Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2010 Lecture 12 Logistics Midterm will be returned at end of lecture HW2 is online, due in two weeks (Wed Mar 17) Second midterm Wed Mar 24 Cumulative, through end of contract law 1 Last time… Default rules Why are gaps left in contracts? What rules should be applied to fill those gaps? C&U: use terms most parties would have chosen (efficient terms) Ayres and Gertner: under some conditions, use default rules which penalize one or both parties for concealing information Regulations Example: derogation of public policy Ways to get out of a contract Formation defenses (“no contract exists”) Performance excuses (“circumstances have changed”) One formation defense: incompetence (but not drunkenness) 2 Another formation defense: dire constraints 3 Dire constraints Necessity I’m about to starve, someone offers me a sandwich for $10,000 My boat’s about to sink, someone offers me a ride to shore for $1,000,000 Contract would not be upheld: I signed it out of necessity Duress Other party is responsible for situation I’m in Someone makes me an offer I can’t refuse 4 Friedman on duress Example Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You write him a check Do you have to honor the agreement? “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” He did – he wants your $100 You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed So why not enforce it? Makes muggings more profitable leads to more muggings Tradeoff: don’t enforce Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior 5 Friedman on duress Example Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You write him a check Do you have to honor the agreement? “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” He did – he wants your $100 You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed So why not enforce it? Makes muggings more profitable leads to more muggings Tradeoff: don’t enforce Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior 6 What about necessity? Same logic doesn’t work for necessity You get caught in a storm on your $10,000,000 sailboat Tugboat offers to tow you to shore for $9,000,000 (Otherwise he’ll save your life but let your boat sink) Duress: if we enforce contract, incentive for more crimes Here: if we enforce contract, incentive for more tugboats to be available for rescues – how is that bad? Social benefit of rescue: value of boat, minus cost of tow Say, $10,000,000 – $10,000 = $9,990,000 If tugboat gets entire value, his private gain = social gain So tugboat captain would invest the efficient amount in being available to rescue you So what’s the problem? 7 What about necessity? What about your decision: whether to sail that day 1 in 1000 chance of being caught in a storm If so, 1 in 2 that a tugboat will rescue you Private cost of sailing: 1 in 2000 you lose boat, 1 in 2000 you pay tugboat captain value of boat $10,000,000/2000 + $10,000,000/2000 = $10,000 So you’ll choose to sail if your value is above $10,000 Social cost: 1 in 2000 boat is lost, 1 in 2000 boat is rescued $10,000,000/2000 + $10,000/2000 = $5,005 Efficient to sail when your value is above $5,005 When your value from sailing is between $5,005 and $10,000, you undersail If the price of being towed was just the marginal cost, you would sail the efficient amount 8 Friedman’s point Same transaction sets incentives on both parties Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! 9 Friedman’s point Same transaction sets incentives on both parties Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! So makes sense for courts to overturn contracts signed under necessity, replace them with ex-ante optimal terms 10 More general point Single price can create multiple incentives Often impossible to set them all efficiently Already saw this with remedy for breach Expectation damages: efficient breach, but inefficient signing Include gains from reliance: overreliance Exclude gains from reliance: inefficient breach 11 Real duress versus fake duress Court won’t enforce contracts signed under threat of harm “Give me $100 or I’ll shoot you” But many negotiations contain threats “Give me a raise, or I’ll quit” “$3,000 is my final offer for the car, take it or I walk” The difference? Threat of destruction of value versus failure to create value A promise is enforceable if extracted as price of cooperating in creating value; not if it was extracted by threat to destroy value 12 Example Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (US Ct App 1902) Captain hires crew in Seattle for fishing expedition to Alaska In Alaska, crew demands higher wages or they’ll quit Captain agrees Back in Seattle, refuses higher wages, claiming duress 13 A performance excuse: impossibility 14 Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility When performance becomes impossible, should promisor owe damages, or be excused from performing? A perfect contract would explicitly state who bears each risk Contract may give clues as to how gaps should be filled Industry custom might be clear But in some cases, court must fill gap 15 Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach But there are exceptions Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” 16 Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach But there are exceptions Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” Efficiency requires assigning liability to the party that can bear the risk at least cost Party that can take precautions to minimize the risk Or can best spread the risk over many transactions 17 Important general concept Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk? Also called low-cost avoider Who is in best position to mitigate/reduce a risk, or hedge it, or endure it? We already saw this question with efficient default rules When a contract leaves a gap, an efficient contract would have allocated each risk to low-cost avoider Construction company building a house, completion is delayed Family might be efficient risk-bearer, because it’s cheaper for them to stay with friends than for construction company to pay for hotel Cost of raw materials goes up, increasing cost of construction Construction company might be efficient risk-bearer, because they can buy materials early or change design plans 18 Contracts based on bad information 19 Misinformation Four doctrines for invalidating a contract based on faulty information Fraud Failure to disclose Frustration of purpose Mutual mistake 20 Fraud and Failure to Disclose Fraud violates “negative duty” not to misinform In some circumstances, positive duty to disclose certain information Civil law: contract may be voided if you did not supply information you should have (“failure to disclose”) Common law: seller is not forced to disclose everything he knows Must warn about hidden dangers Need not share information that makes product less valuable but not dangerous But, new products come with “implied warranty of fitness” 21 Frustration of Purpose Both parties based a contract on the same bad information contract may be voided due to frustration of purpose Coronation Cases Rooms rented out with view of new king’s coronation parade Parade was postponed, owners still tried to collect rent Courts ruled change in circumstance had frustrated the purpose of the original contracts, which were therefore void “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to the party who can bear the risk at least cost” 22 Mutual Mistake Frustration of purpose: circumstances changed after the contract was signed Mutual mistake: circumstances changed before the contract was signed, but the parties didn’t know about it Enforcing the contract would be like forcing involuntary exchange Coase: we expect voluntary exchange to be efficient But involuntary exchange may not be 23 Another principle: knowledge and control Hadley v Baxendale (miller and shipper) Hadley knew shipment was time-critical But Baxendale was deciding how to ship crankshaft (boat or train) A general principle about information: efficiency generally requires uniting knowledge and control Contracts that unite knowledge and control are generally efficient, should be upheld Contracts that separate knowledge and control may be inefficient, should more often be set aside 24 Unilateral mistake Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless You sell it to me at a low price Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld 25 Unilateral mistake Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless You sell it to me at a low price Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld Contracts based on unilateral mistake generally unite knowledge and control And this creates an incentive to gather information 26 Unilateral mistake: Laidlaw v Organ (U.S. Supreme Court, 1815) War of 1812: British blockaded port of New Orleans Price of tobacco fell, since it couldn’t be exported Organ (tobacco buyer) learned the war was over Immediately negotiated with Laidlaw firm to buy a bunch of tobacco at the depressed wartime price Next day, news broke the war had ended, price of tobacco went up, Laidlaw sued Supreme Court ruled that Organ was not required to communicate his information 27 Unilateral mistake: productive versus redistributive information Productive information: information that can be used to produce more wealth Redistributive information: information that can be used to redistribute wealth in favor of informed party Cooter and Ulen Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of productive information – especially if that knowledge was the result of active investment – should be enforced Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of purely redistributive information or fortuitously acquired information should not be enforced 28 More on duty to disclose Sellers must inform buyers about hidden safety risks Common law does not generally require disclosure of other types of information But… Obde v Schlemeyer (1960) Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose Sale did not unite knowledge and control 29 More on duty to disclose Sellers must inform buyers about hidden safety risks Common law does not generally require disclosure of other types of information But… Obde v Schlemeyer (1960) Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose Sale did not unite knowledge and control Many states require used car dealers to reveal major repairs done, sellers of homes to reveal certain types of defects… 30 Other reasons a contract may not be enforced 31 Vague contract terms Courts will generally not enforce contract terms that are overly vague Can be thought of as a penalty default But some exceptions Parties may commit to renegotiating the contract “in good faith” under certain contingencies 32 Fairness Bargain theory: courts ask only whether a contract was part of a bargain, not whether that bargain was fair Hamer v Sidway (drinking and smoking) But two common law doctrines to get out of extremely one-sided contracts Adhesion Unconscionability 33 Adhesion and unconscionability Adhesion: standardized “take-it-or-leave-it” contracts Friedman calls it “bogus duress” 34 Adhesion and unconscionability Adhesion: standardized “take-it-or-leave-it” contracts Friedman calls it “bogus duress” Unconscionability Overly one-sided contract may not be enforced Terms “such that no man in his senses and not under delusion would make on the one hand, and as no honest and fair man would accept on the other” When “the sum total of its provisions drives too hard a bargain for a court of conscience to assist” Terms which would “shock the conscience of the court” Similar concept in civil law: lesion 35 Unconscionability: Williams v WalkerThomas Furniture (CA Dist Ct, 1965) “Unconscionability has generally been recognized to include an absence of meaningful choice on the part of one of the parties together with contract terms which are unreasonably favorable to the other party. …In many cases the meaningfulness of the choice is negated by a gross inequality of bargaining power.” 36 Unconscionability: Williams v WalkerThomas Furniture (CA Dist Ct, 1965) “Unconscionability has generally been recognized to include an absence of meaningful choice on the part of one of the parties together with contract terms which are unreasonably favorable to the other party. …In many cases the meaningfulness of the choice is negated by a gross inequality of bargaining power.” 37 Unconscionability: Williams v WalkerThomas Furniture (CA Dist Ct, 1965) “Unconscionability has generally been recognized to include an absence of meaningful choice on the part of one of the parties together with contract terms which are unreasonably favorable to the other party. …In many cases the meaningfulness of the choice is negated by a gross inequality of bargaining power.” Not normal monopoly cases but “situational monopolies” Think of Ploof v Putnam (sailboat in a storm) 38 Midterms 39 Midterm Overall pretty good Mean 82, median 84, std dev 14 Not actually assigning letter grades till after final But to have an approximate idea of where you stand… 90s roughly AB or A 80s roughly B 70s roughly BC high 50s/60s roughly C A-H I-P Q-Z 40