LargeCardinalsandDeterminacy PeterKoellner September12,2011 The developments of set theory in 1960’s led to an era of independence in which many of the central questions were shown to be unresolvable on the basis of the standard system of mathematics, ZFC. This is true of statements from areas as diverse as analysis (“Are all projective sets Lebesgue measurable?”), cardinalarithmetic(“DoesCantor’sContinuum Hypothesis hold?”),combinatorics(“DoesSuslin’sHypotheseshold?”),andgrouptheory (“IsthereaWhiteheadgroup?”). These developments gave rise to two conflicting positions. The first position—which we shall call pluralism—maintains that the independence resultslargelyunderminetheenterpriseofsettheoryasanobjectiveenterprise. Onthisview,althoughtherearepractical reasonsthatonemightgive infavourofonesetofaxiomsoveranother—say,thatitismoreusefulfora giventask—,therearenotheoretical reasonsthatcanbegiven;and,moreover, this either implies or is a consequence of the fact—depending on the variant of the view, in particular, whether it places realism before reason, or conversely—that there is no objective mathematical realm at this level. Thesecondposition—whichweshallcallnon-pluralism—maintainsthatthe independence results merely indicate the paucity ofour standard resources forjustifyingmathematicalstatements. Onthisview,theoreticalreasonscan begivenfornewaxiomsand—again,dependingonthevariantoftheview— thiseitherimpliesorisaconsequence ofthefactthatthereisanobjective mathematicalrealmatthislevel. The theoretical reasons for new axioms that the non-pluralist gives are quite different that the theoretical reasons that are customarily at play in mathematics,inpartbecause,havingsteppedintotherealmofindependence, amoresubtle formofjustification isrequired, one thatrelies more heavily onsophisticatedmathematicalmachinery. Thedisputebetweenthepluralist 1 andthe non-pluralistis thus onethatlies atthe intersection ofphilosophy and mathematics—on the one hand, it is intimately connected with some ofthecentralquestions ofphilosophyofmathematics, suchasthequestion of realism and the nature of justification; on the other hand, it addresses thesequestionsinamannerthatissensitivetoagreatdealofsophisticated mathematics. The debate between the pluralist and the non-pluralist is really a hierarchy of debates. At the one extreme there is pluralism with regard to all of mathematics and at the other extreme there is non-pluralism with regard to all of mathematics. The intermediate positions (which are much more common) involve embracing non-pluralism for certain domains (say first-orderarithmetic),whileadvocatingpluralismwithregardtoothers(say thosewherethenotionofthefullpowersetentersthepicture). Fortunately, the mathematical systems thatarise in practice can be arrangedin a wellfoundedhierarchy—rangingfromweaksystemslikeRobinson’sarithmeticQ, upthroughPeanoarithmeticPA,thesubsystemsofsecond-orderarithmetic, the subsystems of set theory, and the hierarchy of large cardinal axioms. One can thus arrange the hybrid non-pluralist/pluralist positions and the correspondingdebatesinawell-foundedhierarchy,wherealongthewayone embraces moreandmorenon-pluralism. The challenge forthosewithnonpluralist tendencies is to make the case that non-pluralism extends further andfurtherintotheupperreachesofhighermathematics. Thechallengefor those with pluralist tendencies is to draw the line in a principled manner andmake thecasethatnoargumentfornon-pluralismwill succeed forthe domainsofmathematicsbeyondthatline. 1It is sensible to approach the search for new axioms and the question of pluralism in a stepwise fashion, seeking first axioms that resolve certain low-levelquestionsandmakingthecasefornon-pluralismatthatlevel,and thenproceedingupwardtoquestionsofgreatercomplexityandthequestion ofpluralismathigherlevels. Thepresententryfocusesonthisdebateasit takesplaceinthesettingofclassicaldescriptivesettheory. Therearethree reasonsforthischoice. First,apopularviewembracesnon-pluralismforfirstorderarithmeticbutrejectsthes earchfornewaxiomsforfullsecond-order arithmeticandsettheoryandembracespluralismattheselevels.Theques1Thisviewthatonlynaturalnumbers(andthingsreducibletothem)haverealmathematicalexistence hasalongtradition,goingbackatleasttotheGermanmathematician Martin Ohm (1792–2872). Other notable figures in this tradition include Leopold Kronecker(1823–1891),HermannWeyl(1885–1955),and,morerecently,SolomonFeferman. 2 tions ofdescriptive set theory are importantin this connection since many ofthemarestatementsofsecond-orderarithmeticwhichareindependentof thestandardaxioms, ZFC. Itthus represents acriticaljuncture inthe debatebetweenthepluralistandnon-pluralist. Second,herethemathematical landscape with regard to the implications ofnew axioms has largely stabilized and we now have the resources required to address the issue between the pluralist and the non-pluralist. (In the case of questions of third- and higher-order arithmetic the matter still awaits further mathematical developments. Thattopicistreatedintheentry“TheContinuumHypothesis”.) Finally, the case for new axioms at this level involves so-called “extrinsic justifications”(somethingwe shalldescribe below)and,moreover, provides thestrongestcurrentexampleofsuchjustifications. Hereisanoverviewofthepresententry: Section1providesfurtherphilosophical motivation and sharpens the question of pluralism by briefly discussingtheinterpretability hierarchy, theincompleteness phenomenon, and the nature of axioms. Section 2 describes the central notions and results of classical descriptive set theory along with the independence results concerningthequestions thatremainedopenandwereultimatelyshowntobe unresolvableonthebasisofthestandardaxioms,ZFC. Section3describes the two main approaches to new axioms—axioms of definable determinacy andlargecardinalaxioms—anddiscussestheimplicationsoftheseaxiomsfor theundecided questions ofclassical descriptive settheory. Section 4treats of the intimate relationship between the two approaches and outlines the casethathasbeenmadeforaxiomsofdefinabledeterminacyandlargecardinal axioms. Section 5 revisits the debate between the pluralist and the non-pluralistinlightoftheforegoingmathematicaldevelopments. 1 PhilosophicalMotivation Oneway tosharpen the question ofpluralism involves appeal totheinterpretabilityhierarchy. Inthissectionwewill(1)introducetheinterpretability hierarchy, (2) briefly discuss the incompleteness phenomenon, (3) sharpen thequestionofpluralism,and(4)bringoutthephilosophicalissuesinvolved bybrieflydiscussing thenatureofaxiomsandthenatureofjustificationin mathematics. SeeFerreir´os(2007),pp.11–13forfurtherdiscussionontheearlyhistory. 3 1.1 Interpretability Hierarchy SupposeT andT2 arerecursivelyenumerableaxiomsystems. WesaythatT 1 1 ( T isint erpr etabl einT 1 T2 tothelanguageofT2 1 2 1 1 1 T2 1 andweshallwriteT1 <T2 =T2 whenbothT1 2 andT2 1 01 1 )when,roughlysp eaking,thereisatranslation tfromthelanguageofTsuchthat,foreachsentenc eϕ ofthelanguageofT,ifT1ϕthenT2t(ϕ). WeshallwriteTwhen TandT2T T T. Inthelattercase,T1andT2aresaidtobemutually interpretable. The equivalence class of all theories mutually interpretable with T is called the interpretability degree of T. The interpretability hierarchy is the collection ofalltheoriesorderedundertherelation . Thereisausefulcharacterizationoftherelatio n thatapplieswhenitis restrictedtothetypeoftheoriesthatwewillbecon sidering. Todescribethis weneedafewmorenotions. AtheoryT isreflexiveprovideditproves the consistencyofeachofitsfinitefragments,itisS0 1-completeprovideditproves eachtrueS0 1-statement,anditisS0 1-statement. Let‘T-sound provideditdoesnotproveafalse S1⊆Π0 1T2’beshorthand forthestatement thatallΠsentences provableinT1areprovableinT2. The following characterization ofinterpretabilityiscentraltothetheoryofinterpre tability: IfTisreflexive andS0 1-complete,then T1 T2iff T1⊆Π0 1T22. This result is due to Orey and H´ajek.1It follows from this result and the secondincompletenesstheoremthatforanythe oryTmeetingthesetwoconditions, the theory T+Con(T) is strictly stronger than T, that is, T < T+Con(T). Moreover,itfollowsfromthearithmetizedcomple tenesstheoremthattheT+¬Con(T)isinterpretab leinT,hence,T=T+¬Con(T). It turns out that the interpretability order is 01 3 exceedingly complex. For example,throughtheusesofmetamathematical codingtechniques,onecan showthatforanytwotheoriesT1andT2suchthatT thereisathird theoryT suchthatT1<T<T21<T2. AndforanytheoryT,onecanshowthat therearetheories T1andT2such thatT1>T andT>T andyet neither T T2norT2 T1(thatis,T1andT22areaboveTandar eincomparablein theinterpretabilityorder). Thus,theorderonthedegreesofinterpretability isneitherwell-foundednorlinearlyordered. 2ForfurtherdetailsseeTheorem6onp.103ofLindstr¨om(2 003)andFact3.2ofVisser (1998). 3 S e e F e f e r m a n ( 1 9 6 0 ) . 4 Nevertheless, whenonerestrictstotheoriesthat“ariseinnature”(that is, the kind of formal systems that one encounters in a mathematical text as opposed to examples of the type above, which are metamathematically manufactured by logicians to have the deviant properties in question) the interpretabilityorderingisquitesimple: Therearenodescendingchainsand there are no incomparable elements. In other words, it is a well-ordering. This is quite remarkable: If one takes any two “natural theories”—even fromcompletelydifferentdomains,sayonefromanalysisandanotherfrom combinatorics—then generally it turns out that one is interpretable in the otherandthatthetwolineupalongawell-foundedpaththroughtheinterpretabilityhie rarchy. Thiswellfoundedpaththroughtheinterpretabilityhierarchyhasacanonicalseq uencethroughitwhichenablesonetoclimbthehierarchyinaprincipledmanner. AtthebaseonehastheveryweaktheoryQandoneclimbs upwardbyadding“closureprinciples”. Thisstartswithprinciplesasserting that certain fast-growing functions—exponentiation, super-exponentiation, etc.—aretotalanditproceedsupwardthroughsetexistenceprinciples,passingthro ughthelayersofsecond-orderarithmetic,thesubsystemsofsettheory,andthehier archyoflargecardinalaxioms. Ofparticularinterestwithregardtothequestionofpluralismarethose pointsalongthewell-foundedsequencethatcorrespondtocertainlimitative conceptionsofthenatureofmathematics, suchasthedegreemarkedbyQ (whichcorrespondstostrictfinitisminthesensearticulatedbyNelson),the degreemarkedbyPRA(whichcorrespondstofinitisminthesensearticulated byTait),andthedegreemarkedbyATR0(whichcorrespondstopredicativism inthesensearticulatedbyFeferman). Ineachcase,onedrawsthelineata certainpointinthehierarchy,maintainingnon-pluralismbelowandpluralism above. Further Reading: For a more detailed account of the interpretability hierarchy see the entry “Independence andLargeCardinals”. Foreven further detailseeLindstr¨om(2003)andVisser(1998). 1.2 IndependencePhenomenon We noted above that the second incompleteness theorem provides us with a case where the statement, namely, Con(T), leads to a jump in the interpretability hierarchy whileits negationdoes not. There arealsonatural 5 examplesofthisphenomenon—forexample,largecardinalaxioms. Whena statementϕisindependentofatheoryTinthismanner—thatis,invirtue ofthefactthatT <T+ϕ—weshallrefertothekindofindependence involved as vertical independence. Thus, thesecond incompleteness theorem demonstrated that Con(PA) is vertically independent of PA (assuming, of course, thatPAisconsistent) andthatthelargecardinalaxioms“Thereis astronglyinaccessiblecardinal”isverticallyindependentofZFC(assuming thatZFC+“Thereisastronglyinaccessiblecardinal”isconsistent). In contrast to vertical independence there is the kind of independence thatariseswhenasentenceϕisindependentofatheoryTbecause T=T+ϕ and T=T+¬ϕ. SuchasentenceϕiscalledanOreysentencewithrespecttoT. Weshallrefer tothiskindofindependence ashorizontal independence. Usingmetamathematicaltechniques onecanconstructsuch sentences. Butagain,asinthe caseofverticalindependence,therearealsonaturalnon-metamathematical examples—forexample,PU(thestatementthattheprojectivesetshavethe uniformization property, a property we shall discuss below) is a statement of(schematic)second-orderarithmeticthatisanOreysentencewithrespect to ZFC, and CH is a statement of third-order arithmetic that is an Orey sentencewithrespecttoZFC. 1.3 TheQuestion of Pluralism With these pieces in place we can now begin to sharpen the question of pluralism. As a first step we will restrict our attention to theories which are formulatedinacommonlanguageandourlanguageofchoice willbethelanguage of set theory. The reason for restricting to a common language is thatotherwisetherewillbetheorieswhicharemerelynotationalvariantsof one another. And the reason for focusing on the language of set theory is thatitisauniversallanguageinthesensethatanysystemofmathematics is mutually interpretable with a theory formulated in the language of set theory; for example, PA is mutually interpretable with ZFC-Infinity. We arethus setting aside the question ofpluralism as itmight arise in amore metaphysicalsettingwhereoneconsidersquestionssuchaswhethernatural numbersare“really”setsorwhetherinsteadtherearetwodistinctdomains 6 ofobjects—naturalnumbersandthefiniteordinalsofsettheory. Ourfocus isonthe question ofpluralism asitarises inresponse tothe independence phenomenon and the issues at play in this discussion are invariant across different stances on the above metaphysical question. With regard to our questionthereisnolossofgeneralityintherestrictiontothelanguageofset theorysince theproblem offinding new axiomsforPAtranslates (through thenaturalinterpretation ofnumber theoryintoset theory)into theproblem offinding new axioms forZFC-Infinity, andconversely. Nevertheless, inwhatfollowsweshall,largelyoutofconvenienceandfamiliarity,continue tospeakoftheoriesthatareformulatedinotherlanguages—suchasQand PA—butthereadershouldalways understand ustobestrictly speakingof thecorrespondingtheoryinthelanguageofsettheory. Thequestionofpluralisminitsmostgeneralformulationisthequestion ofwhether there is acorrect path through the hierarchy ofinterpretability or whether instead a multitude of mutually incompatible theories must be admitted as equally legitimate from the pointof view oftheoretical reason and mathematical truth. There are really two problems that must be addressed. Thefirstisthequestionofhowfarthehierarchyofinterpretability extends, that is, which degrees are non-trivial in that the theories within them are consistent. This is the problem of consistency (or non-triviality). Thesecondisthequestionofwhether,foragiven(non-trivial)degreeofinterpretabili ty,therearetheoreticalreasonsthatcanbegivenforonetheory overanother. Thisistheproblemofselection. Ifonemanagedtosolveboth problems—determining the extent of the non-trivial degrees and locating thecorrectpaththroughthem—thenonewouldhavecompletelysolvedthe problem ofmathematical truth. There are, however, two important things tostressaboutthis. First,becauseoftheincompletenesstheorems,anysuch solutionwouldhavetobe“schematic”concerningthefirstpart(verticalindependen ce). Second, thesolution tothe fullproblem ofselection even for thedegreeofZFCisavery difficultonesinceitinvolvesresolvingCHanda multitudeofotherindependentstatementsthatarisealreadyatthislevel. Becauseofthedifficulty ofthesecondproblemitisusefultosplititup intoitsownhierarchybyclassifyingstatementsintermsoftheircomplexity. Weshalldiscussthehierarchyofstatementcomplexityinmoredetailinthe nextsection. Butforthemomentsufficeittosaythat(roughlyspeaking)one startswithquestionsofsecond-orderarithmetic(stratifiedaccordingtotheir complexity) and then one moves on to questions of third-order arithmetic (stratifiedaccordingtotheircomplexity),andsoon. Thus,onefirsttriesto 7 4solvetheproblemofselectionatthelevelof,say,statementsofsecond-order arithmeticandthenonemovesontotheproblemofselectionforstatements ofthird-orderarithmetic,andsoon. Thequestionofpluralismthatwewill beaddressingislocatedinthehierarchyasfollows: Ittakesanon-skeptical stancetowardZFCandseeksaxiomsthatsolvetheproblemofselectionfor thelevelofsecond-orderarithmeticandsomewhatbeyond. Letusnowgivesomeexamplesofthevariouspluralist/non-pluralistpositions. At one extreme there is radical pluralism which maintains that all non-trivial theories in the interpretability hierarchy are on a par and that there are no theoretical reasons that one can give for any theory over another. This form of pluralism is difficult to articulate since, for example, assuming that Q is consistent the theory Q+¬Con(Q) is consistent. But it is hard to see how the pluralist can admit this theory as a legitimate candidate since it contains a principle—namely, ¬Con(Q)—that is in conflictwiththebackgroundassumption thatthepluralistemploys inarguing that the theory is a legitimate candidate. For this reason most people are non-pluralistsaboutsomedomainsbutremainpluralistsaboutothers. 5Thelimitativeviewsthatwementionedearlier—strictfinitism,finitism, andpredicativism—are examples ofsuch hybrid views. Forexample, strict finitists(ononeconstrual)acceptQandcertaintheoriesthataremutually interpretable with Q, thereby adopting non-pluralism for this domain. In addition, the strict finitist takes these theories to exhaust the domain of objectivemathematicsandadoptsapluraliststancetowardtheremainder. Inasimilarfashion,finitismandpredicativismprovideuswithexamplesof hybridnon-pluralist/pluralistpositions. Predicativism is of particular interest for our present purposes since it grantstheframeworksofthenaturalnumbersbutrejectsmostofsettheory and, in fact, most of second-order arithmetic. The predicativist is a non4Weshouldnotethattherearesomeviewsthatacceptthestandardhierarchyoflarge cardinalaxioms—andso climb the canonicalpaththroughthe well-foundedstem ofthe interpretabilityhierarchy“alltheway”—andyetarepluralistaboutstatementsofthirdorderarithmetic ,inparticularCH. Soonceonehassolvedtheproblemofconsistency— eveninthestrongsensewhereoneactuallyadoptsthetheoriesinthecanonicalsequence— thereisstillplentyofroomforpluralisminapproachingtheproblemofselection. 5It should be noted that some strict finitists—like Nelson himself—think that exponentiationis nottotalandsothink thatmostofthe degreesabovethatofQ aretrivial (inconsistent). Suchastrictfinitistwillnotbeapluralistabout,say,PRAandthetheories extendingitforthesimplereasonthatsuchastrictfinitistwillthinkthatthesetheories areinconsistent. 8 pluralist about first-order arithmetic and thinks that there is an objective fact of the matter concerning every statement formulated in the language of first-order arithmetic. And the predicativist accepts as much of secondorder arithmetic and set theory that can be simulated in a theory such as ATR 0. Butthepredicativistremainsapluralistaboutwhatliesabove. The predicativistwilloftengrantthatthereisutilityinemployingaxiomaticsystems of set theory but will maintain that the issue of truth does not arise atthatlevelsincethereisnounivocalunderlyingconceptionofset. Forexample,thepredicativistwillthinkthatthereisanobjectivechoicebetween PAandPA+¬Con(PA)butnotthinkthatthereisanobjectivechoicebetweenPA 2+P UandPA2+¬PU(whereherePAis(schematic)second-order arithmetic)orbetweenZFCandZFC+“Therearenostronglyinaccessible cardinals”. Insofarasthepredicativistthinksthattheindependenceresults insettheoryconcerningsecond-orderarithmeticareareasonforendorsing pluralism about bothZFC andPA22the non-pluralist case we shall present belowisdirectlyengagedwiththepredicativist. Butweshouldstressthatfor thisdiscussionweshallbepresupposingZFCandsothemostdirectbrand ofnon-pluralism/pluralism thatwe shallbeengagedwith isonethattakes anon-pluraliststancetowardZFCbutapluraliststancetowardstatements likePUwhichareformallyunresolvableonthebasisofZFC. Thisisafairly commonview. See,forexample,Shelah(2003). Further Reading: For more on strict finitism see Nelson (1986); for more finitismseeTait(1981);formoreonpredicativismseeFeferman(1964)and Feferman(2005). 1.4 TheNatureof Axioms Theabovecharacterizationofthequestion ofpluralismmakes itclearthat it is closely connected with issues concerning the nature of justification in mathematics. Themosttraditionalformofjustificationinmathematicsinvolvesjustifyingastateme ntbyprovingitfromtheaxioms. Thisthenraises thequestion: Whatisthesourceofthejustificationoftheaxioms? The radical pluralist maintains that there is nothing that justifies the axioms;rathertheyaresimplypostulatesthatoneadoptshypotheticallyfor a given purpose. This view faces the difficulty raised above. Most would maintain thataxioms have aprivileged status and thatthis status is more thanmerelyhypothetical. 9 1.4.1 The Evidentiary Order A popular view is that axioms are self-evident truths concerning their do6main. The difficulty with this view is that the notion of self-evidence is a subjectivenotion. Thereisconsequentlymuchunresolvabledisagreementas towhatistocountasself-evidentandifwerestrictourselvestotheintersectionofthest atementsthatall mathematicianswouldregardasself-evident thentheresultwillbequitelimitedinreach,perhapscoincidingwithQor slightlymore.Markovhadasimilarcomplaintwiththeemploymentofthe relatednotionofbeing“intuitivelyclear”: Icanonnoway agreetotaking‘intuitively clear’asacriterion oftruthinmathematics,forthiscriterionwouldmeanthecompletetriump hofsubjectivismandwouldleadtoabreakwiththe understanding of science as a form of social activity. (Markov (1962)) Forthesereasonswewillsetasidethenotionofself-evidence. But there is a related notion that we shall employ, namely, the notion ofonestatement beingmore evident thananother. Incontrast tothe case ofself-evidence, thereisgenerallymuchmoreagreementonthequestionof whatismoreevidentthanwhat. 7Toillustratethisitisbesttogivesomeexamples: (1)Overthebasetheory EFA, the Finite Ramsey Theorem is equivalent to the totality of superexponentiation.See Friedman (2011), Section 0.5. (2) over the base theory RCA0,theHilbertBasisTheoremisequivalenttothestatementthatωωis well-ordered. See Friedman(2011),Section 0.6D.(3)Over the base theory ACA,Goodstein’sTheoremandtheHydraTheoremareeachequivalentto theS 0 1-soundness ofPA. SeeFriedman(2011),Sections 0.8Band0.8E.(4) Over the base theory RCA, Kruskal’s Tree Theorem is equivalent to the statementthatθΩw0iswell-ordered. SeeFriedman(2011),Section0.9B.(5) OverthebasetheoryACA,theExoticCase(ofBooleanRelationTheory) isequivalenttotheS0 1-soundnessofSMAH. SeeFriedman(2011),Sections 0.14C. 6Nelsonisonemathematicianwhodoesnotacceptthetotalityofexponentiationand thisaloneservestoruleoutmostsystemsbeyondthedegreeofQ. 7This theoryis obtainedfromQbyaddingS0-inductionandthe statementasserting thatexponentiationistotal. 10 first and there is general agreement on this fact. For example, the Hilbert Basis Theorem is far from immediate. It is the sort of thing that we set outtoprovefromthingsthataremoreevident. Incontrast, thestatement thatωiswell-foundedissomethingthatbecomesclearbyreflectingonthe conceptsinvolved. Itisnotthesortofthingthatwesetouttoprovefrom somethingmoreevident. ThisiswhatliesbehindthefactthattheHilbert Basis Theorem is called a theorem and not an axiom. As one climbs up through the other examples, the asymmetry becomes even more dramatic. Forexample,theHydraTheoremandKruskal’sTheoremareactuallyquite surprisingandcounter-intuitive. Thesearedefinitelythesortofstatements thatrequireproofonthebasisofstatementsthataremoreevident. We shall organize the statements in each interpretability degree by the relation ofbeing more evident than and we shall speak of the collection of allstatementssoorderedastheevidentiaryorder. Afewwordsofcautionarenecessaryconcerningthisordering. First,in saying that X is more evident than Y we do not intend that X (or Y) is self-evident orevenevident. Tounderscore thispointwewilloftenusethe expressions“XispriortoY intheevidentiaryorder”and“Xisevidentially prior toY”. Second,eveninthecasewhereXisminimalintheevidentiary order(withinagiveninterpretabilitydegree)werefrainfromsayingthatX isself-evident; indeed ifthedegree issufficiently highthen thiswill notbe the case. Third, the evidentiary order is to be understood as an epistemic orderandnot,say,theorderofconceptualcomplexity. One might raise skeptical worries about the evidentiary order. For example, perhaps judgments of the form “Xis prior to Y in the evidentiary order”arereallyjustreflectionsofourmathematicaltraining. Thebestway toallaysuchconcernsandtesttherobustnessofthenotionistoexamineexamples. Compare,forexample,thestatementoftheHydraTheoremandthe statementthat0iswell-orderedwithrespecttoprimitiverecursiverelations (a weak (semi-constructive) form of the statement that 0is well-ordered). Ifyoudescribetherelevantnotionstoamathematicianorlaypersonwhois not familiar with them then you will find the following: There will be no expectationthatHerculeswinstheHydra. Infact,ifyoudirecttheperson tooneofthecomputerprograms(availableonline)thatsimulatestheHydra youwillfindthattheywillbeastounded athowfasttheHydragrowsand ifyouassurethemthatiftheykeptonplaying—foraperiodofmoreyears thanthereareatomsinthephysicaluniverse(ascurrentlyestimated)—the 11 ωIneachoftheabovecases,thesecondstatementismoreevidentthanthe tideswilleventuallyturn,theywillmakegainsandeventuallycuttheHydra down to size, you will find that they will look at you in amazement. This is something that needs proof. Now if you describe to them the ordinals allthewayuptoandyoudescribethenotionofawell-orderingandask them whether 00is well-founded you will find that the answer rests solely onwhether they have graspedtheobjectinquestion. Tocometotheconclusion that 0is well-founded one does not search for a proof from some otherstatementwhichismoreevident. Ratheroneworksdirectlywiththe conceptsinvolved. Thestatementis,asitwere,restsonthelegitimacyofthe underlyingconceptsandonecomestoacceptitbygraspingthoseconcepts. Itisherethatthebuckstopsintheprocessofseekingjustification. Andthis iswhatwemeaninsayingthatthestatement“0iswell-ordered”isminimal intheevidentiaryorder(ofthedegreeoftheHydraTheorem). 8Inseekingaxiomsfortheorieswithinagiveninterpretabilitydegreewe seekaxiomsthatareaslowaspossibleintheevidentiaryorder. Ultimately one would like to find axioms that are minimal in the evidentiary order. But questions remain: (1) Can we be assured of finding minimal points that are secure? The concern is that as one climbs up the interpretability degrees the security of the minimal points will weaken to the point where therewouldarguablybelittlesecurityleft. Toseethisconsiderstatements oftheform“aiswell-ordered”whereaistheproof-theoreticordinalofthe interpretabilitydegree. Asoneclimbsthedegreesonepassesthrough 0,G, andθΩw0. Thisbarelyscratchesthesurfaceandyetalreadythecorresponding statementshavebecomelessevident. Thisleadstothesecondquestion. (2) Isfindingaminimalpointintheevidentiaryorder(ofagiveninterpretability degree)themostonecouldhopefororarethereother,moresubtlewaysof accumulatingevidenceforaxioms,waysthatmightfurtherbuttresseventhe minimalpointsintheevidentiaryorder(ofagiveninterpretabilitydegree)? 1.4.2 Intrinsicversus ExtrinsicJustifications There isadiscussion ofG¨odelthathasbearingoneachofthese questions, namely, his discussion of intrinsic and extrinsic justifications in his classic paperG¨odel(1947)(expandedasG¨odel(1964)). In introducing the notionof an intrinsic justification G¨odel gives as an examplecertainlargecardinalaxiomsthatarejustbeyondthereachofZFC: 8Notethatweareindividuatingourtheoriesbytheiraxioms. 12 [The] axioms of set theory [ZFC] by no means form a system closed in itself, but, quite on the contrary, the very concept of setonwhichtheyarebasedsuggeststheirextensionbynewaxioms which assert the existence of still further iterations of the operation“setof”(260). Asexamples hementions theaxioms assertingtheexistence ofinaccessible cardinalsandMahlocardinals: These axioms show clearly, not only that the axiomatic system ofsettheoryasusedtodayisincomplete,butalsothatitcanbe supplemented without arbitrariness by new axioms which only unfoldthecontentoftheconceptofsetasexplainedabove. (260– 261,myemphasis) Since G¨odel later refers to such axioms as having “intrinsic necessity” we shall accordingly speak of such axioms being intrinsically justified on the basisoftheiterativeconceptofset. Thenotionofextrinsicjustificationisintroducedasfollows: [E]ven disregarding the intrinsic necessity of some new axiom, and even in case it has no intrinsic necessity at all, a probable decisionaboutitstruthispossiblealsoinanotherway, namely, inductivelybystudyingits“success”. (261) Here by “success” G¨odel means “fruitfulness in consequences, inparticular “verifiable”consequences”. Inafamouspassagehewrites: There might exist axioms so abundant in their verifiable consequences,sheddingsomuchlightuponawholefield,andyielding such powerful methods for solving problems (and even solving them constructively, as far as that is possible) that, no matter whetherornottheyareintrinsically necessary, theywouldhave tobeacceptedatleastinthesamesenseasanywell-established physicaltheory. (261) Let us now consider some examples. Consider first the conception of natural number that underlies the theory of Peano Arithmetic (PA). This conception ofnaturalnumber notonlyjustifies mathematical inductionfor thelanguageofPAbutalsoforanymathematicalextensionofthelanguage 13 9of PA that is meaningful.10For example, if we extend the language of PA by adding the Tarski truth predicate and we extend the axioms of PA by addingtheTarskitruthaxioms,then,onthebasisoftheconceptionofnaturalnumber, wearejustifiedinacceptinginstancesofmathematicalinduction involving the truth predicate. In the resulting theory, one can prove Con(PA). Thisprocesscanthenbeiterated.Incontrast,theΠ0 1-statement Con(ZFC+“Thereareω-manyWoodincardinals”) (a statement to which weshallreturnbelow)isundoubtedlynot intrinsicallyjustifiedonthebasis of the conception of natural number; rather its justification flows from an intricatenetworkoftheoremsincontemporarysettheory,asweshallargue below. Considernexttheiterativeconceptionofset. Asinthecaseofarithmetic, thisconception(arguably)intrinsicallyjustifiesinstancesofReplacementand Comprehension for certain extensions of the language of set theory. But there are richer principles that are (arguably) intrinsically justified on the basisofthisconception,namely,theset-theoreticreflectionprinciples. These principlesassert(roughly)thatanypropertythatholdsofV holdsofsome initialsegment Va. These principles yield inaccessible andMahlo cardinals (and more) and quite likely underlie G¨odel’s claims in the above passage. Somehavearguedthatsuchreflectionprinciplesareintrinsicallyjustifiedon thebasisoftheiterativeconceptionofsetand,moreover,thattheyexhaust theprinciplesthatcanbeintrinsicallyjustifiedonthatconception. See,for example,Tait(2001),reprintedinTait(2005b),pp.283–284. Thereisaviewaccordingtowhichintrinsicallyjustifiedaxiomsareminimalpoints intheevidentiaryorderand,moreover,thatthatisthemostthat onecanhopefor. Onsuchaview,ifonegrantsthattheaboveprinciplesof settheoryareintrinsicallyjustifiedonthebasisoftheiterativeconceptionof set,thenalthoughonewouldhaveaxiomsthatfarsurpassedthereachesof predicativismandevenZFC,limitationswouldstillremainandpresumably aproponentofsuchaviewwouldembracepluralismfortheremainder. For example,if,asTait(2001)argues,intrinsicjustificationsareconfinedtothe 9NoticethatinspeakingofX beingintrinsicallyjustifiedonthebasisofY,X stands forastatementandY standsforaconception. Therelationisthusquitedifferentthanthe usualrelationofjustifiedonthebasisof whichholdsbetweenstatementsandstatements. The presentnotionbears comparisonwith the evidentiaryordersince in the casewhere onehas reacheda minimalpoint—suchasthe case of“0is well-ordered”one looksnot tootherstatementsforepistemicsupportbutrathertotheunderlyingconception. 10FormoreonthissubjectseeFeferman(1991)andthereferencestherein. 14 hierarchy of reflection principles investigated in Tait (2005a), then by the results of Koellner (2009a), such a view would have to embrace pluralism withregardtoPU. 11Extrinsicjustificationsprovideuswiththehopeofsecuringaxiomsthat have much greater reach. For they provide us with an additional way to secure axioms, onethatproves tobevery rich. Onthisview onecanhope formuchmorethanaminimalpointintheevidentiaryorder—onecanhope to garner evidence for a proposition examining its inter-relationships with otherstatementsthatarelowintheevidentiaryordering. Letusdescribein verybroadbrushstrokeshowthismightwork. Tobeginwith,letussaythat astatementis“intrinsicallyplausible”ifitis“low”intheevidentiaryorder butthesortofthingthatcouldbeoverturnedbyotherevidence.Oneway to garner support for a proposition is to show that it leads to intrinsically plausibleconsequences. Ifonethenshowsthatitistheonly statementthat hastheseintrinsicallyplausibleconsequencesthenthatstrengthensthecase by ruling out possible incompatible competitors. If one shows that there areotherintrinsicallyplausiblestatementsthatactuallyimplytheaxiomin questionthenthatagainstrengthensthecasebymappingoverthedegreeof intrinsicplausibilityattachedtoonestatementovertoanother. Onthispicturethegeneralstructureofthecasefornewaxiomsisthis: First,foreachinterpretabilitydegreeoneisolatestheminimalpointsinthe evidentiaryorderandoneorganizestheentiredegreeunderthedegreeofone statementbeingmoreevidentthananother. Asoneclimbstheinterpretability degrees the minimal points generally become less evident and so one seeks additional support. Second, one then examines the interconnections among the statements in the interpretability degree, in particular, among the statements which are low in the evidentiary order. The hope is that a seriesofdeepmathematicaltheoremswillrevealstructuralconnectionsthat providesmoreandmoreevidential supportforthestatements. Shouldthis bethecasethenthelossinevidenceattachedtotheminimalpointsasone climbs theinterpretability hierarchy wouldbecompensatedforbythegain instructuralconnectionsthatarerevealedasoneascendstoricherdomains ofmathematics. All of this is rather abstract at this stage. It is now time to turn to 11We intend to use this term in the same sense as Parsons. See Parsons (2000) and chapter9ofParsons(2008)foramoredetaileddiscussionofthenotionandsomeofthe themeswetouchuponhere. 15 a concrete mathematical case where such structural connections have been found. Thequestion,ofcourse,willbewhetherthemathematicsmakesfor aconvincingextrinsiccasefornewaxioms. Andthequestionofpluralismat thislevel—wherewearepresupposingZFCandtryingtosolvetheproblem ofselectionforsecond-orderarithmetic—willrestonthenatureofthecase. FurtherReading: ForfurtherdiscussionofthenatureofaxiomsandjustificationinmathematicsseePa rsons(2008)andMaddy(2011). 2 ClassicalDescriptiveSetTheory Descriptive set theory is the study ofthe structural properties ofdefinable sets of real numbers. In this section we shall (1) provide a brief historical overview,(2)introducethebasicnotionsofdescriptivesettheory(explaining whatwemeanby“definablesets”and“structuralproperties”),(3)describe the central classical results, and (4) discuss the limitative results that ultimately explained why the classical descriptive set theorists had run into difficultieswhenattemptingtogeneralizetheirresults. 2.1 Historical Overview Onereasonforconcentratingondefinablesetsofrealsisthatitisgenerally easiertogaininsightintodefinablesetsofrealsthanarbitrarysetsofreals and, furthermore, there is hope thatthis insight will shed light on the latter. For example, in one of the earliest results in the subject, Cantor and Bendixsonshowedthateveryclosedsetiseithercountableorhasthesizeof thecontinuum;inotherwords,theclosedsetssatisfyCH. Themainoriginsofthesubjectlieintheearly20thcenturyinthework of the French analysts Borel, Baire, and Lebesgue. The subject grew into an independent discipline through the work of the Russian mathematician Luzin (who had learned of the subject as a student while in Paris) and was developed by his students, most notably Suslin. The end of this early period of descriptive set theory was marked by a major theorem proved by the Japanese mathematician Kondˆo in 1937. After nearly 40 years of development,progresscametoanabrupthalt. Theexplanationforthiswas eventuallyprovidedbytheindependenceresultsofG¨odelandCohen(in1938 and1963). For,usingthismachinery,itwasshownthattheopenquestions 16 that the early descriptive set theorists were trying to answer could not be resolved on the basis ofthe standard axioms ofmathematics, ZFC. It is a testamenttotheingenuityoftheearlydescriptivesettheoriststhattheyhad developedtheirsubjectrightuptotheedgeofundecidability. The independence results of G¨odel and Cohen thus showed that if one wished to develop descriptive set theory further then one must invoke additional axioms. There were two main approaches, each of which led to a rebirth of descriptive set theory. The first approach was to invoke axioms of definable determinacy. The axiom of determinacy (AD) was introduced by Mycielski and Steinhaus in1962anditwas quickly seen toyield generalizations of the results of classical descriptive theory. Unfortunately, AD contradicts AC and for this reason it was never really proposed as a new axiom. However, Solovay and Takeuti pointed out that there is a natural suchsubuniverse, namely,L(R),inwhichADcouldhold,consistently with assuming AC in the full universe. This led toa hierarchy ofaxioms of definabledeterminacythatunderwentintensiveinvestigationinthe1970sand 1980s. ThemainsourcesforthisperiodareMoschovakis(1980)andthevolumesoftheCab alseminarduring1977–1985. Thesecondapproachwasto invokelargecardinalaxioms. ThisapproachwasinitiatedbySolovayin1965. Finally,inthelate1960sSolovayconjecturedthatlargecardinalaxiomsactually imply axioms of definable determinacy. If true, this would open the way foraunification ofthe two approaches. This hope was realized inthe workofMartin,Steel,andWoodinfrom1984onward. FurtherReading: Formoreonthehistoryofclassicaldescriptivesettheory seeKanamori(1995). 2.2 Basic Notions 2.2.1 Hierarchies of Definability Indescriptivesettheoryitisconvenienttoworkwiththe“logician’sreals”, that is, Baire space: ωω12. This is the set of all infinite sequences of naturalnumbers (with the product topology(taking ωas discrete)).In what 12ωThis structure is homeomorphic to the irrationals (as standardly construed). The reasonforworkingwithωinsteadofRisthatωωishomeomorphictoitsfiniteproducts, (ω)nωω, in contrast to the situation with R. This enables one to concentrate on proving resultsforω, andsimply notethat theylift (throughthe naturalhomeomorphisms)to thefiniteproducts. 17 follows,whenwewrite‘R’weshallalwaysmean‘ωω’. Weareinterested insets ofrealsthatare“definable”or“builtupfrom below by simple operations.” We shall discuss three central regions ofthe hierarchyofdefinability—theBorel setsofreals,theprojective setsofreals, andthesetsofrealsinL(R). ωTheBorelsetsofreals(orsetsofk-tuplesofreals)areobtainedbystarting withthe closed subsets ofω(or(ωω)kforsome k<ω)andclosing under the operations of countable union and countable intersection. This can be describedlevelbylevelasfollows: Letk<ω. Atthebaselevel,letS~ 0ωconsist oftheopensubsetsof(ω)kandletΠ~ 011consistoftheclosedsubsetsof(ωω)k. Foreachordinalasuchthat0<a<ω1,recursivelydefineS~ 0atoconsistof thesetsthatarecountableunionsofsetsappearinginsomeΠ~ 0,forß<a, anddefine Π~ 0aßtoconsist ofthesets thatarecountable intersections ofsets appearingin some S~ 0ß13, forß<a. The Borel sets of(k-tuples of)reals are thesetsappearinginthishierarchy.In1905Lebesgueemployed Cantor’s notionofauniversal setandtechnique ofdiagonalizationtoshow thatthe hierarchyofBorelsetsisaproper hierarchy(thatis,newsetsappearateach level). ωThe projective sets of reals (or sets of k-tuples of reals) are obtained bystartingwiththeclosedsubsets of(ω)kωanditeratingtheoperationsof complementation and projection. For A⊆ (ω)kω, the complement of Ais simply(ω)k-A. ForA⊆(ωω)k+1,theprojection ofAis p[A]={x1,...,xk∈(ωω)k|∃yx1,...,xk,y∈A}. (Thinkofthecasewherek+1=3. HereAisasubsetofthree-dimensional spaceandp[A]istheresultof“projecting”Aalongthethirdaxisontothe plane spanned by the first two axes.) We can now define the hierarchy of projectivesetsasfollows: Atthebaselevel,letS~ 1ωconsistoftheopensubsets of(ω)kandletΠ~ 100consist oftheclosed subsets of(ωω)k. Foreach nsuch that 0 < n < ω, recursively define Π~ 1to consist of the complements of setsinS~ 1n,anddefineS~ 1n+1ntoconsistoftheprojectionsofsetsinΠ~ 1n. The projectivesetsof(k-tuplesof)realsarethesetsappearinginthishierarchy. Thishierarchyisalsoaproperhierarchy,ascanbeseenusinguniversalsets anddiagonalization. It is useful to also introduce the ∆~ 1nsets. A set of (k-tuples of) reals is ∆~ 1niff it is both S~ 1nand Π~ 1n. In 1917, Suslin showed that the Borel sets 13It is straightforwardto see that this collection is the least collection containing the closedsetsandclosedundertheoperationsofcomplementationandcountableunion. 18 areprecisely the∆~ 11sets. Thus, theprojective hierarchy extends theBorel hierarchy. Itmightseemoddtorefertotheabovehierarchiesashierarchies ofdefinability. However, asthe notationindicates, theabove hierarchies canbe recast interms ofdefinability. Forexample, theprojective sets areexactly thesetswhicharedefinable(withparameters)insecond-orderarithmetic. In thenotationS~ 1n,thesuperscriptindicatesthatweareallowingquantification over objects of second-order (that is, sets of integers (or, equivalently, real numbers)), ‘S’ indicates thatthe starting quantifier is existential, the subscriptindicatesthattherearen-alternationsofquantifiers,and‘~’indicates thatweareallowingrealparameters. Inthecasewhererealparametersare prohibited,thecorrespondingpointclassesaredenotedS1 n,Π1 n,and∆1 n14. The formerhierarchy(whererealparametersareallowed)iscalledaboldface hierarchy, while the latter (where real parameters are prohibited) is called a lightface hierarchy. Inasimilarmanneronecandefinealightfaceversionof the Borel hierarchy.Thus, we really have two hierarchies of definability: thelightfacehierarchyandtheboldfacehierarchy. Theprojectivehierarchycanbeextendedintothetransfiniteasfollows: Foraset X,letDef(X)consist ofthesubsets ofXthataredefinable over XusingparametersfromX. Thisisthedefinablepowerset operation. The hierarchy L(R) is the result of starting with R and iterating the definable powersetoperationalongtheordinals;moreprecisely,weletL0(R)=V, La+1(R) = Def(La(R)), Lλ(R) = a<λLaω+1(R) for limit ordinals λ, and, finally, L(R)= La(R). a∈On ωWeareinterestedinthesetsof(k-tuplesof)realsappearinginthishierarchy, that is, P((ω)k)nLaω(R) for a ∈ On. Notice that in the definition of theprojectivesets,complementationcorrespondstonegationandprojection corresponds to existential quantification over real numbers. It follows that theprojectivesetsof(k-tuplesof)realsareexactlyP((ω)kω(R). Thus, the hierarchy of sets P((ω)k)nLa)nL1(R) (for a∈ On) does indeed yield a transfiniteextensionoftheprojectivesets. Onecanpassbeyondtheabovehierarchyofsetsofrealsbyconsidering 14 We shall not discuss the details but let us note that the result is that the ∆0 1 sets coincidewiththerecursivesetsandthelightfaceversionoftheBorelhierarchycoincides withthehyperarithmeticalhierarchy. 19 richer notionsofdefinability. Weshall say littleaboutthese stages, except tonotethattherearenaturallimitstothelightfaceandboldfacehierarchy, namely that of being definable from ordinal parameters (OD) and that of beingdefinablefromordinalparametersandrealnumbers(OD(R)). Tosee thatthenotionofordinaldefinability isalimitingcaseofthelightfacehierarchynoticefirstthatanynotionofdefinabilitywhi chdoesnotrenderallof theordinalsdefinablecanbetranscended(ascanbeseenbyconsideringthe leastordinalwhichisnotdefinableaccordingtothenotion)andsecondthat thenotionofordinaldefinability cannotbesotranscended(sincebyreflectionODisordinaldefinable). (Similarconsiderationsapplytotheboldface hierarchy.) It is for this reason that G¨odel proposed the notion of ordinal definabilityasacandidateforan“absolute”notionofdefinability. Asalimitingcaseofthelightfaceandboldfacehierarchywethereforehavethesets ofrealsthatareODandthesetsofrealsthatareOD(R),respectively. 2.2.2 Regularity Properties Therearemanypropertiessharedby“well-behaved”setsofreals. Theseare calledregularity properties. Weshallconcentrateonthethreemostcentral regularity properties—the perfect set property, the property of Baire, and Lebesguemeasurability. A set of reals is perfect iff it is nonempty, closed and contains no isolatedpoints. Thekeyfeatureofthisforourpurposesisthatifasetofreals containsaperfectsubsetthenitmusthavethesamesizeasthecontinuum (i.e.thereals). Asetofrealsissaidtohavetheperfectsetproperty iffitis either countable orcontains aperfectsubset. The interest ofthis property is that the sets of reals with the perfect set property satisfy CH. In early work, CantorandBendixson established (in1883)thatallclosed sets have the perfect set property. Thus, there is no closed counter-example to the continuumhypothesis. Later,in1903,YoungshowedthattheΠ~ 02setshave theperfectsetproperty. Acentralquestionwashowfarthispropertypropagates. DoalloftheBorelsetsofrealshavetheperfectsetproperty? Doall oftheprojectivesetsofrealshavetheperfectsetproperty? A set of reals is nowhere dense iff its closure under limits contains no opensets. A set ofreals is meager iffitis the countable union ofnowhere densesets. Finally,asetofrealsAhasthepropertyofBaireiffitis“almost open”inthesensethatthereisanopensetOsuchthattheregionwhereO andAdonotoverlap(thatis,thesymmetricdifference(O-A)∪(A-O)) 20 ismeager. ItisstraightforwardtoshowthatallBorelsetshavetheproperty ofBaire. DoalloftheprojectivesetshavethepropertyofBaire? ThepropertyofLebesguemeasurabilityisfamiliarfromanalysisandhere weshallbemorebrief. Tobeginwith,oneintroducesaprobabilitymeasure oversetsofreals. Asetofrealsisnull iffithasmeasurezero. Asetofreals AisLebesguemeasurable iffitis“almostBorel”inthesensethatthereisa BorelsetBsuchthattheregionwhereBandAdonotoverlapisnull. The interestofthisnotioncanperhapsbebestbroughtoutbyrecallingatheorem ofBanachandTarski. BanachandTarskishowed thatitispossible tocut theunitsphereintofinitelymanypieces,andshiftthosepiecesaround(using only translations and rotations) to bring them back together into a sphere oftwicethesize. ThisrequiresakeyapplicationoftheAxiomofChoice. It isimmediatethatsuchpiecescannotbeLebesguemeasurable. Thequestion is “How complex must such pieces be?” and this amounts to the question “Which sets are Lebesgue measurable?” It is clear thatthe Borel sets are Lebesguemeasurable. AretheprojectivesetsLebesguemeasurable? InallthreecasesitisstraightforwardtousetheAxiomofChoicetoshow thattherearesetsofrealswithouttheregularityproperty. Thequestionis whetheralldefinable setsofrealshavetheseproperties. 2.2.3 Structural Properties Therearemanystructuralpropertiesconnectedwithsetsofreals—theuniformizationproperty,theseparationproperty,theprewellorderingproperty, thebasisproperty,theexistenceofscales, Suslincardinals,theexistence of homogeneous representations, etc. We shall concentrate on just one such property—theuniformizationproperty. Let Aand Bbe subsets of the plane (ωω)2ω. Auniformizes Biff A⊆ B and for all x ∈ ω, there exists y such that x,y ∈ B iff there is a unique ysuch that x,y ∈ A. In other words, Ayields a choice function for B. Using AC it is clear that every set B has a uniformizing set A. However, thequestionofwhetheruniformizationsexistbecomesinteresting whenoneimposesadefinabilityconstraint. LetGbeacollectionof(k-tuples of) sets of reals. Such a class is called a pointclass. The pointclass G has uniformization property (Unif(G)) iff every subset of the plane that is in G admitsauniformizationthatisalsoinG. 21 2.3 Classical Results Duringtheearly20thcenturythereweremanyadvancesbytheFrenchand Russiananalystsinestablishingthatdefinablesetshadtheaboveregularity and structural properties. We shall limit our discussion to the crowning achievements: Theorem 2.1 (Luzin, Suslin, 1917). Assume ZFC. The S~ 11sets have the perfectsetproperty,thepropertyofBaire,andareLebesguemeasurable. Notice that the property of Baire and Lebesgue measurability have the featurethatiftheyholdofAthentheyholdofthecomplementofA. However, theperfectsetpropertydoesnothave thisfeature. Itremainedopen whether all Π~ 11sets have the perfect set property and whether all S ~ 12sets havethepropertyofBaireandareLebesguemeasurable. Theorem 2.2(Kondˆo,1937). AssumeZFC. ThenUnif(S~ 1)holds. It remained open whether all sets of reals in Π~ 12, S~ 132, etc. have the uniformizationproperty. 2.4 Limitative Results Itproveddifficulttoextendtheaboveresultstohigherpointclasses,somuch so that in 1925 Luzin said that “one will never know” whether all of the projectivesetsofrealshavetheregularityproperties. Wenowknowthereasonforthedifficulties—theearlyanalystswereworkinginZ FCandtheabovequestionscannotberesolvedonthebasisofZFC alone. It is a testament to the power of the early analysts that they obtainedthestrongestresults thatwere withinthereachoftheirbackground assumptions. The independence of the above statements follows from the dual techniques of inner model theory (invented by G¨odel in 1938)and outer model theory (inventedbyCohenin1963). ThefirsthalfwasestablishedbyG¨odelandAddison: Theorem 2.3 (G¨odel). Assume ZFC+V=L. ThenthereareS~ 1setsthat donothavethepropertyofBaireandarenotLebesguemeasurableandthere areΠ~ 11setsthatdonothavetheperfectsetproperty. 2 22 Theorem 2.4 (Addison,1959). AssumeZFC+V=L. Thenforalln 2, Unif(S~ 1n). Itfollowsthat(assumingthatZFCisconsistent),ZFCcannotprovethatS~ 12 sets have the property ofBaire and areLebesgue measurable, thatΠ~ 11sets havetheperfectsetproperty,andthatUnif(S~ 1n)failsforn 2. Itremained openwhetherZFCcouldestablishthenegations. ThesecondhalfwasestablishedbyMartin,SolovayandLevy: Theorem 2.5 (Solovay, 1965). Assume ZFC and that there is a strongly inaccessiblecardinal. Thenthereisaforcingextensioninwhichallprojective sets have the perfect set property, the property of Baire and are Lebesgue measurable. The strongly inaccessible cardinal is necessary for the perfect set property (even for Π~ 1sets (Solovay)) and Lebesgue measurability (Shelah) but not forthepropertyofBaire(Shelah). However,MartinandSolovayshowedin 1970thatifZFCisconsistentthensoisZFCalongwiththestatementthat allS 1 21setshavethepropertyofBaireandareLebesguemeasurable. Theorem2.6(Levy,1965).AssumeZFC. Thenthereisaforcingextension inwhichUnif(Π~ 12)fails. Infact,Levynotedthatthisisthecaseintheoriginalmodelintroducedby Cohen. Puttingeverythingtogetherwehavethefollowing: (1)IfZFCisconsistent, then ZFC cannot determine whether all S~ 12sets have the property of BaireandareLebesguemeasurable. (2)IfZFC+“Thereisastronglyinaccessible cardinal”is consistent, then ZFCcannotdetermine whether allΠ~ 11 setshavetheperfectsetproperty. (3)IfZFCisconsistent,thenZFCcannot determine the pattern of the uniformization property; more precisely, it is consistentwithZFCthattheuniformizationpropertyhaseitherthepattern ... S1S~ 12S4 ~1 ~1 Π~ S~ Π~ Π 12 13 11 ~ Π~ 14 13 Figure1: UniformizationunderV=L. 23 orthepattern S~ S~ S~ 12 13 14 ... Π ~ 14 S~ 11 Π~ Π~ 12 13 Π~ 11 Figure2: UniformizationintheCohenmodel. FurtherReading: Formoreonthehistoryofclassicaldescriptivesettheory seeKanamori(1995). Formoreonthemathematicsofclassical descriptive set theory see sections 12and 13 of Kanamori (2003), Kechris (1995), and Moschovakis(1980). 3 DeterminacyandLarge Cardinals TheabovelimitativeresultsshowthatZFClackssufficientpowe rtoresolve many questions about simple definable sets of reals—it cannot determine whetherS~ 12setshavetheregularitypropertiesanditcannotdeterminethe patternoftheuniformizationpropertybeyondS~ 12. Thisplacedmathematiciansinaninterestingpredicament. Inordertoresolvethesequestionsthey mustexpandtheirresourcesbeyondZFC. Buttherearemanywaysofdoing this and it is unclear at the outset whether there is a correct direction of expansion. Thereweretwomaincandidatesfornewaxiomsthatunderw entintensive investigationinthe1970sand1980s: Axiomsofdefinabledeterminacyand large cardinal axioms. In this section we will (1) introduce the basic machineryofdeterminacyanddescribetheimplicationsofaxio msofdefinable determinacyforclassicaldescriptivesettheoryand(2)describe theimplicationsoflargecardinalaxiomsforclassicaldescriptive settheoryandbriefly touchontheconnectionbetweenthetwoapproaches. 24 3.1 Determinacy For a set of reals A⊆ ωωconsider the game where two players take turns playingnaturalnumbers: I x(0) x(2) x(4) ... II x(1) x(3) ... At the end of a round of this game the two players will have produced a real x, obtained through “interleaving” their plays. We say that Player I wins the roundifx∈A; otherwise Player IIwins the round. The set Ais saidtobedetermined ifoneoftheplayers hasa“winningstrategy”inthe associated game, that is, a strategy which ensures that the player wins a roundregardlessofhowtheotherplayerplays. TheAxiomofDeterminacy (AD)isthestatementthatevery setofrealsisdetermined. Thisaxiomwas introducedbyMycielskiandSteinhausin1962. It is straightforward to see that very simple sets are determined. For example, if Ais the set of all reals then clearly I has a winning strategy; if Ais empty then clearly II has a winning strategy; and if Ais countable thenIIhasawinningstrategy(by“diagonalizing”). Thismightleadoneto expectthatallsetsofrealsaredetermined. However,itisstraightforwardto usetheAxiomofChoice(AC)toconstructanon-determinedset(bylisting allwinningstrategiesand“diagonalizing”acrossthem). ForthisreasonAD wasneverreallyconsideredasaseriouscandidateforanewaxiom. However, there is an interesting class ofrelated axioms thatare consistent with AC, namely,theaxiomsofdefinabledeterminacy. Theseaxiomsextendtheabove patternbyasserting thatallsets ofrealsatagivenlevel ofcomplexity are determined, notableexamples being∆~ 11L(R)-determinacy (allBorelsetsofreals aredetermined),PD(allprojectivesetsofrealsaredetermined)andAD (allsetsofrealsinL(R)aredetermined). Oneissueiswhetherthesearereallynewaxiomsorwhethertheyfollow fromZFC. Oneoftheearliestresultsinthesubject(duetoGaleandStewart in1953)isthat(inZFC)allΠ~ 01(thatis,closed)gamesaredetermined. This result was extended to the next few levels of the Borel hierarchy. Finally, in1974,Martinprovedthelandmarkresultthat∆~ 1-determinacyisprovable in ZFC. It turns out that this result is close to optimal—as one climbs thehierarchyofdefinability,shortlyafter∆~ 111onearrivesataxiomsthatfall outsidetheprovenanceofZFC. Forexample,thisistrueofΠ~ 1L(R)1-determinacy, PD and AD. Thus, we have here a hierarchy of axioms (including PD 25 andADL(R))whicharegenuinecandidatesfornewaxioms. ForapointclassGof(k-tuplesof)setsofreals,letDet(G)bethestatement thatallsetsofrealsinGaredetermined. Inwhatfollowsweshallassumethat Ghascertainminimalclosureproperties;moreprecisely,weshallassumethat Gisanadequate pointclassinthesenseofMoschovakis(1980). Theprecise detailsofthisnotionarenotimportantforourpurposes;sufficeittosaythat allofthepointclassesintroducedthusfarareadequate. Theorem3.1(Banach,Mazur,Oxtoby,1957).AssumeZFC+Det(G). Then thesetsofrealsinGhavethepropertyofBaire. Theorem3.2(Mycielski-Swierczkowski,1964).AssumeZFC+Det(G). Then thesetsofrealsinGareLebesguemeasurable. Theorem 3.3 (Davis, 1964). Assume ZFC+Det(G). Then the sets in G havetheperfectsetproperty. L(R)Inparticular,ifoneassumesPDthenallprojectivesetsofrealshavethe regularitypropertiesandifoneassumesADthenallofthesetsofreals inL(R)havetheregularityproperties. RInfactbymodifyingtheaboveproofsonecanobtaintheregularityproperties for a larger pointclass, namely, ∃G. This is the pointclass obtained by taking projections of sets in G. So, for example, if G is ∆~ 11Rthen ∃G is S~ 11. It follows that assuming ∆~ 1-determinacy (which is provable in ZFC) one gets that the S~ 11115sets of reals have the regularity properties.In this sensedeterminacy liesattheheartoftheregularitypropertiesandmaybe consideredtheirtruesource. Theaboveresultsshowthataxiomsofdefinabledeterminacyextendthe resultsonregularitypropertiesthatcanbeprovedinZFC. ZFCcanestablish thatall S~ 11sets of reals have the regularity properties and∆~ 11-determinacy (a theorem of ZFC) lies at the heart of this result. The extension of ∆~ 1L(R)1determinacy tostronger formsofdefinable determinacy (PD, AD, etc.) generalizestheseresultsbyextendingtheregularitypropertiestothecorrespondin gpointclasses(projective,inL(R),etc.) Inasimilarfashion,axiomsofdefinable determinacy extendtheresults ontheuniformizationproperty. ). ThenUnif(Π~ Theorem3.4(Moschovakis,1971).AssumeZFC+Det(∆~ 12n 12n+1 ~ 12n+2). 15Seetheexercisesin6.GofMoschovakis(1980). 26 ) and Unif(S Thus,underPDtheuniformizationpropertyhasthefollowingpattern: S~ S~ S~ ... 12 13 14 S~ Π 11 ~ 14 Π~ Π~ 12 13 Π~ 11 Figure3: UniformizationunderPD. L(R)Thispatternrecursathigherlevelsunderstrongerformsofdeterminacy. For example, under ADthe pattern recurs throughout the transfinite extensionoftheprojectivesetswithinL(R). ForallofL(R)onehas: Theorem3.5(Martin-Steel,1983). AssumeZFC+ADL(R). TheninL(R), S~ 21hastheuniformizationproperty. (Here S ~ 21is defined just as (the logical version) of S~ 11except that now the initialquantifierrangesoversetsofrealsandnotjustreals(asisindicated bythesuperscript).) Moreover,theuniformizationpropertyisnotanisolatedcase. Thesame patternholdsforotherproperties,suchastheprewellorderingpropertyand thescaleproperty. 3.2 Large Cardinals Thesecondapproachtonewaxioms—whichraninparalleltotheapproach using definable determinacy—was toinvoke largecardinal axioms. In fact, itwas graduallyshown (asSolovayhadconjectured inthelate1960s)that largecardinalaxiomsactuallyimplyformsofdefinabledeterminacy. Theresultthatunderscoredthesignificanceoflargecardinalaxiomsfor the structure theory of simply definable sets of reals is the following early resultofSolovay: Theorem3.6(Solovay,1965). AssumeZFCandthatthereisameasurable cardinal. Thenall S~ 12setsofrealshavetheperfectsetproperty,theproperty ofBaire,andareLebesguemeasurable. 27 Given thatΠ~ -determinacy implies the regularity properties forS~ 11 12 n<ω n n+1 κn(j).(Notice that j(κω(j)) = κω ~ 11 i 0 n(j)). Let κw set s of reals (see the discussion after Theorems 3.1–3.3), it was reasonable to suspect that a measurable cardinal actually implied Π~ 11-determinacy. This wasestablishedbyMartin: Theorem 3.7 (Martin,1970). AssumeZFCandthatthereisameasurable cardinal. Then Π-determinacyholds. Sincedefinabledeterminacylayattheheartofthestructuretheory,much of the energy was focused on trying to show that it followed from large cardinalaxioms. Thenextmajoradvancewasmadein1978. Theorem 3.8 (Martin,1978). AssumeZFCandthat thereisanon-trivial elementaryembeddingj:Vλ+1→Vλ+1. Then Π~ 12-determinacyholds. (Martin actually used a somewhat weaker assumption but it is somewhat technicalanditwouldnotbeilluminatingtostateithere.) In early 1979, Woodin extended this by showing that PD follows from much strongerlargecardinalhypotheses. Todescribe this, letusintroduce some terminology: Suppose j : Vλ+1→ Vis a non-trivial elementary embedding. Letκ0λ+1(j)bethecriticalpointofjandforeachnletκ(j)= j(κ(j) = sup,...,j(j).) A sequenceofembeddingsjisann-foldstrongranktorankembedding sequence ifthereexistsaλsuchthat (1) foreachi=n, j :Vλ+1 →Vλ+1 isanon-trivialelementaryembeddingand (2) foreachi<n, κω(ji)<κω(ji+1). Theorem 3.9 (Woodin,1979). AssumeZF. Foreachn<ω,ifthereisan n-foldstrongranktorankembeddingsequencethenΠ~ 1n+2-determinacyholds. SoPDfollowsfromtheassumptionthatforeachn,thereisann-foldstrong ranktorankembeddingsequence. The interesting thing about these large cardinal hypotheses is that for n>0theyareinconsistentwithAC(byaresultofKunen). Moreover,there isnowreasontobelievethatforn>0theyareoutrightinconsistent(inZF). 28 SeeWoodin(2011). Shouldthisturnouttobethecaseitwouldberather interestingsinceitwouldbeacasewhereonederivedstructuretheoryfrom aninconsistencywithoutawarenessoftheinconsistency. Fortunately,inDecemberof1983Woodinbothstrengthenedtheconclusionand reducedthelargecardinalhypothesis toonethatisnotknown to beinconsistentwithAC: Theorem3.10(Woodin,1984).AssumeZFCandthatthereisanon-trivial elementaryembeddingj:L(Vλ+1)→L(VL(R)λ+1)withcriticalpointlessthanλ. ThenADholds. Infact,WoodingotmuchmoredefinabledeterminacythanADL(R). Still,thelargecardinalassumptionwasthoughttobetoostrong. Atthis point the episode of history described earlier—the one involving Solovay’s theoremof1965andMartin’stheoremof1970—repeateditself. Forin1984 Woodinshowed thatifthereisasupercompactcardinalthenallprojective setshavetheregularityproperties. InjointworkwithShelah,thehypothesis wassignificantlyreduced. Theorem 3.11 (Shelah-Woodin, 1984). Assume ZFC and that there are nWoodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above them all. Then the S ~ 1n+2have the perfect set property, the property of Baire, and are Lebesgue measurable. As in the earlier episode, this suggested that the above large cardinal hypothesisactuallyimpliedΠ~ 1n+1-determinacy. Thiswassoonestablishedby alandmarkresultofMartinandSteel. Theorem 3.12 (Martin-Steel, 1985). Assume ZFC and that there are n Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above them all. Then Π~ 1n+1determinacyholds. Finally, in combination with Woodin’s work on the stationary tower, the followingresultwasestablished. L(R)Theorem 3.13 (Martin, Steel, andWoodin,1985). Assume ZFC andthat there are ωmany Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above them all. ThenADholds. Inthiswaythetwoapproaches tonewaxioms—viaaxiomsofdefinable determinacyandvialargecardinalaxioms—wereshowntobecloselyrelated. 29 In fact, in subsequent work it was shown that the connections are much deeper. But tofully appreciate this we must first introduce the machinery ofinnermodeltheory. FurtherReading: Formoreondeterminacyseesections27–32ofKanamori (2003)andMoschovakis(1980). Forfurtherdetailsconcerningthestructure theoryprovided bydeterminacy see thevolumes oftheCabalSeminarand Jackson(2010). 4 TheCasefor DefinableDeterminacy Wearenowinapositiontodiscussaspectsofthecasethathasbeenmade foraxiomsofdefinabledeterminacy. 4.1 Basic Notions Letusstressfromthebeginningthatbecauseoftheincompletenesstheorems the case for any new axiom is going to have to be delicate. The standard wayofestablishingapropositioninmathematicsisbyprovingitwithinsome acceptedsetofaxioms. However,theaxiomsimplicitlyacceptedbymathematiciansineveryday practiceseem tobeexhausted by thoseofZFC,and weareheredealingwithquestionsandnewaxiomsthatarebeyondthereach ofZFC. Given the nature of the case, it seems unlikely therefore that one willhaveaknock-downargumentfornewaxioms. Insteaditseemsthatthe mostthatonecanhopeforistoaccumulateevidenceuntileventuallythecase becomescompelling. Theotheralternativeisthatthecaseremainsdivided betweentwoequallycompellingbutmutuallyinconsistentapproaches. Let us first say something very general about how such a case might proceed. Some propositions have a certain degree of intrinsic plausibility. For example, the statement that there is no paradoxical decomposition of the sphere using pieces that are S~ 12is intrinsically plausible, although it is notprovableinZFC. Suchinitialsupportforapropositionisnotdefinitive. For example, the statement that there are no space filling curves and the statement that there is no paradoxical decomposition of the sphere using any pieces whatsoever might have once seemed intrinsically plausible. But in each case these statements were overturned by theorems proved against the backdrop of systems that had much more than this degree of initial 30 plausibility in their favour. However, althoughsuch intrinsic plausibility is notdefinitive,itneverthelesshassomeweight. Moreover, theweightcanaccumulate. Supposewehavetwostatements from conceptually distinct domains that are intrinsically plausible—for example, one might concern the existence of (inner models of)large cardinal axiomsandtheothermightconcerntheregularitypropertiesofsimply definablesets. Ifitisshownthatthefirstimpliesthesecondthenthesecond inherits the initial plausibility attached to the first. Should the two statementsultimatelybeshowntoimplyoneanotherthiswouldstrengthenthe caseforeach. The hopeis thatthroughtheaccumulation ofmathematical results—theoremsprovedinfirst-orderlogic,whicharemattersuponwhich everyone can agree—various independent intrinsically plausible statements will come to reinforce each other to the point where the case as a whole becomescompelling. Somehavemaintainedthatthisisactuallythesituationwithaxiomsof definable determinacy and large cardinal axioms. In the remainder of this sectionweshallpresentthecaseinthestrongestwayweknowhow. FurtherReading: Formoreonthenotionofintrinsicplausibility andhowit figuresinthestructureofreason,seeChapter9ofParsons(2008). 4.2 StructureTheory Fordefiniteness,whenwespeakofthe“structuretheory”(atagivenlevel)we shallbereferringtotheregularitypropertiesintroducedabove—theperfect setproperty,andthepropertyofBaire,andLebesguemeasurability—along withtheuniformizationproperty. Thereisactuallymuchmore(asindicated above)tothestructuretheoryandwhatweshallhavetosaygeneralizes. We shall concentrate on two levels of definable determinacy—∆~ 1L(R)1-determinacy and AD. Again, this is just for definiteness and what we shall have to saygeneralizestocertainhigherformsofdefinabledeterminacy. The axiom ∆~ 1-determinacy (equivalently, Borel-determinacy) is a theoremofZFCandliesattheheartofthestructuretheoryofBorelsets(and, in fact, the S~ 111-sets and S~ 12sets). One virtue of ADL(R)is that it lifts this entirestructuretheoryfromtheBorelsetstothesetsinL(R). Summarizing resultsfromabovewehave: Theorem4.1. AssumeZFC+ADL(R). TheneverysetofrealsinL(R)has 31 the perfect set property, the property of Baire, is Lebesgue measurable, and S2 1-uniformizationholdsinL(R). Many descriptive set theorists take these consequences to be intrinsiL(R)cally plausible. Moreover, they have found the particular pattern of the uniformization property provided by ADto be a plausible extension of the pattern initiated inZFC. Forthis lastpoint consider the first ωmany levels and compare the case of V=Lwith that of PD. In ZFC, the uniformizationpropertypropagatesfromΠ~ 11toS~ 12. Itisnaturaltoexpectitto continuetozig-zagbackandforth. However,underV=Litstabilizes: ... S1S~ 12S4 ~1 ~1 Π~ S~ Π~ Π 12 13 11 ~ Π~ 14 13 Figure4: UniformizationunderV=L. Incontrast,PDprovideswhatappearstobethecorrectextrapolation: S~ S~ S~ ... 12 13 14 Π S~ 11 Π~ Π~ 12 13 ~ 14 Π~ 11 Figure5: UniformizationunderPD. Again,this“periodicityphenomenon”occursathigherlevelsinL(R). OnemightgrantthattheseareindeedfruitfulconsequencesofADL(R)L(R)and as such are evidence that ADL(R)holds. However, one might be concerned that perhaps there are axioms that share these fruitful consequences and yetareincompatiblewithAD. Asaresponse, onemightnotethatthis objectionisneverraisedintheanalogouscaseofphysicswhereamultitude ofincompatibletheoriescanagreeintheirempiricalconsequences. Butthere isamuchstrongerresponsethatonecanmake. Forincontrasttothecaseof physics—whereonecouldneverhopetoshowthattherewasonlyonetheory 32 L(R)with the desired empirical consequences—in set theory this is actually the case; more precisely, any theory that has these fruitful consequences—that is,whichliftsthestructuretheorytothelevelofL(R)—must implyAD. Thisremarkablefactisembodiedinthefollowingtheorem: Theorem4.2(Woodin).AssumethatallsetsinL(R)areLebesguemeasurable,have thepropertyof Baire,andthat S2 1L(R)-uniformizationholdsinL(R). ThenAD. Summary: Thereisa“goodtheory”(onethatliftsthestructuretheory) L(R)andallgoodtheoriesimplyAD. 4.3 Large Cardinals Largecardinalaxiomsaretaken(bythosewhostudythem)tohavecertain degrees of intrinsic plausibility. As we noted above, large cardinal axioms implyformsofdefinabledeterminacyandsothelatterinherittheconsiderationsinfav ouroftheformer. L(R)Theorem4.3(Martin,Steel,andWoodin).AssumeZFCandthatthereare ωmanyWoodincardinalswithameasurableabovethemall. ThenAD. In fact, it turns out that the existence of certain inner models of large cardinalaxiomsissufficient toprovedefinabledeterminacy. Sinceitis(arguably)evenmoreplausiblethattherearesuchinnermodels,this(argu ably) strengthens the case. So definable determinacy is a fruitfulconsequence of theexistenceofsuchinnermodels. 16However,justasintheprevioussubsection,onewouldlikesomeassurance thattherearenotincompatibleaxiomsthatsharethisfruitfulconsequence. Remarkably,thisturnsouttobethecase—axiomsofdefinabledeterminacy areactuallyequivalent toaxiomsassertingtheexistence ofinnermodelsof large cardinals. We discuss what is known about this connection, starting withalowlevelofboldfacedefinabledeterminacyandproceedingupward. It shouldbeemphasized thatourconcernhereisnotmerelywithconsistency strengthbutratherwithoutrightequivalence(overZFC). 16Innermodeltheoryisaveryadvancedsubbranchofsettheoryandwewillnotbeable to describe it in anydetail here. Suffice it to say thatthe goalofinner modeltheory is to find“L-like”models thatcancontainlargecardinals. Inthe results belowMis the canonicalinnermodelforω-manyWoodincardinalsandM# ωωisthe“sharp”ofthismodel. ForamoredetaileddiscussionoftheseresultsseeKoellner&Woodin(2010). 33 Theorem 4.4(Woodin). Thefollowingareequivalent: (1) ∆~ 12ω-determinacy. (2) For all x ∈ ω, there is an inner model M such that x ∈ M and M|=“ThereisaWoodincardinal”. Theorem 4.5(Woodin). Thefollowingareequivalent: (1) PD(Schematic). (2) For every n <ω, there is a fine-structural, countably iterable inner modelMsuchthatM|=“TherearenWoodincardinals”. Theorem 4.6(Woodin). Thefollowingareequivalent: L(R)(1) AD. (2) InL(R),foreverysetSofordinals,thereisaninnermodelMandan a<ωL(R) 1suchthatS∈MandM|=“aisaWoodincardinal”. Theorem 4.7(Woodin). Thefollowingareequivalent: # andR# ω L(R)(1) AD exists. (2) Mexistsandiscountablyiterable. Theorem 4.8(Woodin). Thefollowingareequivalent: B |=ADL(R) (1) ForallB,V 34 #ω . (2) Mexistsandisfullyiterable. Summary: Large cardinal axioms are sufficient to prove definable determinacyandinnermodelsoflargecardinalaxiomsarenecessarytoprove definable determinacy. In fact, through a series of deep results, these two conceptuallydistinctapproachestonewaxiomsareultimatelyseentobeat rootequivalent. 4.4 Generic Absoluteness L(R)Largecardinalaxiomshavethefruitfulconsequencethattheyimplyaxioms ofdefinabledeterminacyandhenceilluminatethestructuretheoryofdefinablesets ofreals. Infact,ADappearstobe“effectivelycomplete”with regardtoquestionsconcerningL(R). Letustrytomakethispreciseinterms ofgenericabsoluteness. Themotivatingresultinthisareaisthefollowing: Theorem 4.9 (Shoenfield). AssumeZFC. SupposeϕisaS1 2sentenceand BisacompleteBooleanalgebra. Then B V |=ϕ iff V 12 12 17 L(R)V VB L(R) L(R) L(R) L(R). 17 35 |=ϕ. Inotherwords,theS-theorycannotbealteredbythemethodofoutermodels. Insuchasituationwesaythatϕisgenericallyabsolute. Sinceourmain methodofestablishingindependence(withoutleavinganinterpretabilitydegree)is themethodofoutermodels, thisexplains why therearenoknown Sstatements thatlieintheinterpretability degreeofZFCandareknown tobeindependentofZFC. A fruitful consequence of large cardinal axioms is that they place us in exactlythissituationwithregardtoamuchlargerclassofstatements. Theorem 4.10 (Woodin). AssumeZFCandthatthereisaproperclassof Woodin cardinals. Suppose ϕis a sentence and B is a complete Boolean algebra. Then |=ϕ iff L(R)|=ϕ. In this situation one, of course, has AD. Again, one might be concerned that one can have this fruitful consequence without having AD. Thisisaddressedbythefollowingtheorem: Theorem 4.11 (Woodin). AssumeZFCandthatthereisaproperclassof stronglyinaccessiblecardinals. SupposethatthetheoryofL(R)isgenerically absolute. ThenAD. Summary: There is a “good theory” (one that freezes the theory of L(R)) and (granting a proper class of strongly inaccessible cardinals) all goodtheoriesimplyAD SeeLarson(2004)foranaccountofthisresult. 4.5 Overlapping Consensus WehavediscussedtworecoveryresultsforADL(R). First,ADL(R)L(R)isimplied byitsstructuralconsequences(Theorem4.2). Second,ADL(R)isrecoveredby thegenericabsolutenessthatfollowsfromlargecardinalsthatimplyAD (Theorem4.11). Theserecovery resultsarenotisolatedoccurrences. Thetechniqueused L(R)to establish them is known as the core model induction. This technique hasbeenusedtoshowthatmanyotherstrongtheoriesimplyAD. This evenholdsfortheoriesthatareincompatiblewithoneanother. Forexample, considerthefollowing: Theorem4.12. (Woodin) AssumeZFC+thereisanω1-denseidealonωL(R). ThenAD. Theorem 4.13. (Steel) AssumeZFC+PFA. ThenADL(R)1. These two theories are incompatible. There are many other examples. In L(R)fact, the examples are so ubiquitous and the technique is so general that thereisreasontobelievethatADliesintheoverlappingconsensusofall sufficientlystrong,naturaltheories. Summary: ADL(R)L(R)liesintheoverlappingconsensusofnumerousstrong theoriesandsoitinheritstheconsiderationsofeach. Moreover,thereisreasontobelievethatADliesintheoverlappingconsensusofall sufficiently strong,“natural”theories. 4.6 Beyond L(R) Much ofthe above case can be pushed even beyond L(R). To explain this wewillneedtointroducethenotionofauniversallyBaire setofreals. V[G]Foracardinald,asetA⊆Risd-universallyBaireifforallpartialorders Pofcardinalityd,thereexisttreesSandTonω×λ(forsomeλ)suchthat A= p[T] and, if G⊆ P is V-generic, then p[T]= RV[G]V[G]-p[S]8. A setA⊆RisuniversallyBaireifitisd-universally Baireforalld. Thekey pointisthatuniversallyBairesetshavecanonicalinterpretationsingeneric extensionsV[G]. LetGbethecollectionofsetsofrealsthatareuniversally Baire. This collection has strong closure properties. For example, Woodin showedthatifthereisaproperclassofWoodincardinalsandA∈G+then (1)L(A,R)|=ADand(2)P(R)nL(A,R)⊆G8. HereAD+8isa(potential) 36 strengtheningofADdesignedformodelsoftheformL(P(R)). SeeWoodin (1999). Forκaninfinite regularcardinal, let H(κ)be theset ofallsets xsuch thatthecardinalityofthetransitiveclosureofxislessthanκ. 8Theorem 4.14. (Woodin) Supposethere is a proper classof Woodin cardinalsandA∈G. SupposeG⊆PisV-generic. Then (H(ω1),∈,A)V≺(H(ω1)V[G],∈,AG). Thatis,wehave genericabsoluteness for“projective-in-A”whereAisuniversallyBaire. Infact,onehas“S2 1(G8)-genericabsoluteness”: Theorem 4.15. (Woodin) Supposethere is a proper classof Woodin car8dinalsandletϕbeasentenceoftheform ∃A∈G(H(ω1),∈,A)|=ψ. SupposeG⊆PisV-generic. Then V |=ϕ iff V[G]|=ϕ. Stronger large cardinal axioms imply that many sets of reals beyond L(R) areuniversallyBaire. Letuscallasetabsolutely ∆2 1 ifthereareS2 1 sets of reals are universally Baire.18 21 19 21 18 37 19 formulas which definecomplementary sets ofrealsinallgeneric extensions. Woodin showed thatifthere isaproperclassofmeasurable Woodincardinalsthen all absolutely ∆This is one precise senseinwhichCHwasanunfortunatechoiceofatestcasefortheprogram for large cardinals—large cardinal axioms effectively settle all questions of complexitystrictlybelow(intheabovesense)thatofCH. 4.7 Summary Eachoftheaboveargumentshastwoparts. Inthefirstpart,onearguesthat thereisa“good”theory(onehavingcertainfruitfulconsequences). Inmany Under the same hypothesis one has that all of the “provably-∆” sets of reals are universallyBaire. Onemightworrythatwhatisreallygoingonhereisthatlargecardinalaxiomsthrow awrenchintotheforcingmachinery. Butthisisnotso. Underlargecardinalassumptions one has more generic extensions. What is really going on is that large cardinal axioms generatetreesthatarerobustandactasoraclesfortruth. casesthistheoryexplicitlyincludes(orjustis)ADL(R)L(R). Inthesecondpart, oneshowsthatallsuchtheoriesincludeAD. Wewanttostressthissecondpart—therecoverytheorems. Withoutthe recoverytheoremsonecouldalwayswonderwhetherthereareincompatible axiomswiththesamefruitfulconsequences. Incontrasttothecaseofphysics, whereonecouldneverhopetoshowthatthedatalogicallyimpliesthetheory, in the case of the search for new axioms this is in fact possible. It is the recoverytheoremsthatsealthecase. L(R)Perhapsthestrongestargumentinfavourofaxiomsofdefinabledeterminacyisth elast. Fortheresultsshowthattherearedeepconnectionsbetween approachestonewaxiomsfromconceptuallydistinctdomainsandthat,remarkably ,ADispartofthepictureprovidedbyeach. Inshort,ADL(R) liesintheoverlappingconsensusofallapproachesthatinvolveclimbingthe hierarchyofinterpretabilityalonganaturalpath. FurtherReading: FormoreonthetopicsofthissectionseeKoellner(2006), Koellner (2009b), Maddy (1988a), Maddy (1988b), Martin (1998), Steel (2000), Woodin (2001a), Woodin (2001b), Woodin (2005b), and Woodin (2005a). 5 PhilosophicalDiscussion L(R)Letusreturntothequestionofpluralism. Dotheaboveresultscollectively provideuswithastrongextrinsicjustificationofADandtherebysecure non-pluralismatthislevel? L(R)The pluralist will certainly accept the above results—after all, they are mathematicaltheorems—butwillresisttheclaimthattheyprovideuswith theoretical reasons for adopting ADL(R). The pluralist may grant that the results are quite interesting and that they show that ADL(R)has a certain appeal—since, for example, it renders L(R) a paradise for analysts—but theywillviewthisasapracticalreasonforadoptingADL(R),notatheoretical reason. Onthisviewtherearemanyroadsthatonecantake—V=L,AD, etc.—and that while each has its advantages with respect to certain aims thereisno“factofthematter”astowhichisthecorrectone,anymorethan there is a “fact of the matter” as to which of two notations is the correct notation. Atthislevel,accordingtothepluralist,notheoreticalreasonsare at play and there is no issue of objective mathematical truth. This is the 38 viewofFeferman(1999),Kanamori(2003),Shelah(2003),andmanyother philosophersandmathematicians. L(R)Thenon-pluralistregardstheaboveresultsascollectivelyprovidingvery strongtheoreticalreasonsforthinkingthatADholdsandthattheother, incompatiblealternativesfail. ThisistheviewofMartin(1998),Steel(2000), Woodin(2005a),manyphilosophersandmathematicians,andmostdescriptiveset theoristsandinnermodeltheorists. Aswementionedintheintroduction,somepluralistsandnon-pluralists take realism to be prior to reason while others take reason to be prior to realism. It is important to keep these two versions separate and address themindividually. Let us start with those who take realism to be prior to reason. To fix ideasconsiderthepluralistwhoacceptsrealismaboutthenaturalnumbers butnotaboutarbitrarysubsetsofnaturalnumbersandthen,onthisbasis, concludesthattheoreticalreasonscanbeofferedinthecaseofnewaxioms innumbertheorybutnotinthecaseofanalysisorsettheory. Whenpressed on the source of this asymmetrical stance concerning realism in the two domainsthepluralistusuallyrespondsbyresortingtotheintuitionthatthe naturalnumbersare“clear”whilethenotionofanarbitrarysubsetofnatural numbersis“inherentlyvague”. Tothisthenon-pluralistmightrespondthat thenotionofclarityisnotclear. Intuitionsofclarity,likeintuitionsofselfevidence,arenotoriouslyvagueandsubjecti veandhenceaweakpointupon whichtorestone’scase. Letusnowturntothosewhotakereasontobepriortorealism. People in this category take objectivity to be the hallmark of realism and they come to their conclusions concerning realism about a given domain only afteronehasagoodunderstandingofwhatkindoftheoreticalreasonshave tractioninthatdomain. Apluralistwhothinksthattheoreticaljustification inmathematicsmustultimatelytracebacktoaxiomswhichareself-evident will be unmoved by the above extrinsic case. Likewise for a pluralist who thinks that theoretical justification in mathematics must ultimately trace back to axioms that are extrinsically justified. The case we have given is clearly an extrinsic one. The issue, then, comes down to the legitimacy of extrinsicjustifications. Wearecertainlynotinapositiontoresolvethisdebatehere. Butitwill be helpful to draw a parallel with the debate between the instrumentalist andnon-instrumentalistinphysics. Anextremeformofinstrumentalismwas advancedbytheneo-KantianHansVaihingerinhisbookThePhilosophyof 39 As If (1911). According to this view, the “hard data” of physics consists inthedataofourimmediatesenseimpressions. Uponthisbasiswearefree to construct—in common sense and in physics—a “reality”, but the result isnotgenuineknowledge—rather,itisausefulfictionformovingaroundin everyday life and making predictions in physics. In a similar fashion, the extremepluralisttakesthe“harddata”toconsistofthetheoremsthathave actuallybeenestablishedandregardseverythingelseasausefulfiction. 20In the physical case the non-instrumentalist sees theoretical reason at playatamuchhigher-level,farbeyondthedata. Forexample,inthetimeof Copernicus,whenthePtolemaicandCopernicantheorywereobservationally indistinguishable,theoreticalreasonscouldstillbegivenfortheCopernican theory over the Ptolemaic theory.L(R)Similarly in the set theoretic case the non-pluralistseestheoreticalreasonatplayathigherlevel,beyondthetheorems and the intrinsically plausible statements. Just as in astronomy the non-instrumentalistfindsevidenceofahigher-levelstructureintheconstellation of connections, likewise in the case of set theory the non-pluralist takes the constellation of connections in the interpretability hierarchy—in particular,theabovetheoremsconcerningAD—asprovidingevidenceof structureofahigherlevel. There is, ofcourse, much moretobesaid. But wehopetohavebroughttheissuestothefore. It should be mentioned that the non-pluralist about ADL(R)is open to thepossibility thatpluralismholdsathigherlevels, sayatthelevelofCH. Foratreatmentofthatsubjectseetheentry“TheContinuumHypothesis”. References Feferman,S.(1960). Arithmetizationofmetamathematics inageneralsetting,FundamentaMathematicae49:35–92. Feferman, S. (1964). Systems of predicative analysis, Journal of Symbolic Logic29:1–39. Feferman,S.(1991).Reflectingonincompleteness,JournalofSymbolicLogic 56:1–49. 20Consider,forexample,thereasonsgiveninKepler’s“DefenseofUrsus”andEpitome ofCopernican Astronomy. 40 Feferman,S.(1999). Doesmathematicsneednewaxioms?,AmericanMathematicalMonthly106:99–1 11. Feferman, S. (2005). Predicativity, in S. Shapiro (ed.), The Oxford HandbookofPhilosophyofMathematicsandLogic,OxfordUniversityPress, pp.590–624. Ferreir´os, J. (2007). Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and ItsRoleinModernMathematics,secondrevisededn,Birkh¨auserVerlag AG. Foreman, M. & Kanamori, A. (2010). Handbook of Set Theory, SpringerVerlag. Friedman,H.M.(2011). BooleanRelationTheory,AssociationofSymbolic Logic. Forthcomming. G¨odel, K. (1947). What is Cantor’s continuum problem?, (G¨odel 1990), OxfordUniversityPress,pp.176–187. G¨odel, K. (1964). What is Cantor’s continuum problem?, (G¨odel 1990), OxfordUniversityPress,pp.254–270. G¨odel,K.(1990). CollectedWorks,VolumeII:Publications1938–1974,OxfordUniversityPress,Ne wYorkandOxford. Jackson,S.(2010). Structuralconsequences ofAD,(Foreman&Kanamori 2010),Springer. Kanamori, A. (1995). The emergence of descriptive set theory, in J. Hintikka (ed.), From Dedekind to G¨odel: Essays on the Development of theFoundationsofMathematics,Vol.251ofSyntheseLibrary,Kluwer, Dordrecht,pp.241–262. Kanamori, A. (2003). The Higher Infinite: Large Cardinals in Set Theory from their Beginnings, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, second edn,Springer,Berlin. Kechris,A.S.(1995).ClassicalDescriptiveSetTheory,Vol.156ofGraduate TextsinMathematics,Springer-Verlag,NewYork. 41 Koellner,P.(2006). Onthequestionofabsoluteundecidability,Philosophia Mathematica 14(2): 153–188. Revised and reprinted with a new postscriptinKurtG¨odel: EssaysforhisCentennial,editedbySolomon Feferman,CharlesParsons,andStephenG.Simpson.LectureNotesin Logic,33.AssociationofSymbolicLogic,2009. Koellner, P. (2009a). On reflection principles, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic157(2–3):206–219.KurtG¨odelCentenaryResearchPrizeFellowships. Koellner, P.(2009b). Truthinmathematics: The question ofpluralism, in O.Bueno&Ø.Linnebo(eds),NewWavesinPhilosophyofMathematics,NewWave sinPhilosophy,PalgraveMacmillan,pp.80–116. Koellner, P. & Woodin, W. H. (2010). Large cardinals from determinacy, (Foreman&Kanamori2010),Springer. Larson,P.B.(2004).TheStationaryTower: NotesonaCoursebyW.Hugh Woodin, Vol. 32 of University Lecture Series, American Mathematical Society. Lindstr¨om,P.(2003). AspectsofIncompleteness,Vol.10ofLectureNotesin Logic,secondedn,AssociationofSymbolicLogic. Maddy, P. (1988a). Believing the axioms I, Journal of Symbolic Logic 53:481–511. Maddy, P. (1988b). Believing the axioms II, Journal of Symbolic Logic 53:736–764. Maddy,P.(2011). DefendingtheAxioms,OxfordUniversityPress. Markov, A. A. (1962). On constructive mathematics, Trudy MatematicheskogoInstitutaImeniV.A.Steklova67(8–14).TranslatedinAmerican MathematicalSocietyTranslations: Series2,98,1–9. Martin,D.(1998).Mathematicalevidence,inH.G.Dales&G.Oliveri(eds), TruthinMathematics,ClarendonPress,pp.215–231. Martin, D. A. & Steel, J. R. (1989). A proof of projective determinacy, JournaloftheAmericanMathematicalSociety2(1):71–125. 42 Moschovakis,Y.N.(1980). DescriptiveSetTheory,StudiesinLogicandthe FoundationsofMathematics,North-HollandPub.Co. Nelson, E. (1986). Predicative Arithmetic, number 32 in Princeton MathematicalNotes,PrincetonUniversityPress. Parsons,C.(2000). Reasonandintuition,Synthese125:299–315. Parsons,C.(2008). MathematicalThoughtanditsObjects,CambridgeUniversityPress. Shelah, S. (2003). Logical dreams, Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society40(2):203–228. Steel,J.(2000). Mathematicsneedsnewaxioms,BulletinofSymbolicLogic 6(4):422–433. Tait,W.W.(1981).Finitism,JournalofPhilosophy78:524–556.Reprinted in(Tait2005b). Tait, W.W. (2001). G¨odel’s unpublished papers on foundations ofmathematics,PhilosophiaMathematica9:87–126. Tait,W.W.(2005a). Constructingcardinalsfrombelow,(Tait2005b),OxfordUniversityPress,pp.133–154. Tait,W.W.(2005b).TheProvenanceofPureReason: EssaysinthePhilosophy of Mathematics and Its History, Logic and Computation in Philosophy,OxfordUniversityPress. Visser, A.(1998). Anoverview ofinterpretability logic, Advancesin modal logic,Vol.1(Berlin,1996),Vol.87ofCSLILectureNotes,CSLIPubl., Stanford,CA,pp.307–359. Woodin, W. H. (1999). The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal, Vol. 1 of de Gruyter Series in Logic and its Applications,deGruyter,Berlin. Woodin, W. H. (2001a). The continuum hypothesis, part I, Notices of the AmericanMathematicalSociety48(6):567–576. 43 Woodin,W.H.(2001b). Thecontinuumhypothesis, partII,Noticesof the AmericanMathematicalSociety48(7):681–690. Woodin,W.H.(2005a).Thecontinuumhypothesis,inR.Cori,A.Razborov, S.Todorˆcevi´c&C.Wood(eds),LogicColloquium2000,Vol.19ofLectureNotesin Logic,AssociationofSymbolicLogic,pp.143–197. Woodin,W.H.(2005b). SettheoryafterRussell: thejourneybacktoEden, in G. Link (ed.), One Hundred Years Of Russell’s Paradox: Mathematics,Logic,Philosophy,Vol.6ofdeGruyter SeriesinLogicandIts Applications,WalterDeGruyterInc,pp.29–47. Woodin,W.H.(2011).SuitableextendermodelsI,JournalofMathematical Logic11(1–2):101–339. 44