Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2011 Lecture 15 Reminders Happy Halloween HW3 due Thursday (11:59 p.m.) Second midterm next Wednesday (Nov 9) Cumulative – covers property and contract law No tort law – covers everything through end of last lecture 1 Results from Wednesday’s experiment 2 A two-player game, similar to the investment/agency game Player A starts with $10 Chooses how much of it to give to player B That money is tripled Player B has $10, plus 3x whatever A gave him/her Chooses how much (if any) to give back to player A Four treatments Anonymous Private Face-to-face Public 3 Results In the anonymous version, trust was an issue On average, player A sent $5.69, so about half the potential gains were realized On average, player B sent back $8.09, so average payoffs were $12.40 and $18.98 Of those player A’s who sent something, 24% got back less than they sent, and 18% got back nothing Knowing who you were playing with helped In second version, average A sent $7.46, average B sent $11.49 Average payoffs of $14.04 and $20.88 11% of player A’s who sent something, still got nothing back 4 Results ANONYMOUS VERSION (STUDENT ID NUMBERS) A sent… # obs Avg B % zero 0 12 $0.08 1-3 7 4-6 PRIVATE VERSION (NAMES) # obs Avg B % zero 92% 3 $0.67 67% $0.93 57% 2 $3.50 0% 13 $8.08 8% 15 $6.53 13% 7-9 10 $11.40 10% 10 $9.70 20% 10 19 $14.05 16% 27 $16.70 7% Average $5.68 $8.09 33% $7.46 $11.49 14% 5 Let’s look just at the Player A’s who sent $10 Anonymous Private 19 27 % who got back $0 or $1 21% 7% % who got back $10 or $11 26% 19% % who got back $15 or $16 11% 22% % who got back $20 or more 42% 52% $14.05 $16.70 # of Player A who sent $10 Average received 6 Results Knowing the name of the person you’re playing with helped Increased trust significantly; increased trustworthiness a little Interacting face-to-face completely solved problem All 5 A’s sent $10, all 5 B’s sent back at least $15 That worked even better than playing the game in public! (Public version: two player A’s sent $10 and got back $20, one sent $8 and got back $0) 7 Let’s recap our story so far… 8 Our story so far Efficiency Maximizing total surplus realized by everyone in society Scarce resources are owned by whoever values them most Actions are taken if social benefit exceeds social cost Design a legal system that leads to efficient outcomes Once we set up the rules, we don’t expect people to act based on what’s efficient We expect people to do whatever’s in their own best interest So the goal is set up the rules such that people acting in their own best interest will naturally lead to efficiency 9 Our story so far Coase gives us one way to do that If property rights are clearly defined and tradable, and there are no transaction costs, people have incentive to trade until each resource is efficiently owned So initial allocation of rights doesn’t matter for efficiency But if there are transaction costs, we may not get efficiency this way Led us to two normative views of the legal system: 1. Minimize transaction costs (“lubricate” private exchange) 2. Allocate rights as efficiently as possible Tradeoff between injunctive relief and damages 10 Our story so far Property law works well for simultaneous trade Contracts allow for non-simultaneous trade Contract law can… Enable cooperation Encourage efficient disclosure of information Secure optimal commitment to performance Secure efficient reliance Supply efficient default rules and regulations Foster enduring relationships 11 Our story so far So far, we’ve been talking about voluntary exchange Coase is predicated on exchange being voluntary for both parties Contracts are an extension of voluntary trade Up next: “involuntary trade” You’re bicycling to class, I’m texting while driving and I hit you You didn’t want to deal with me, I didn’t want to deal with you… 12 Our story so far To put it another way… Property law covers situations where transaction costs are low enough to get agreement ahead of time Exceptions to property law – private necessity, eminent domain – when this isn’t the case Contract law covers situations when transaction costs are low enough for us to agree to a contract, high enough that we may not want to renegotiate the contract later Tort law covers situations where transaction costs are too high to agree to anything in advance 13 Tort law 14 An example 15 An example punish the choice • criminal law • regulations Choice + Bad Luck Outcome 16 An example punish the choice punish the outcome • criminal law • “strict liability” • regulations Choice + Bad Luck Outcome punish the combination of choice and outcome • “negligence” 17 Tort law Tort, noun. from French word meaning injury Contract law: situations where someone harms you by breaking a promise they had made Tort law: situations where someone harms you without having made any promises “If someone shoots you, you call a cop. If he runs his car into yours, you call a lawyer.” 18 As always, we’ll be focused on achieving efficiency I hit you with my car, do $1,000 worth of damage You’re $1,000 worse off (No damage to me or my car) Should I have to pay you damages? I owe nothing I owe $1,000 I owe $50,000 –1,000 0 49,000 My payoff 0 –1,000 –50,000 Combined payoffs –1,000 –1,000 –1,000 Your payoff 19 Something to remember distribution but not efficiency efficiency 20 Tort law Question: how to structure the law to get people to behave in a way that leads to efficient outcomes? Deliberate harms: make punishment severe (criminal law) Accidental harms: trickier Goal isn’t “no accidents”; goal is “efficient number of accidents” 21 Tort law Question: how to structure the law to get people to behave in a way that leads to efficient outcomes? Deliberate harms: make punishment severe (criminal law) Accidental harms: trickier Goal isn’t “no accidents”; goal is “efficient number of accidents” Unlike nuisance law, injunctive relief is not an option Unlike contract law, no agreement ahead of time Cooter and Ulen: essence of tort law is “the attempt to make injurers internalize the externalities they cause, in situations where transaction costs are too high to do this through property or contract rights” 22 Cast of characters Plaintiff – person who brings a lawsuit Defendant – person who is being sued In a nuisance case, the defendant caused a nuisance, plaintiff was bothered by it, might be asking for injunction or damages In a contract case, defendant breached a contract or violated its terms In a tort case, defendant caused some harm to plaintiff, plaintiff is asking for damages Plaintiff is the victim (person who was harmed) Defendant is the injurer (person who caused the harm) 23 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 24 Element 1: Harm For a tort to exist, the plaintiff needs to have been harmed “Without harm, there is no tort” Gas company sold gas with a defective additive Dangerous for cars with turbocharged carburetors You have a car with normal carburetors You might be angry; but you weren’t harmed, so you can’t sue Similarly, no compensation for exposure to risk Manufacturer exposed workers to some chemical Exposure will cause 15% of them to develop cancer later in life Can’t sue now – have to wait, see who gets cancer, then they can sue 25 Element 1: Harm Money Health Perfect compensation restores victim to original level of well-being generally done through money damages 26 Perfect Compensation Tangible harms • Medical costs • Lost income • Damaged property Intangible harms • Emotional harm • Pain and suffering • Loss of companionship In theory, perfect compensation should cover all losses Historically, courts have been less willing to compensate for intangible or hard-to-measure losses Over time, U.S. courts have started compensating for more intangible harms Pro: the closer liability is to actual harm done, the better the incentive to avoid these harms Con: disparity in award sizes, unpredictability 27 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 28 Element 2: Causation For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?” 29 Element 2: Causation For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?” Proximate cause Immediate cause – defendant’s action can’t be too distant from the harm Palsgraf v Long Island Railway (NY Ct Appeals, 1928): Guard pushed a passenger to help him onto train, passenger dropped fireworks he was carrying, they went off, explosion knocked down scales at the other end of the platform, which fell on Mrs. Palsgraf Guard’s actions were not the proximate cause 30 Element 2: Causation “A tree fell on a moving trolly, injuring passengers. One of them sued. He succeeded in demonstrating that in order for the trolly to be where it was when the tree fell on it the driver had to have driven faster than the speed limit at some point during the trip. Breaking the law is per se negligence, so the driver was legally negligent whether or not his driving was actually unsafe. If he had not driven over the speed limit, the trolly would not have been under the tree when it fell, so, the plaintiff argued, the driver’s negligence caused the injury.” Court ruled driver’s negligence “had not caused the accident in the legally relevant sense” 31 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 32 Element 3: Breach of Duty (Sometimes required, sometimes not) Strict Liability • Harm • Causation Negligence • Harm • Causation • Breach of duty (fault) When someone breaches a duty he owes to the defendant, and this leads to the harm, the injurer is at fault, or negligent Injurers owe victims the duty of due care Negligence rule: I’m only liable if I failed to take the required standard of care – not if I was careful and the accident happened anyway 33 Hence the language in the trolly example “A tree fell on a moving trolly, injuring passengers. One of them sued. He succeeded in demonstrating that in order for the trolly to be where it was when the tree fell on it the driver had to have driven faster than the speed limit at some point during the trip. Breaking the law is per se negligence, so the driver was legally negligent whether or not his driving was actually unsafe. If he had not driven over the speed limit, the trolly would not have been under the tree when it fell, so, the plaintiff argued, the driver’s negligence caused the injury.” 34 So under a negligence rule… If I breach my duty of due care and injure you, I am liable If I exercise the appropriate level of care but still injure you, I’m not liable How is the standard of care determined? That is, how careful do I have to be to avoid liability, and who decides? Is it negligent to drive 40 MPH on a particular road at a particular time of day? What about 41 MPH? 42? 35 How is the standard of care determined? Some settings: government imposes safety regulations that are also used as standard for negligence Speed limits for highway driving Requirement that bicycles have brakes Workplace regulations Some standards are left vague “Reckless driving” may depend on road, time of day, weather… Common law focuses on duty of reasonable care Level of care a reasonable person would have taken (Civil law relies less on “reasonableness” tests, tries to spell out what level of care is required) 36 Strict liability versus negligence Strict liability rule: plaintiff must prove harm and causation Negligence rule: must prove harm, causation, and negligence A little history Early Europe: strict liability was usual rule By early 1900s, negligence became usual rule Second half of 1900s, strict liability became more common again, especially for manufacturer liability in American consumer products U.S. manufacturers now held liable for harms caused by defective products, whether or not they were at fault 37 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 38 Economic model 39 Precaution The more carefully I drive, the less likely I am to hit you But, driving more carefully is also more costly to me Must be some efficient level of care Similarly… Construction company can reduce accidents with better safety equipment, better training, working shorter days, all of which cost money Manufacturer can reduce accidents by designing/inspecting products more carefully – again, more expensive 40 Actions by both injurer and victim impact number of accidents • speed like hell • drive slowly • drive drunk while texting • drive carefully • cheap, hasty manufacturing • careful quality control • save money • install smoke detectors, other safety equipment • wear helmet and use light • bicycle at night wearing black LESS EFFORT TO PREVENT ACCIDENTS “LESS PRECAUTION” GREATER EFFORT TO PREVENT ACCIDENTS “MORE PRECAUTION” 41 We will call all these things precaution Precaution: anything either injurer or victim could do to reduce likelihood of an accident (or damage done) The next two questions should be obvious… How much precaution do we want? What is efficient level of precaution? How do we design the law to get it? 42 To answer these questions, we’ll introduce a very simple model of accidents Car hits a bicycle In real life: driver probably has insurance In real life: some damage to bicycle, some damage to driver’s car In real life: driver and bicyclist may not even know what the law is We’ll simplify things a lot, by assuming… Only one party is harmed Parties know the law, don’t have insurance (for now) We’ll focus on one party’s precaution at a time 43 Model of unilateral harm x w p(x) A level of precaution marginal cost of precaution probability of an accident cost of an accident Unilateral harm – just one victim Precaution – costly actions that make accident less likely Could be taken by either victim or injurer We’ll focus on one at a time Notation x – the amount of precaution that is taken w – the cost of each “unit” of precaution p(x) – probability of an accident, given precaution x so total cost of precaution is wx p is decreasing in x A – cost of accident (to victim) so expected cost of accidents is p(x) A 44 Model of unilateral harm x w p(x) A level of precaution marginal cost of precaution probability of an accident cost of an accident efficient precaution: minx { wx + p(x) A } $ w + p’(x) A marginal social cost of precaution w marginal social benefit of precaution = 0 = – p’(x) A wx + p(x) A (Total Social Cost) wx (Cost of Precaution) p(x) A (Cost of Accidents) x* (Efficient Level of Precaution) x < x* x > x* Precaution (x) 45 Model of unilateral harm We haven’t yet said who is taking precaution Some situations, only injurer can reduce accidents Some situations, victim can too Bilateral precaution – we’ll look at the two parties one at a time Wednesday: consider effect of different liability rules on precaution 46 Effect of Liability Rules on Precaution (won’t get to this) 47 Effect of liability rules on precaution Three rules we’ll consider: No liability Strict liability Negligence 48 Rule 1: No Liability In a world with no liability… Victim bears the cost of any accidents, plus the cost of any precaution he takes Injurer bears cost of any precaution he takes, does not have to pay for accidents 49 Rule 1: No Liability Injurer precaution $ Private cost to injurer wx + p(x) A wx p(x) A x* x Injurer’s private cost is just wx Injurer minimizes private cost by setting x = 0 50 Rule 1: No Liability Victim precaution $ Private cost to victim wx + p(x) A wx p(x) A x* x Victim’s private cost is wx + p(x) A To minimize this, victim takes efficient level of precaution 51 Rule 1: No Liability So in a world with no liability… Injurer takes inefficiently low level of precaution (zero, or minimal amount) Victim takes efficient amount of precaution 52 Rule 2: Strict Liability Perfect compensation: damages D = A Under strict liability… Injurer pays damages for any accidents he causes So injurer bears cost of accidents, plus his own precaution Victim pays only for his precaution 53 Rule 2: Strict Liability Injurer precaution $ Private cost to injurer wx + p(x) A wx p(x) A x* x Injurer’s private cost is wx + p(x) A Injurer minimizes this by taking efficient level of precaution 54 Rule 2: Strict Liability Victim precaution $ Private cost to victim wx + p(x) A wx p(x) A x* x Victim’s private cost is wx No incentive to take any precaution, victim sets x = 0 55 Effect of liability rules on precaution No Liability Strict Liability Victim precaution Injurer precaution Efficient Zero Zero Efficient 56 So for accidents with unilateral precaution… When it’s the injurer who can take precautions, a rule of strict liability is more efficient When it’s the victim who can take precautions, a rule of no liability is more efficient Each rule works well for one incentive, poorly for other Similar to paradox of compensation we saw in contract law Negligence rule may allow us to get both incentives right 57 Rule 3: Simple Negligence “Simple Negligence” rule Legal standard of care xn Injurer is liable for damages if precaution level was below the legal standard of care x < xn D = A x xn D = 0 So on our graph from before, private cost to injurer is… wx + p(x) A wx for x < xn for x xn 58 Rule 3: Simple Negligence Injurer precaution $ Private cost to injurer wx + p(x) A wx p(x) A xn = x* x Private cost is wx + p(x) A if x < xn, only wx otherwise If standard of care is set efficiently (xn = x*), injurer minimizes private cost by taking efficient precaution 59 Rule 3: Simple Negligence Victim precaution What about victim? We just said, injurer will take efficient precaution Which means injurer will not be liable So victim bears costs of any accidents (Victim bears residual risk) So victim’s private cost is wx + p(x) A Victim minimizes private cost by taking efficient level of precaution too! $ Private cost to victim (assuming injurer takes efficient level of precaution and is therefore not liable for damages) wx + p(x) A wx p(x) A x* 60 Effect of liability rules on precaution No Liability Strict Liability Simple Negligence, with xn = x* Victim precaution Injurer precaution Efficient Zero Zero Efficient Efficient Efficient 61