicantsatcollege2worsens. This portfolioeffectwaspresentwithprivatevalues. Second,college2confrontsanacceptance curse. Astudentwhoenrollsthereeitheronlyappliedtoit,oralsoappliedtocollege1 —andwasrejected. Sotheeventthatastudentenrollsatcollege2isaworsesignalof hiscaliberifcollege1hasfavoredthem. 8 ConcludingRemarks Wehave formulated thecollege admissions problemfortworanked colleges with fixed capacities in order to study the effects of two frictions in equilibrium. Student types areheterogeneous andcolleges only partiallyobserve their types. College applications arecostly,andstudentsthereforefaceanontrivialportfoliochoice. Thismodeladmits atractableseparablesolutioninstages—studentportfoliosreflecttheadmissionstandards,an dcollegesthencompeteasiftheywereBertrandduopolists. Thisframework is the only equilibrium model that speaks to the recent empirical explorations of studentapplicationbehavior(AveryandKane(2004);Pallais(2009);CarrellandSacerdote (2012);HoxbyandAvery(2012)). Wehavecharacterizedinatestablefashionhowstudentadmissionchancesco-moveas theircalibersimprove,showinghowtheiroptimalportfoliochoicesoverstretchandsafety schools differ. We have have discovered that even in this highly monotone matching world, sorting of students and colleges fails absent stronger assumptions. For better studentsneednotalwaysapplymoreaggressively: Iftheworsecollegeiseithertoogood ortoosmall,ortheapplicationprocessisnoisyenough,onestudentmaygambleonthe bettercollegewhileamoretalentedonedoesnot. Likewise,collegeadmissionsstandards neednotreflecttheirquality—theworsecollegemayoptimallyimposehigherstandards 29Thisasymmetricresultshouldspeaktostudies,likeKane(1998),thatfoundthataffirmativeaction fordisadvantagedminoritiesisgenerallyconfinedtoselectiveschools—aswethinkofcollege1. 26 30if it is small enough. Large public schools might well be punished in college rankings publicationsthatuseSATscoresofenrolledstudentsinrankingschools. Turning to affirmative action, we predict that favored minority applicants apply asambitiouslyasif theyweremajorityapplicantsofhighercaliber. CardandKrueger (2005)investigatewhathappenedwhenaffirmativeactionwaseliminatedatstateschools in California and Texas. They find a small but statistically significant drop in the probability that minority applicants send their SAT scores to elite state schools, but find no such effect for highly qualified minority applicants (those with high SATs or GPAs). Thisisconsistentwithourfindingthatlowercaliberminorityapplicantssend stretchapplicationsunderaffirmativeaction. While the two college world is restrictive, it is the most parsimonious model with portfolioeffects,stretchandsafetyschools,andadmissionstandardssetbycompeting schools. Theportfolioeffectsinduceimportantandrealisticinterdependencies missing fromallfrictionlessmodelsofstudent-collegematching. Sinceassortativematchingcan fail in this setting, it can fail more generally. Our baseline model has assumed that studentsperfectlyknowtheircalibersandcollegesonlyobservethemwithnoise,butwe havearguedthattheportfolioeffectsandsortingfailuresmonotonicallydiminishaswe shift toward the opposite extreme when colleges have superior information. And even inthislimit,studentssendstretchandsafetyapplications,andsortingcanfail. A Appendix: OmittedProofs A.1 Colleges Optimally Employ Admissions Thresholds Letχ(s)betheexpectedvalueofthestudent’scalibergiventhatheappliestocollegei, hissignaliss,andheaccepts. Collegeioptimallyemploysathresholdruleif,andonly if,χii(s)increasesins. Forcollege1thisisimmediate,sinceg(s|x)enjoystheMLRP property. College2facesanacceptancecurse,andsoχ2(s)is: xg(s|x)f(x)dx+ Bg( xG(s 1|x)g(s|x)f(x)dx (11) s|x)f(x)dx+ B C 2 G(s 1 7 χ2(s)= C2 2|x)g(s|x)f(x)dx Avery,Glickman,Hoxby,andMetrick (2004) develop an innovative revealed 30 preference college ranking based on enrollment decisions by students admitted at multiple sc and public schools areindeed rankedhigherunder their approach. One difficulty for themis tha initial application portfolios are endogenous. Explicitly modeling the application decision using model of portfolio choice—asinFu(2010)—maybehelpfulinresolvingtheeconometricinferenceproblemsthatresult. B∪C22hwhere we denoteby C312theset ofcalibersapplying to2only, andB thoseapplyingto both.Write(11)asχ2(s)= B∪C(x|s)= (I2Cxh22(x|s)dxusingindicatorfunctionnotation:(x)+I(IC2BG(s(t)+IB1G(s1|t))g(s|t)f(t)dt , (12) |x))g(s|x)f(x) (x|s)hasth 2 2 eMLRP.Therefore,χ2 i 2 1(S),s 1(S)ands 1 henthe‘density’h2 (s)increasesins. T Noticethatthesameresultsobtainforanyincreasingfunctionχ(s)—inparticular, ifitistheidentityfunction,asintheprivatevaluescase. A.2 Simultaneous versus Sequential Timing We claim that the subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE) outcomes of the two-stage game withstudentsmovingfirstcoincidewiththeNashequilibriaoftheone-shotgame. First,considertheoutcomeofaSPEofthetwo-stagegame,wherestudentschoose applicationS=S(·)andthencollegeschoosestandardss(S). Thencolleges mustbestrespondtoeachotherandtoS(whichisrealizedwhentheychoose). Also, sincestudentscanforecasthowcollegeswouldrespondtoSinanSPEofthetwo-stage game,theirapplicationsmustbestrespondtothestandardss(S)ands(S). Soitis anequilibriumoftheone hasmeasure zero, hecannot affectthe college -shotgame. standardsbyadjustinghisapplicationstrategy. Hence,anyequilibrium(S,s(S))of Conversely, sincetheone-shotgameisalsotheoutcomeanSPEofthetwo-stagegame. each student A.3 AcceptanceFunctionShape: Proof of Theorem 1 1 >s 2 2 owetothecontinuityofourfunctionsai(x)in§3.2. sinceG(s 31 oavoidduplication,weassumes T throughouttheproof. (⇒)TheAcceptanceFunctionhastheDoubleSec First, 1|x)iscontinuouslydifferentiableinx,theacceptancefunctioniscontinuous on (0,1]. Given a= 1-G(s|ξ(a,s)), partial derivatives have positive We assume that students employ pure strategies,which followsfromour analys optimizationin§3.1. MeasurabilityofsetsBandC 28 slopesξa,ξs = -Gx(s ∂ψ ∂s2 = -g(s = -Gx(s ∂ψ ∂a1 >0. ∂ψ ∂s1 Differentiating(3), 2|ξ(a1,s 1 ))<0. 1,s PropertiesofthecdfGimplyψ(0,s 1))and1-G(s|ξ(a1,s 1,sinces 1,s (1 3) 1,s 2)=0andψ(1,s 1)>0 1))ξa(a1,s 2|ξ(a1,s 1)>0 1,s 2 1 1))ξs(a1,s 2|ξ(a1,s 1 >s 1))arethenstrictlylog-supermodularin(s,a1 2: )=1. Thelimitsofψas thresholdsapproachthesupremumandinfimumowetolimitpropertiesofG. Now, G(s|x) and 1-G(s|x) are strictly log-supermodular in (s,x) since the density g(s|x) obeys the strict MLRP. Since x = ξ(a1) is strictly increasing in a, G(s|ξ(a). So thesecantslopesbelowstrictlyfallina 1-ψ(a1 = G(s 11|ξ(a2|ξ 1 (a1)) . 11|ξ(a2|ξ(a1)) an d ψ(a1) = 1-G(s )) 1-G(s ) 1-a )) G(s a1 (⇐) D eriving a Signal Distribution. Conversely, fix a function hwith the doublesecantpropertyandasmoothlymonotoneontofunctiona1(x). Also,puta(x)= h(a1(x)),sothata2(x)>a12(x). Wemustfindacontinuoussignaldensityg(s|x)with thestrictMLRPandthresholdss1>s2thatrationalizethehastheacceptancefunction consistentwiththesethresholdsandsignaldistribution. Step1: ADiscreteSignalDistribution. Consideradiscretedistributionwith realizationsin{-1,0,1}: g1(x)=a1(x),g0(x)=a2(x)-a1(x)andg-1(x)=1-a(x). Indeed,foreachcaliberx,gi2=0andsumto1. ThisobeysthestrictMLRPbecause g0(x) a2(x)-a(x) a11(x) h(a1(x)) a1(x) g1(x) = = -1, isstrictlydecreasingbythefirstsecantpropertyofh,and g0(x) a2(x)-a(x) 1-a21(x) 1-a1(x) g-1(x) = =-1+ 1-h(a1(x)) isstrictlyincreasinginxbythesecondsecantpropertyofh. Let the 1|x) = g-1 college thresholds be (s1,s2) = (0.5,-0.5). Then G(s 0(x) = 1-a1(x) and G(s 2|x) = g-1(x) = 1-a2(x). Rearranging yields a1 2|ξ(s 2|x). Invertinga1(x)andrecallingthata2 =h(a1 21|x)anda2 ,a1 (x)+ g(x) = 1-G(s(x)=1-G(s), weobtaina=h(a1)=1-G(s1)) ,therebyshowingthathistheacceptance 29 functionconsistentwiththissignaldistributionandthresholds. Step 2: A Continuous Signal Density. To create an atomless signal distrii={-1,0,1}gibution,wesmooththeatomsusingacarefullychosenkernelfunction. Defineg(s|x)= (x)k(x,s-i)andletk(x,s)=1(|s|<0.5)(1+2sw(x)),wheretheweightingfunction w(x)hasrange[0,1]. Thetransformationismass-preservingsinceasw(x) transfersmasstoapoints>0itremovesthecorrespondingmassfrom-s. Theweightingfunctiondeterminestheshapeofthesmoothing,sowenowfindconditionsonw( x) suchthatthestrictMLRPholds. Considers0<s∈(-1.5,1.5),andsupposefirstthat theyarebothclosetothesameatomiinthat|sj1-i|<0.5forj=0,1. Then g(s1|x) gi(x)(1+2(s1-i)w(x)) 1+2(s1-i)w(x) g(s0|x) = gi(x)(1+2(s0-i)w(x)) = 1+2(s0-i)w(x) whichwillbestrictlyincreasinginxifw(x)isastrictlyincreasingfunction. Imposing thisrestrictiononw(x),iftheyinheritmassfrompointsi<j,wehave g(s1|x) gk(x)(1+2(s-k)w(x)) g(s0|x) = gi1(x)(1+2(s0-i)w(x)) Asufficientconditionforthistobestrictlyincreasinginxalmosteverywhereisthatit isweakly increasingwhens1-k=-0.5ands0-i=0.5(i.e.gki(x) g(x) (1-w(x)) (1+w(x))gkincreasing ∀k>i∀x). Sincei(x) g(x)is strictly increasing, choosing a strictly increasing w(x) with appropriatelyboundedderivativesachievesthis. A.4 MonotoneStudentStrategies Claim 1 Student behavior is monotone in caliber if (a) college 2 has payoff u=0.5, and(b)college2imposesalowenoughadmissionsstandardrelativetocollege1. By part (a), if a student applies to college 1, then any better student does too. By part(b),ifastudentappliestocollege2,thenanyworsestudentappliesthereornowhere. Theproofproceedsasfollows. Wefirstshowthat(i)u=0.5impliesthatifacaliber appliestocollege1,thenanyhighercaliberappliesaswell. Second,we(ii)producea sufficientconditionthatensuresthattheadmissionsthresholdatcollege2issufficiently lower than that of college 1, so that if a caliber applies to college 2, then any lower caliberwhoappliestocollegesendsanapplicationtocollege2,andcalibersatthelower tailapplynowhere. Fromthesetworesults,monotonestudentbehaviorensues. 30 ProofofPart(i),Step1. Wefirstshowthattheacceptancefunctiona2 1=(1/u)(1-c/a1)(i.e., MB12 1=a1(1-a2 =ψ(a1 =1,(ii) MB12 2 [(1-ψ(a1 1 )u)=c. =0andends ata1 1 ) crosses au)=c)onlyoncewhenu=0.5. Since (i)theacceptance functionstartsata=c starts at a=cand ends at a=c/(1-u), and (iii) both functions are continuous, thereexistsacrossingpoint. Andtheyintersectwhena1(1-ψ(a1 )u)a1]'=1-uψ(a1)-a1uψ'(a1)>1-uψ(a1)-uψ(a1)=1-2uψ(a )=1-2u=0, falling in a1 (Theorem 1), i.e. ψ'(a1 where the first inequality exploits ψ(a1)/a1 12 1)/a1;thenexttwoinequalitiesuseψ(a1 whentheacceptancerelationhitsa2 1 1(x) <a1(y) and a2(x) <a2 2(x)/a1 2 =(1-c/a1 2(y)/a1(y),andthusa2(y)u=a1 (x)u>a1 2 12 1,¯a2)= =c/ u(1a1),i .e. MB u(1 1-4c/u)/2 —pointPinthe 1,¯a2)if 21 )< ψ(a)=1andu=0.5. SinceMBisrisingin a)/u,theintersectionisunique. Proof of Part (i), Step 2. We now show that Step 1 implies the following singlecrossingpropertyintermsofx: ifcaliberxappliestocollege1(i.e.,if1∈S(x), then any caliber y >xalso applies to college 1 (i.e., 1 ∈ S(y)). Suppose not; i.e., assume that either S(y) = Ø or S(y) = {2}. If S(y) = Ø, then S(x) = Ø as well, as a(y), contradicting the hypothesis that 1 ∈ S(x). If S(y)={2}, then there are two cases: S(x)={1}or S(x)={1,2}. The first cannot occur, forby Theorem1a(x)>a(y)implies a(x),contradictingS(x)={1}. Inturn,thesecondcaseisruledoutbythe monotonicityofMBderivedabove,ascaliberyhasgreaterincentivesthanxtoadd college1toitsportfolio,andthusS(y)={2}cannotbeoptimal. ProofofPart(ii),Step1. Wefirstshowthatiftheacceptancefunctionpasses abovethepoint(¯a1-4c/u)/2,(1 rightpanelofFigure6—thenthereisauniquecrossingofthea cceptancefunctionand a=c. Now,theacceptancefunctionpassesabove(¯a ψ(¯a1, 1,s 2)= ¯a2. (14) s 1 ands 2. Rewrite(14)usingTheorem1ass 2 =η(s 1)<s 1 2 Thisconditionrelatess , requiringalargeenough“wedge”betweenthestandardsofthetwocolleges. Toshowthat(14)impliesauniquecrossing,considerthesecantofa =c/u(1-a1 2 =c). Ithasanincreasingsecantifandonlyifa1 1 2 1 l = c/ua1(1-a1) in a1. Notice also that MB 1l 2)=(1/2 1-4c/u/2,1/2 2 h 1,ah 2 ) (thecurveMB/a=1/2. Toseethis, differentiate a= cintersects the diagonala=a1atthepoints(a,a211-4c/u/2)and (a)=(1/2+ 1-4c/u/2,1/2+ 1-4c/u/2)>( 1/2,1/2).31 Condition(14)givesψ(al 1,s 1,s 2)>al 2. S inces 2 <s 1,wehaveψ(a1,s 1,s 2)=a2 =catorabove(ah 1 h= 1 ¯a1. Thus,theacceptancefunctioncrossesMB21 foralla1 1(x)<a2(y)/a1 21 ,ah 2 2 ). Andsincea>1/2,thesecantofMB=cmustbeincreasingatanyintersectionwith theacceptancefunction. Hence,theremustbeasinglecrossingpoint. ProofofPart(ii),Step2. Wenowshowthatthissinglecrossingpropertyina impliesanotherinx: Ifcaliberxappliestocollege2(i.e.,if2∈S(x)),thenanycaliber y <xthat applies somewhere also applies to college 2 (i.e., 2 ∈ S(y) if S(y) =Ø). Suppose not; i.e., assume that S(y)={1}. Then there are two cases: S(x) = {2}or S(x)={1,2}. Thefirstcannotoccur,forbyTheorem1a2(x)/a(y),and thusa(x)u=a1(x)impliesa2(y)u>a1(y),contradictingS(x)={2}. Thesecondcase isruledoutbythemonotonicityofMBgivencondition(14),ascaliberyhasgreater incentivesthanxtoapplytocollege2,andthusS(y)={1}cannotbeoptimal. Finally, S(y)=Øifa221(y)u<cby(14),whichhappensforlowcalibersbelowathreshold. A.5 TheLaw of Demand Claim 2 (TheFalling Demand Curve) Ifeithercollegeraisesits admissionstandard,thenitsenrollmentfalls,andthusitsrival’senrollmentrises. 1 rises, since the argument for s 2 1 1 32 2 2,thena2(x)u-c=0anda (x)u=a1 1 2 1 1,sincea1 We only consider the case when is similar. Also, we focus onthe nontrivial portfolioeffect in each case s standard effect ofan increaseinsisimmediate: itlowersenrollmentincollege1,andraisesitincollege2. Proof Step1: The at college 1 Shrinks. Whensrises, the acceptance relation shifts up b thus the above type sets change as well. Fixacaliberx∈Corx∈F,sotha /∈S(x).Wewillshowthatxcontinues toapplyeithertocollege2onlyornowhere,andthusthepoolofapplicantsat shrinksbecausea(x)declines. Ifx∈C2(x)fallswhilea(x),and thiscontinuestoholdaftertheincreaseins(x)isconstant. Andifx∈F,thenclearlycaliberxwillcontinuetoapplynowherewhensincrea Step 2: The applicant pool at college 2 expands. It suffices to showthatifanycaliberxthatappliestocollege2ats 2 1 1alsoappliesthereatahighers 2, 1 then a2 1 2(x)u=a1 32 32 . Fix a caliber x∈Cor x∈B, so that2 ∈S(x). If x∈C(x)u-c=0 and a(x);theseinequalitiescontinuetoholdaftersrises,sincea(x)fallswhile Withaslightabuseofnotation,weletFdenotethesetofcalibersthatapplynowhere. Thesame symbolwaspreviouslyusedtodenotetheanalogoussetina-space. S2 S E 1 1 L 2 S 1 Κ 1 S2 S1 S2 u Κ2 S1 L Κ2 S1 Κ1 1 2 E Κ 2 S1 S1 u Κ1 >¯κ1(κ2 2(x)urises in s 1 2 1 1 a2(x) remains constant. And if x∈ B, then MB21 satisfyinglimc→0 ¯κ1(κ2,c)=1-κ2 1suchthatifκ >¯κ1(κ2 (κ2,c)<1-κ2 1 1 1(κ2 2 ∈(0,1),andletsL 1(κ2)be theuniquesolutiontoκ2 Fixanyκ2 2 1 ( κ 2(8,-8)=1,andE2(s 1(κ2)=E1 1(κ2 ) c o n =E2(s L 1(κ2 1 v o1-κ2 e r 33 g e s t 2 1 1,-8)increasingandcontinuousi 2 ns ( sL 1 ( κ2 =E2(sL 1(κ2),-8),¯κ1(κ2 Figure8: Equilibrium Existence. Intheleftpanel,sinceκ1 = (1-a ),thebestresponse functionsSandS2donotinterse Therightpanel depictstheproofofClaim3fortheca (x))a rises. 1 1 1 ,c). We will choose the capacity ¯κ given κ2 1 ( κ 2 , encouragingcaliberxtoapplytocollege2. Sox/∈C∪Fevenafters A.6 Existence of aRobustStable Equilibrium Claim 3 (Existence) A robust stable equilibrium exists. College 1 fills its capacity. Also,thereexists¯κ= ¯κ,c),thencollege2alsofillsitscapacityinanyrobustequilibrium. Ifκ,c), thencollege2hasexcesscapacityinsomerobustequilibrium. Proof: Fordefiniteness,wenowdenotetheinfimum(supremum)signalby-8(8). Definition of ¯κso that when college 2 has no standards, both colleges exactly fill their capacity. This borderline capacityislessthan1-κsinceapositivemass ofstudents —perversely, thosewith thehighestcalibers—appliesjusttocollege1,andsomearerejected. ,-8),i.e., when college 2 accepts everybody. (Existence and uniqueness of s) follows from E(-8,-8)=0,E.) Definethethresholdcapacity ¯κ),-8). Li mitingBehaviorof ¯κ,c). Sinceκ)equals1-κ minus themassofstudents whoonlyappliedto,andwererejectedby, college1. This massvanishesascvanishes,fortheneverybodyappliestobothcolleges. Therefore,the threshold¯κ2ascgoestozero. Robust Stable Equilibrium with Excess Capacity. Let κ1 l 1(κ1), l 1(κ1) theunique solution to κ1 = ¯κ1(κ2 =E1(s l 1(κ1 1 = sL 1(κ2 L 1(κ2)an 1,s dE2(s (κ2 (-8,κ2 )<8,theuniquesolutiontoκ2 andS2 (-8,κ2 ),w hile the rec anb eex ces sca pac itya tcol leg e2if κ1 ). We claimthatthereexistsarobuststableequilibriuminwhichcollege2acceptseverybody, andcollege 1sets athreshold s,-8), which satisfies s). For since college 2 rejects no one, s) fills college 1’s capacityexactly. Theenrollmentatcollege2isthenE),-8)=κ)= s2)isincreasingins1),sobyacceptingeverybodycollege2fillsas muchcapacityasitcan. Thisrobustequilibriumistriviallystable,asSis‘flat’atthe crossing point (see Figure 8, left panel). Moreover, if κ1>¯κ12), then college 2 has excesscapacityinthisequilibrium. Robust Stable Equilibrium without Excess Capacity. Assume nowκ< ¯κ1(κ2). WewillshowthatthecontinuousfunctionsS1andS2mustcrossatleastonce (i.e., a robust equilibrium exists), and that the slope condition is met (i.e., it is stable). First,inthiscasesL 1(κ2)<sl 1(κ1)or,equivalently, S-1 2)<S). Second, asthestandardofcollege2goestoinfinity, college 1’sthresholdconverges to su 1(κ1)<8,theuniquesolutiontoκ1=E1(s1,8). Thisisthelargestthresholdthat college 1can set given κ1. Similarly, as the standard ofcollege 1goes to infinity, college2’sthresholdconvergestosu 2(κ2),i.e. thelargestthresholdthatcollege2cansetgivenκ2. Third,S1=Earecontinuous. BytheIntermediateValueTheorem,theymustcrossatleastoncewiththeslopeconditio nbeingsatisfied(seeFigure8,rightpanel). Thus,arobuststableequilibriumexists when κ1<¯κ1(κ2). Moreover, inany robust equilibrium there isnoexcess capacity at eithercollege,sincethebestresponsefunctionssatisfyS-1 2)<S1(-8,κ). Hence, a robust stable equilibrium exists for any κ21∈ (0,1). Capacities are filled whenκ1=¯κ1(κ2>¯κ1(κ2). A.7 Stochastic Dominance in RobustSorting Equilibria Claim 4 (Sortingand the Caliber Distribution) Inanyrobustsortingequilibrium, thecaliberdistributionatcollege1first-orderstochasticallydominatesthatatcollege2. Proof Step 1: Monotone Student Strategy Representation. Amonotonestudentstrategyisrepresentedbythepartitionofthesetoftypes: =[ξ2,ξB),B=[ξB,ξ1),C1 =[ξ1,8) (15) 34 F=[0,ξ2),C2 ξB ξ <ξB 2 2 <ξ1 2 1=c/[u(1-a1)](i.e.,MB21 =c),anda2 1 2. Letf1 ands )/u(i.e.,MB12 f2 B8 B ξ[ξ1aB](x)f(x) 2 ξ 1 whereξ2 aredefinedbytheintersectionoftheacceptancefunctionwithc/u, a=(1-c/a=c),respectively. Proof Step 2: Enrolled Caliber Densities. Fixs(x)and f(x)bethedensitiesofcalibersenrolledatcolleges1and2,respectively. Formally, 2 1 (t)f(t)dt I[ξ (x) = a ,8)(x) (1 6) f1 2,ξ (x)a2(x)f(x)+(1-I[ξ2,ξB](x))a2(x)(1-aa(x))f(x) (s)f(s)ds+ ξ1 ,ξ ](x),(17) (x) = I Ba2(s)(1-a11(s))f(s)ds I[ξ H H i ,thenf1(xH)f2(xL)=f2(xH)f1(xL);i.e.,fi (x )f (x )isequivalentto whereIA >xL istheindicatorfunctionofthesetA. ProofStep3: (x). Weshallshowthat,ifx Log-Supermodularityoff L ∈ [0,8),withx(x)islog-supermodular in (-i,x), oritsatisfies MLRP. The result follows asMLRP implies thatthe cdfs are orderedbyfirst-orderstochasticdominance. 2 L 2 H 1 L Using(16)and(17),f (x 2L a1HI[ξB,8)(xH ) I[ξ2,ξB](x L)a +(1-I[ξ2,ξB](xL))a2L(1-a1L) I[ξ2,ξ1](x)= a1LI[ξB,8)(xLI2BH2BH21LH), (18) 1 H )f (x )=f whereaij H =ai(x ) j ,ξ [ξ ,ξ ](x B 1 1 )a2H +(1-I[ξ ,ξ ](x 1H ))a2H (1-a1H 1L a2L ) 1L I[ξ,ξ ](x a (1-a1H ,x ),or H ),i=1,2,j=L,H. Itiseasytoshowthattheonlynontrivialcaseis whenxL,x∈[ξB](inalltheothercases,eitherbothsidesarezero,oronlytheright sideis). IfxL,x∈[ξ,ξ],then(18)becomesa(1-a)=a2H 2 |xL))G(s 1 |xL ). (19) 1 |xH ))(1-G(s 2 1 1 |xH |xL |xH))G(s |xSince g(s| x) satisfies MLRP, it follows that G(s| x) is decreasing in x, and hence 1 |xH 1 G(sL)=G(s 1 |xL))(1-G(s 2 |xH )), (1-G(s |xH 1 ))(1-G(s 2 |xL))=(1-G(s 2 1 ass >s inarobustsortingequilibrium. Thus,(19)holds,therebyprovingthatf first-orderstochasticallydominatesF2. 1 ( -G(s 1 ). Next, ) ) (1-G(s)= (1-G(s i islog-supermodularin(-i,x),andsoF 35 (x) A.8 Comparative Statics: Changing Application Costs Claim 5 Inarobuststablesortingequilibrium,iftheapplicationcostateithercollege rises,thenatcollege1theadmissionstandardfallsandthecaliberdistributionstochasticallyimp roves. Proof: Assumearobuststablesortingequilibrium. Wemodify(15)fordifferentcosts: ξ1isdefinedbyMB21=c2,ξBbyMB12=c1,andξ2bya2u=c. Step 1: An Increase in College 2’s Cost. Ifc22rises,thenξ1drops,ξrises, and ξB2is unchanged; thus, the applicant poolatcollege 2shrinks, andat college 1is unchanged. Sothe S2curve shifts down, while S1remains unchanged. The functions nowcrossatalowerthresholdpair,andsobothstandardss1,s2bothfall. Step 2: An Increase in College 1’s Cost. Next consider an increase in c. ThisraisesξB1,whichshrinkstheapplicantpoolatcollege1,andincreasestheenrollment at college 2, at a fixed admission standard. This shifts S1left and Sup. While the effectonthestandards2isambiguous,wenowdeducethats12falls. Differentiating(4) and(5)withrespecttoc1,andusingCramer’sRule: 2 2)-(∂E1/∂c1)(∂E2/∂s 1 2)-(dE2/ds 1/dc1 1/ 1)(dE1/ds 2 d i=2,B,1 2 s 2(ξB|c 1 2 2 B ∂s 11 = (∂E2/∂c1) (∂E1/∂s ) (dE1)(dE2/ds) (20) ∂c Sincetherobustequilibriumisstable,theslopeofS issteeperthatofS 2 2 P2(ξi|s 2)-S2(C2)-S i =S =P1(ξB|c1)<0, dE2/ds B ) >0, and dE1/ds / d c B)a1a2 1 ' 2= P1(ξB|s slightly rises, then ξ 2)equals B B|c1)P2(ξB|s 2) >0. If c1 B|c1)-P1 ,andthusthe denominatorispositive. LetP(ξ|y)betheportfoliodensityshifttocollegeiattypeξ givenanincrementtostandardorcosty,andletS(A)betheown-standardseffectat college2insetA. Thenparsetheenrollmentderivativesintotheportfolioandstandards effects: dE(B)<0, dE= P 2 risesbysomed>0. Thus,college1losesmassf(ξ )a1 B)a1a 2d'. falls by some d Thus,P1(ξB|s 2)P2(ξ B)a1d' 1 2d]-[f(ξB)a1d][f(ξB)a1a2d']=0 [f(ξB)a1d'][f(ξB dofstudents,andcollege2gains massf(ξdofstudentswhowouldhavegonetocollege1. Likewise,ifsslightly rises, then ξ, and college 1 gains mass f(ξand college 2 loses massf(ξ(ξ )a a Hence,thenumeratorin(20)reducesto 2)+P(ξ1|s 2)-S2(C2)-S2(B)]<0 36 -P1(ξB|c1)[P2(ξ2|s St e p 3: I m pr o v e m e nt in C ol le g e 1’ s C al ib er Di st ri b ut io n. In a ro b u st s or ti n g e q ui li br iu m ,t h e a p pl ic a nt p o ol at c ol le g e 1 c o n si st s of c al ib er sx ∈[ ξ, 8) . Fr o m th el a st p ar t, a n yc o sti n cr e a s e d e pr e ss e s s1 Bi n e q ui li br iu m . Itf ol lo w st h at ξr is e s in e q ui li br iu m — si n c e c ol le g e 1 h a s th e s a m e c a p a cit y a s b ef or e, if it is to h a v e lo w er st a n d ar d s,i t m u st al s o h a v ef e w er a p pl ic a nt s. L et (ξ 0 B, s0 1B )b et h e ol d e q ui li br iu m p ai r a n d( ξ1 B, s1 1)t h e n e w o n e, wi th ξ0 B < ξ1 B a n d s0 1> s1 1. T h e nt h e di st ri b ut io nf u n cti o n of e nr ol le d st u d e nt s at c ol le g e 1 u n d er e q ui li br iu m i= 0, 1i s: We must show F1 1 (x) = F0 1 8 ξi B(1-G(s|t))f(t)dt (x) for all x ∈ [ξi 11 B|t))f(t)dt,8). For any x, the denominators on both sides equal k1, so cancel them. Now notice that 0 = F1 1(ξ1 B) < F0 1(ξ1 B) and limx→8F1 1(x) = limx→8F0 1(x) = 1. Since both functions are continuous in x, if ∂F1 1/∂x > ∂F0 1/∂x for all x ∈ [ξ1 B,8), then F1 1(x) < F0 1(x). But this requires (1-G(s1 1|x))f(x)>(1-G(s0 1|x))f(x),whichfollowsfroms1 1<s0 1. A.9 Sorting and Non-Sorting Equilibria: Proof of Theorem 2 Part(a): College2isTooGood. Weconstructacceptancechances(a1(x),h(a(x))) such that student behavior is non-monotone, college enrollment equals capacity, and a 1(x) and h((a11(x)) obey the requirements of Theorem 1. Then that theorem yields existenceofasignaldistributionwithnon-monotoneequilibriumstudentbehavior. Step1: TheAcceptanceFunctionandStudentBehavior. Whenu>0.5, thesecantfromtheorigintoMB12=cfallsasatendstoc/(1-u)—asintheleft panel of Figure 6. So for some z <c/(1-u), a line from the origin to (z,1) slices the MB121curve twice. Let h:[0,1]→[0,1] be defined by h(a1)=a/zand on [0,z), andh(a1)=1fora11=z. Observe thath(0)=0andh(1)=1,andthathisweakly increasing,withbothh(a1)/a1and[1-h(a1)]/[1-a]weaklydecreasing,sohobeysthe doublesecant property. Nowconsider student behavior. Movingalongtheacceptance relation h, students with acceptance chance a11<(c¯z)/uwill apply nowhere; those in the interval [(c¯z)/u,a ) will apply to college 2 only; those between [a,a] will apply to both;thosein(a,c/(1-u))willapplytocollege2only,thosein[c/(1-u),1-(c/u)] willapplytoboth,andthoseabove1-(c/u)willapplytocollege1;wherea,aarethe pairofintersectionswiththeMB12curve. Hence,studentbehaviorisnon-monotone. 37 (1 S2 S2 4 1 1 1' Η S1 25' ° E1 E0 E0 2 2 E1 S1 S1 Figure 9: Existence of Sorting and Non-Sorting Robust Equilibria. We depict theproofofTheorem2. Intheleftpanel,whenκ2falls,S2shiftsuptoS' 2,inducingarobust non-sorting equilibrium at E1. In the right panel, when κ1falls, S1shifts right to S' 1. The standardsatthenewrobustequilibriumE1obeys2<η(s1),i.e.,theequilibriumissorting. Step2: Transformingthetypespace. Noticethatifonechoosesamonotone functiona1(x),thenweinduceadistributionG(a)=P(a(X)<a)(i.e.,theprobability thatarandomstudentXhasacceptance chanceatcollege1less thana). Conversely, we can obtain any distribution G(a) by choosing a11(x) = G-1(F(x)). The resulting functiona1(x)thusobtainedwillbesmooth,monotoneandontoprovidedthatGhasa continuousandstrictlypositivedensityover[0,1]. Therefore,wecanrestateourproblem aschoosingaGwiththesepropertiesandsuchthattheenrollmentequationshold. aaadG(a)+ 1c 1-uadG(a)=κ1Step 3: Enrollment. Theenrollmentequationsaregivenby: a a ¯zdG(a)+ aa(1-a) a¯z a¯z a dG(a)+ c 1- c u c¯z u (1-a)dG(a)=κ2. dG(a)+ ¯z¯zdG(a)+ c1-u 1 u WenowdecoupletheequationsbylettingG( a)-G(a)=G(1-(c/u))-G(c/(1-u))= ofor some small o(e.g. by using a uniform density). It is clear that the resulting individual integral equations have an infinite number of solutions for G(a) on those regions. Choosingoneofthemcompletestheproof. ForthenTheorem1yieldsasignal densityg(s|x)andthresholdss1>s2suchthath(a1(x))istheacceptancefunction. Part (b): College 2 is Too Small. The proof is constructive. Consider =a1/u. Theacceptancefunctionevaluatedata1 ψ(c,s 1,s 2)<c/u. (21) (a1,a2)=(c,c/u)onthelinea2 =c liesbelowc/uwhen 38 Wewillrestrictattentiontopairs(s 1,s 2 1,s 2)= 1). Thenenrollmentatcollege1isgivenby 8 1 E1(s )suchthat(21)holds. Inthiscase,anystudent who applies to college starts by adding college 1 to his portfolio, and this happens as soonasa(x)=c,orwhenx=ξ(c,s (1-G(s 1|x))f(x)dx, 1) ξ(c,s . Thus, for any capacity κ∈ (0,1), a unique threshold s1(κ1)solves κ1=E1(s1,s which is independent of s 11functionis“vertical” when (21)holds, since theapplicantpoolatcollege1doesnotdependoncollege2’sadmissionsthreshold Theanalysisaboveallowsustorestrictattentiontofindingrobustequilibriawithin thesetof(s1,s2)suchthats1=s1(κ1)ands2satisfiesψ(c,s1(κ1),s2)<c/u. Enrollmentatcollege2isgivenby E2( 1(κ1),s 2)= B G(s 1(κ1)|x)(1-G(s 2|x))f(x)dx, s 1 (seeClaim2). Thus, κ2 2,andincreasingins 2(s 2 ),κ2 1strictly falls in κ2, for any κ2 2 = s <¯κ2(κ1 1, let ¯κ2(κ1) = E2(s 33 ),s 1(κ1 1(κ1 ). Then (i) for any κ1 2 2 2 1(κ1 1(κ1) 2(κ1 Fix κ2 and s 1 1 2 1 ,s 33 2)thatsatisfiesκ1 =E1(s 1,s 2),κ2 1 2 2/∂s =E2(s 1,s 2),ands 2 <η(s 1 1 whichiscontinuous, decreasingins = E1(κ1),s2)yieldss2=S2(s1(κ1),whichisstrictlydecreasinginκ. Given κ1 equilibrium ensues if both colleges set the same threshold.Since S> equilibrium exists with s∈ (0,1) and having(ii)non-monotonecollegeandstudentbehavior(Figure9,left). Pa κ∈ (0,¯κ)], there is a unique robust Conditions for Equilibrium Sorting. We prove that there exists equilibrium with s= s234), = (κ2 ),smallerthanthebound¯κ1(κ2 1 ) >0 such that if κ1 κ (κ2 1(κ 1(κ2 ∂S ) and u= 0.5, then there are only κ robust sorting equilibriaandneithercollegehasexcesscapacity. ∈ (0,1). We first show that the robust stable equilibrium with no excess capacityderivedinClaim3isalsosortingwhenthecapacityofcollege1issmallenough. Moreprecisely,thereisathresholdκ)definedinthe proofofClaim3,suchthatforallκ∈(0,κ)),thereisapairofadmissionsthresholds (s/∂s)(i.e.,arobust sortingequilibrium),and∂S<1(i.e.,therobustequilibriumisstable). The proof uses three easily-verified properties of the ηfunction implicitly defined 2 =s 1(κ1). 1,s 2)<c/uissatisfiedifs Itisnotdifficulttoshowthatψ(c,s 34 Wearenotrulingouttheexistenceofanotherrobustequilibriumthatdoesnotsatisfy(21). 39 2 =η(s 1)→ 8 as s 1 2 1,s 1 1 1 =E1(s 1,s 2)andκ2 =E2(s 1,s 2),with(∂S1/∂s 2)(∂S2/∂s 1)<1. by inequality (14): (a) ηis strictly increasing; (b) s → 8; (c) s=η-1(s2)→-8ass→-8. Foranyκ∈(0,¯κ1(κ22)),weknowfromClaim3thattheree Claim 6 Thepair(s 1,s 2)isarobustsortingequilibriumwhenκ1 issufficientlysmall. 21 1 )={(s 1,s 2)|κ2 2(s =E2(s 1,s 2(s 2) and s 2 (s =η(s =η(s 1 Proof: LetM(κ 2 2 =E1 -1 1)foralls 2 2 1 2 2 1 1,κ 1( s 1(κ ),ss 2 (s ,κ2 1 1 1 u2 (κ2)=¯κ1(κ 2 2 )}. Graphically, thisis thesetofallpairsatwhichs=S1,κ)crossess2). IfM(κ2)=Øwe aredone,forthens=S1,κ1)<η(s,including those at which κ(s,s) and κ2=E(s1,s2). To see this, note that (i) s-1= η(s2) → -8 as s2→ -8, while we proved in Claim 3 that s= S) convergestosl 1(κ2)>-8. Also,(ii)s2=η(s1)→8ass1→8,whileweprovedin Claim3thats2=S2(s2)converges tosu 2(κ)<8. Pr operties(i)and(ii)reveal thatifS2andηdonotintersect,thenS22iseverywherebelowη. IfM(κ2)=Ø, let(s2(κ2))=supM(κ), which isfinite by property (b)of η(s1)and since s2=S21)converges tosu 22goestoinfinity (see theproofofClaim3). Now,asκgoestozero,s(κ12)<8 ass=S2,κ1)goestoinfinityforany valueofs,forcollege1becomesincreasinglymoreselectivetofillitsdwindlingcapacity. Sinces22isboundedabovebys(κ2),thereexistsathresholdκ1)suchthat, forallκ1∈(0,κ1(κ2)),theaforementionedpair(s1,s)thatsatisfiesκ2=E) andκ2=E2(s1,s2)isstrictlybiggerthan(ss 1(κ2),ss 2(κ)),therebyshowingthatitalso satisfies s2<η(s1). Hence, arobust sorting stable equilibrium exists forany κand κ1∈(0,κ1(κ22)),withbothcollegesfillingtheircapacities(seeFigure9,rightpanel). Tofinishtheproof,noticethat,iftherearemultiplerobustequilibria,bothcolleges filltheircapacityinallofthem(graphically,theconditionsoncapacitiesensurethatS 2 1 andS2 intersectareallbelowη). startsaboveS1 forlowvaluesofs 1(κ 2 1 1 40 andeventuallyendsbelowit). Moreover,adjusting theboundκ)downwardifneeded,allrobustequilibriaaresorting(graphically,for κsufficientlysmall,thesetofpairsatwhichS 1 A.10 Affiliated Evaluations Wenowshowthatifstudentsandcollegesseenoisyconditionallyiidsignalsofcalibers, thenthisisformallyaspecialcaseof(⋆). Lettbeastudent’s truecaliber, unknown tohimandcolleges. Ithasdensity p(t) on[0,1]. AfterseeingthesignalrealizationX=x,drawnwithtype-dependentdensity f(x|t),thestudentupdateshisbeliefstop(t|x)=f(x|t)p(t)/f(x). Ifastudentofcaliber tappliestoacollege,thecollegeobservesasignalsdrawnwithdensityγ(s|t)andcdf G(s|t)on[0,1]. Ifastudentappliestobothcolleges,thentheyobserveconditionallyiid signals. Weassumethatf(x|t)andγ(s|t)obeythestrictMLRP. 1 0|x)= γ(s1|t)γ(s2 Definetheconditionaljointdensityofsignalsg(s1,s2 10 (1-G(si|t))p(t|x)dt= ai(x)= 0 1 s1i γ(si|t)p(t|x)dsidt= s1i 0 1 g(si,sj |x)dsjdsi 01 |t)p(t|x)dt. Noticethatgintegratesto1,andsoisavaliddensity. Also,asanintegralofproducts oflog-supermodularfunctions,itinheritsthisproperty,byKarlinandRinott(1980). In otherwords, thesignalsareaffiliated. Next, definethedensity f(x)=f(x|t)p(t)dt. Wenowreinterpretthesignalxintheconditionaliidcaseasthestudenttruecaliber. To show that this model is a special case of (⋆), we prove that student and college optimizationshavethesamesolutionsasintheconditionaliidcase. StudentBehavior. Itsufficestoexpressthechancesoftwoacceptanceeventsfor the conditionaliidmodel without reference tothe type t, andthus as intheaffiliated model(⋆). First,theunconditionalacceptancechanceatcollegei=1,2is = 001G(s1|t)(1-G(s2Next,theprobabilityofbeingrejectedat1andacceptedat2is |t))p(t|x )dt = 01s 10s s112 s12g(sγ(s1,s22|t)γ(s|x)ds11|t)p(t|x)sds2.1ds2dt CollegeBehavior. Itlikewisesufficestoexpresstheenrollmentfunctionswithout referencetothestudenttypet. Forinstance,forcollege1, E1( 1,s 2) = 01 C1∪B f(x|t)dx s11 γ(s1|t)ds1 p(t)dt s 1 0 1 ∪B f(x)dx. g(s1,s2|x)ds2ds1 = C1 s1 Theanalysisofcollege2isanalogousandthusomitted. 41 = C1 ∪B s11 0 1 |t)f(x|t)p(t)dt ds1dx γ(s1 A .1 1 A ffi r m at iv e A ct io n: P r o of of T h e o r e m 3 St e p 1: E q ui li br iu m C o n di ti o n s. H er e, w e a ss u m e a c o nt in u o u ss ig n al c df d er iv at iv e G x. Gi v e n a n y di sc o u nt p ai r( ∆1 ,∆ 2), th e c a p a cit y e q u at io n s wi th tw o gr o u p s ar e: = fEt 1 (s 1 -∆1,s 2 = fEt 2 (s 2 1 -∆1,s 2 1: -∆2)+(1-f)EN 1 (s 1,s -∆2)+(1-f)EN 2 (s 1,s 2 2), (23) x s J ∂∆ 1 f κ1 ) (22) κ w her aretherespectivefractionsoftargetedandnon-targetedgroupsenrolledat eEt collegei,definedjustasin(4)and(5),forthesetsofsignals(15). Sincethesignaldensity g = i,EN i Gand its derivative Gare both continuous, all derivatives of the enrollment function(usingLeibnitzrule)arecontinuoustoo. Step 2: Single College Preference Case. Differentiating equations (22) and(23)withrespectto∆ = i=1,2(-1)i+1 1∂ ∂( 1∂Et i ) f ∂E∂(s2t 3-i-∆2) +(1-f) ∂s ∂EN 3-i s s -∆1 2 2 = ∂ ∂ J ∂ ) f ∂E∂(s1t 3-i-∆1) +(1-f) -∆1 wherethedenominator,fromCramer’sRule,equals ∆ s E 1 t f ( i 1 )i = 1 , 2 i 1∂(s ∂ s 2 f ∂( s 1∂Et 2 ) +(1-f) 1 ∂E N1 -∆1 J = f ∂E∂(s 1t 1-∆f ∂E∂(s2t 11) +(1-f)-∆2∂EN 1∂s) +(1-f)1 ∂(s is p o sit iv ei n a n yr o b u st st a bl e e q ui li br iu m — i. e. th et w o gr o u p v er si o n of th e 2 -∆ ∂s ∂EN 2 ∂s 2 ∂Et 2 2 f ) +(1-f) ∂EN 2 c o n di ti o n th at th e sl o p e of S 1e xc e e d th e sl o p e of S 2i n § 4 a n d § A. 8. N o w, ∂s 1/ ∂ ∆ = f> 0 a n d ∂s 2/ ∂ ∆1 = 0 w h e n ∆1 = ∆2 1= 0, b e c a u s et h e d er iv at iv e s of th ef u n cti o n Et i, E N iat c ol le g e si = 1, 2 c oi n ci d e. T h u s, th ef e e d b a ck e ff e ct sv a ni s h w h e n ∆1 = ∆2 = 0, a n d ar e n e gl ig ib le in a n ei g h b or h o o d of it, b yc o nt in ui ty of th e e nr ol l m e nt d er iv at iv e s. Since ∆1 =p1, it follows that s 1)/∂p1|p1=0 1 g o e s u 1 increases while s1 -∆1 2 1 = p 2 i 42 decreases when p1 =p=0 p, a s∂ (s -∆ =f -1 < 0. T h e a n al ys is of th e d er iv at iv e s of s,i = 1, 2, wi th re s p e ct to ∆i s a n al o g o u s. St e p 3: B ot h C ol le g e Pr ef er e n c e C a s e. S u p p o s e n o wt h at p = ∆2 i i -∆goesdown,therebyprovingtheresult. 43 i nd thus ∆1 = ∆ = 0.aNow let pincrease. Replacing in the analysis above ∆,i=1,2,by∆anddifferentiating,yields,afterevaluatingtheexpressionat∆=0, ∂s/∂∆=f>0,i=1,2. Asbefores References Albrecht, J., P. Gautier, and S. Vroman(2003): “EquilibriumDirectedSearch withMultipleApplications,”TinbergenInstituteDiscussionPapers. Anderson, A., and L. Smith(2010): “AssortativeMatchingwithEvolvingHuman Capital,”ReviewofEconomicStudies,77(1),3–29. Avery, C., M. Glickman, C. Hoxby, and A. Metrick (2004): “A Revealed PreferenceRankingofU.S.CollegesandUniversities,”NBERWorkingPaper10830. Avery,C.,andT.Kane(2004): “StudentPerceptionsofCollegeOpportunities: The BostonCOACHProgram,”inCollegeChoices: TheEconomicsofWheretoGo,When to Go, and How to Pay for It, ed.by C.Hoxby, pp.355–393.University ofChicago Press. Avery,C.,and J.Levin(2010): “EarlyAdmissionsatSelectiveColleges,”American EconomicReview,100(5),2125–2156. Azevedo, E., and J. Leshno(2012): “ASupply andDemandFrameworkforTwoSidedMatchingMarkets,”Workingpaper,HarvardUniversi ty. Bettinger, E. P., B. T. Long, P. Oreopoulos, and L. Sanbonmatsu(2009): “The Role ofSimplification and Informationin College Decisions: Results from the H&RBlockFAFSAExperiment,”NBERWorkingPaper15361. Burdett, K., and K. Judd (1983): “Equilibrium Price Dispersion,” Econometrica, 51(4),955–69. Burdett,K.,S.Shi,andR.Wright(2001): “PricingandMatchingwithFrictions,” JournalofPoliticalEconomy,109(5),1060–1085. Card,D.,andA.B.Krueger(2005): “WouldtheEliminationofAffirmativeAction AffectHighlyQualified Minority Applicants? Evidence fromCaliforniaandTexas,” IndustrialandLaborRelationsReview,58(3). Carrell,S.,and B.Sacerdote(2012): “LateInterventionsMatterToo: TheCase ofCollegeCoachinginNewHampshire,”WorkingPaper,DartmouthCollege. Chade, H.(2006): “Matchingwith noiseandtheacceptance curse,” Journal of EconomicTheory,129(1),81–113. Chade,H.,andL.Smith(2006): “SimultaneousSearch,”Econometrica,74(5),1293– 1307. Curs, B., and L. Singell (2002): “An analysis of the application and enrollment processesforin-stateandout-statestudentsatalargepublicuniversity,”Economics ofEducationReview,21,111–124. Epple, D., R. Romano, and H. Sieg (2006): “Admission, Tuition, and Financial AidPoliciesintheMarketforHigherEducation,”Econometrica,74(4),885–928. (2008): “Diversity and Affirmative Action in Higher Education,” Journal of PublicEconomicTheory,10(4),81–113. Fu, C.(2010): “EquilibriumTuition,Applications,AdmissionsandEnrollmentinthe CollegeMarket,”WorkingPaper,UniversityofWisconsin. Gale, D., and L. Shapley(1962): “CollegeAdmissionsandStabilityofMarriage,” AmericanMathematicalMonthly,69(1),9–15. Groen,J.,andM.White(2004): “In-stateversusout-statestudents: thedivergence ofinterestbetweenpublicuniversitiesandstategovernments,”JournalofPublicEconomics,88 (9),1793–1814. Hickman, B. (2010): “Effort, Race Gap and Affirmative Action: A Game Theoretic AnalysisofCollegeAdmissions,”WorkingPaper,UniversityofChicago. Hoxby, C.(2009): “TheChangingSelectivityofAmericanColleges,”JournalofEconomicPerspectives,23(4),95 –118. Hoxby,C.M.,and C.Avery(2012): “TheMissing”One-Offs”: TheHiddenSupply ofHigh-Achieving,LowIncomeStudents,”NBERWorkingPaper18586. Kane,T.(1998): “Racialandethnicpreferencesincollegeadmissions,”inTheBlackWhiteTestScoreGap,ed.by C.Jencks,andM.Phillips.BrookingsInstitutionPress, Washington,D.C. 44 Karlin, S., and Y. Rinott (1980): “Classes of orderings of measures and related correlationinequalities.I.Multivariatetotallypositivedistributions,”JournalofMultivariateAnal ysis,10,467–498. Kircher, P., and M. Galenianos(2006): “DirectedSearchwithMultipleJobApplications,”mimeo,UniversityofPennsylvania. Pallais,A.(2009): “SmallDifferencesthatMatter: MistakesinApplyingtoCollege,” WorkingPaper,HarvardUniversity. Persico,N.(2000): “InformationAcquisitioninAuctions,”Econometrica,68(1),135– 148. Shimer,R.,andL.Smith(2000): “AssortativeMatchingandSearch,”Econometrica, 68(2),343–369. Smith, L.(2006): “Assortative Matching andSearch,” Journal of Political Economy, 114(6),1124–1146. Steinberg, J.(2010): “CollegesMarketEasy, No-FeeSelltoApplicants,” NewYork Times. 45