Deep History: Deeper Waters A Review of David Laibman’s Deep History (New York, 2007) ‘My project is to reach behind the rich veins of human experience, in all its forms, through the entire time of our existence on Earth, and seek out explanatory principles that might help organise our understanding of that record – our basic sense of ourselves, where we have been and where we are going.’1 Except for those still enjoying the wordplay of postmodernism, historians and political theorists will appreciate opening a book with such a stated goal. Here is a subject worth getting to grips with, for it promises so very much: nothing less than a total conception of the pattern of history. David Laibman is a Marxist and the explanatory principles that he offers are derived from Marx’s formulations, in particular the notion of modes of production distinguished by their respective forces and relations of production. But this book is not an exegesis of Marx’s model of history; it is an adoption of these conceptual tools to entirely new formulations and ways of looking at the evolution of human societies. Direct quotes from Marx are few because the author does not want to reheat past debates about orthodoxy, but rather knuckle down to the substantive issue. What concepts explain the deep structural evolution of human history? Laibman’s answer is that there is a high level construct, the ‘abstract social totality’ (AST) that explains the logic of historical development. To be clear, for Laibman the AST is not a metaphor or helpful illustration, it is an explanatory, scientific, testable theory. Now for most readers of Imprints, this will be an attractively ambitious project. Nor is the goal of the author simply to provide historians and political theorists with new tools for academic investigations, Laibman is an ardent believer in the necessity for human beings to achieve a classless society, that is, ‘communism’ in its classical sense. The same logical schema that the author claims explains past epoch making historical changes also points towards future evolutions and the potential for the abolition of capitalism. I should state here that have enormous sympathy for this project in both its senses. There are patterns in history and I would like tools that help investigate them; there is a need to replace capitalism with a more egalitarian way of living and I would like this 1 Laibman 2007, p.viii. to be provable from an understanding of the past. My engagement with the book was therefore positive and whatever axes I might unconsciously find myself grinding elsewhere, I feel that I read this book with a hope that it would prove successful in its aims. My report, unfortunately, is that in several ways that are fundamental to its project, I believe the book to have failed. This conclusion has nothing to do with a fairly widespread belief that such totalising efforts in the social sciences are inevitably doomed by the complexity of human behaviour. In offering my, sometimes quite fundamental, reasons for believing that the work hasn’t achieved its goals I hope that I am not disparaging the spirit of the project. One very positive aspect of the book is that the author has approached the subject in a non-sectarian way. He is writing with the aim of enriching an important discussion for all those wishing to elucidate the movement of history from a perspective critical of modern capitalism. You also get the impression that the author is open-minded towards fair criticism. The tone of the book is admirably direct without being dogmatic, assertive without being defensive. It also shows a high degree of sensitivity to where the problem areas lie. The kinds of questions that Laibman poses with regard to his own project are thus: ‘Is this work good social theory? Does it contribute to our toolbox for a politically fruitful and developing understanding of history? Is it scientific, critical, humane, open? Does it help orient people in the vast emancipatory projects of our time? I face the answers to these questions with considerable trepidation; my only consolation is that they must also be asked of all other efforts rendered along the same lines.’2 I hope that the following observations, questions and disagreements will be understood as being written by a reader who shares the basic goals of the author, with the aspiration that they will assist to clarify very complex matters. The first question I would raise in regard to Deep History is a relatively obscure one, but one that does colour an assessment of the main innovations set forth in the book. Is the underlying philosophical method at work in this book appropriate to its goals? The author believes in ‘transcending’ contradictions. He writes that the nature versus nurture spectrum regarding human behaviour needs to be transcended.3 A section on the need to bring various 2 3 Ibid., p. x. Ibid., p. 21. streams of enquiry together is entitled ‘Synthesis: Transcending the Disciplinary Boundaries’.4 Most importantly for his project, Laibman believes he has found a way to transcend the apparent dichotomy between theories about history and the ‘tangle of formless empirical material’5 that arises from the study of specific historical moments. What this solution is will be discussed shortly, but here I just want to raise a doubt. The notion of transcendence of contradiction is, of course, perfectly orthodox in Marxism’s Hegelian inheritance. But an insightful transcendence of the Hegelian kind is, in fact, relatively rare in human thought. We are talking of radical shifts of perspective that allow us to see that what had formerly appeared to irreconcilable concepts are in fact one-sided features of a more dynamic, dialectical, totality. By contrast, for example, to say that the difference between apples and pears can be resolved by understanding them both as fruit is not very profound or dialectical in the above sense. Several times while reading this book I felt that the author was offering us apparently transcendent solutions to problems, but that his actual formula lacked the penetration necessary to really convince the reader that they were fundamental resolutions of contradictions rather than metaphysical constructions. The most critical example of this for Deep History is the question of whether Laibman has overcome the problem of ‘hard’ overarching historical theories dissolving in to ‘soft’ theories when undermined by specific micro studies. Whether, in other words, the dynamics of history can be explained at an abstract high level, without their having to be adapted to specific historical detail in such a way as they lose their explanatory power. ‘My suggestion,’ writes Laibman, is to overcome this dichotomy, by developing a theory that is simultaneously “hard” and “soft”. I posit level of abstraction, and arrange these into a hierarchy, so that at the “highest” level we find the abstract social totality (AST) and at a “lower” level the (more) concrete social formation reflecting geo-climatic and developmental variation. At still “lower” levels numerous contingent and accidental factors, including the personalities and capacities of individuals, come into play and infuse variety into the picture, which thus approaches the concreteness of the actual historical record.’6 4 Ibid., p. 121. Ibid., p. 4. 6 Ibid., p. 4. 5 Straight away, Laibman recognises that if this is a resolution of the ‘hard’ and ‘soft’ dichotomy, he has to demonstrate that the AST, the highest level of historical understanding, ‘must inform the construction of the lower levels, it cannot operate in a vacuum, independently of the rich detail of the historical record.’7 Secondly, the AST has to be falsifiable by the historical evidence. ‘Rejecting any simple path from pristine facts to confirmation or disconfirmation of theory, I still accept the responsibility to support the theory from the evidence and experience of history. In other words, the theory cannot merely be useful, or fruitful, it must, in some sense, be true as well.’8 The idea then is that the two opposites (crudely: theory and data) affect each other, but not equally. The AST encompasses both the next level down, social formations, and below that, very particular events. Philosophically, this is schema is consistent with Laibman’s notion of dialectics. ‘Dialectics refers not simply to mutual interaction, but to interaction between unequal poles. In a dialectical interaction, dominant determination runs from one pole to the other; without this, the dialectic characterizes the mutual conditioning of the poles, their relational consistency, but does not reveal a dynamic movement in the system that they constitute.’9 It seems to me that this formulation is different to the classic Hegelian – Marxist tradition, for which the revelation of dynamics occurs at a different level to that of the contradictions (from the level of the ‘negation of the negation’ to use Hegelian language). Laibman’s italicising of ‘dominant determination’ is curiously evocative of those who want to ‘de-Hegelianise’ Marx’s dialectics10 and as an aside I would ask Laibman if this is conscious? But it is time to move from philosophy to history and I simply flag the point that I think the methodology of the book is being shaped, for better or worse, at this rather intangible philosophical level. In any case, what matters here is whether we are being offered a metaphysical construction or a valuable method of understanding the relationship between the trends of history and the concrete historical record. The most important theoretical assertion by Laibman is that the abstract social totality (AST) explains the pattern of history. ‘Social evolution proceeds through a series of stages, and at the 7 Ibid, p. 4. Ibid, p. 4. 9 Ibid., p. 51. 10 Althusser 1970, p. 178; Haug, 2006. 8 level of the AST these stages are an absolutely determinate ladder.’11 And ‘the determinate ladder of theoretical stages – assuming it exists, an assumption that cannot be separated from confirmation of its ongoing extraction from the raw material of history – occurs only at the level of the AST. As soon as we depart from this level and examine social formations at more concrete levels, variety in external conditions and consequent variations in pace and detailed features of development are introduced. We might say that the AST would only be directly visible only on a planet with one continent, with no mountains, rivers, narrow isthmuses or any other barriers to communication and diffusion of cultural traits, and a common climate, flora, fauna and so on.’12 The point about the hypothetical planet is vivid and makes Laibman’s contention admirably clear. Given those ‘perfect’ conditions, human society would necessarily go through certain historical periods. These being: primitive communism, slavery, feudalism and capitalism. These periods are derived not from historical observation, but from the logic of the structures of the AST.13 What are those structures? They are the ‘productive forces’ (PF) and the ‘production relations’ (PR) that will be familiar to readers of Imprints from the works of Marx and the huge subsequent literature about them. The PFs and PRs form a consistent whole, the ‘mode of production’ (MP). Laibman, probably wisely given that it would lead away from his main purpose, does not spend a great deal of time on the debates about these concepts. Rather he formulates two propositions that are important for developing his logical stages-view of history. Firstly, that PRs are progressively replaced over time with ever more sophisticated PRs and, secondly, there is a tendency towards development in the PFs. Because any particular set of PRs tend to stasis, a tension develops within a mode of production, resolved if a revolution takes place leading to a new mode of production. Laibman rather ably defends himself from those who would characterise such a view as ‘productive forces determinism’, by pointing out that that the whole dynamic of the model relies on a notion that the PRs persistently shape the PFs. They progressively restrain the PFs, blocking the development of productivity like ‘so many fetters’ to be ‘burst asunder’ in the famous phrase of Marx. Laibman 2007, p. 4 – 5. Ibid., p. 5. 13 Ibid., p. 28. 11 12 According to Laibman there have been five stages (modes of production) in human history: primitive communism, slavery, feudalism, capitalism and (modern) communism. The ordering of these modes ‘is not determined from historical observation as such… The ordering is theoretical, not empirical, and is based on the concept that the development of the PFs, through the entire period of class-antagonistic MPs requires periodic replacement of PRs, in an order revealing progressively more sophisticated and powerful means of coercion, incentive and control. This ordering must now be explained.’14 Now we come to the crunch. If this model is something more than a way of organising historical material, if changes in history can be explained at this AST level, then the test is whether the logic of the model requires human history to evolve through these stages. Laibman thinks it does, I wasn’t convinced. The first transition that Laibman believes arises from AST considerations is from primitive communism to the slave mode of production. Laibman, who rejects the idea present in Marx that there was ever an ‘Asiatic mode of production’, asserts that slavery is logically and necessarily the first form of systematic surplus extraction. The slave mode of production, he argues, appears when it is possible to extract a surplus large enough to support the necessary apparatuses of coercion and control, and at a time when only direct physical coercion will produce a surplus.15 Purely on the basis of the content of these formulations and not the actual historical record, in other words, from within Laibman’s own framework, are these definitions enough to convince us that the first form of class society has to be slavery rather than, say, one based on the extraction of tributes from peasants? Suppose agriculture to have reached the point that it is possible to generate significant surpluses and suppose coercion necessary to gather this surplus, why would the person being exploited, be, in the first instance, a slave, the chattel of a ruling class? Isn’t it as likely, in fact, that initially the first elites would not be able to leap from primitive communism straight to owning other human beings, but rather and perhaps over many centuries, their privileged position would have arisen through the gradual tightening of their control over the limited surplus available to society? If we leave the terrain of logic and structure to follow E. Gordon Childe’s account of the actual origins of class society on 14 15 Ibid., p. 28. Ibid., p. 28. this planet, then as well as the appearance of slavery we find examples, such as that of ancient Egypt, where tomb paintings show ‘peasants coming in to pay their rent or dues, always in kind, while a scribe notes down on papyrus what each man brings and an overseer with a whip keeps the tributaries up to the mark.’16 This latter source of wealth was almost certainly far more important initially than that created by slaves.17 It is possible for Laibman’s schema to be adjusted to take in to account the above point, he does not, in fact, need to insist that slavery was the first form of exploitation to have a working AST model, but already the particular model we have been offered looks inexact. Nevertheless, assuming, then, that a slave mode of production has come in to being, is there a dynamic, at the AST level, that explains what will happen to it? Laibman follows earlier Marxist historians in saying that there is a fundamental problem for the stability of a slave mode of production in that it is continually obliged to seek outside its own territory for new sources of slaves and to devote an increasing share of the surplus to supporting this activity. The slave MP also, because of the lack of incentive for the slave to develop the productive forces intensively has a tendency to expand them extensively: larger agricultural holdings, construction projects, etc. The PF – PR model therefore points towards a crisis of the mode of production, as more and more of the share of the surplus is devoted to the means of coercion and control in this expanding system. For Laibman, the explanation for the overrunning of Rome by Germanic and other peoples ultimately lies at the level of the AST.18 There are many accounts of the decline of Roman civilisation as well as an increasing number of both Marxist and non-Marxist studies that argue the decline has been exaggerated.19 My own preference is for that of G. E. M. de Ste. Croix. This differs from Laibman’s AST explanation in one very important aspect. The author of Deep History believes that the backdrop of small-scale peasant production against which the gangs of slaves are working is an ‘inert medium within which the slave dynamic occurs.’ For Ste Croix, on the other hand, the decline of the importance of slavegenerated surpluses (for, approximately, the reasons given above) caused a massive tightening of the screw by the Roman elite on 16 Childe 1966, p. 166. Harman, 1999, p. 22 – 8. 18 Laibman 2007, p. 30. 19 Most recently Ward-Perkins 2007. 17 the non-slave lower social classes. The ruination and demoralisation of the once-free Roman peasantry is what contributed, above all, to the inability of the empire to save itself from invasion.20 The difference is important for the question of methodology. Laibman’s book is an attempt to distil a few high level explanations for the pattern of history, it does not suit this project to have to constantly adjust ‘hard’ theory with ‘soft’ lowerlevel historical data; but without amendment, the explanation for the conquest of the Western Roman Empire in Deep History seems inadequate. The crisis of the slave mode of production gives way to the feudal mode. Laibman argues that this change is a necessary one because it is not possible for a slave mode of production to move directly to a capitalist mode.21 Now again, adhering strictly to the logic of the model and setting aside actual historical events for the moment, I have a question about this. I’m happy to agree that at the AST level, a slave mode of production cannot develop directly into a capitalist one, but why, therefore, must the end of slavery mean specifically feudalism? There are several theoretical ways in which surpluses could be extracted from a labouring class. Excluding the possibility of a capitalist form does not necessitate a feudal form: that needs to be demonstrated. Here we are not helped by Laibman’s definition of a feudal mode of production. ‘The feudal solution rests on the confinement of class relations to the small scale of the manor: a self-contained and territorially enclosed social system based on agricultural production (although it also incorporates handicrafts and other non-agricultural activities). The ruling function rests in the Lord of the Manor, with a retinue of retainers and a caste of military functionaries (the knighthood). The subjugated producing class consists of serfs, who are held in service to the lord (vassalage) through their connection to the land. Unlike slaves, serfs are not owned outright by the lord; they cannot be bought and sold. Tied to the manor by birth, they also have a right to that connection, which cannot be taken from them.’22 Medieval historians, Marxist or otherwise, would only recognise parts of this definition. Since we are dealing with logic and structure, rather than history, Laibman can, of course, define feudalism however he wants. But if the model is ultimately to be de Ste. Croix 1981, pp. 453 – 503. Laibman 2007, p. 30. 22 Ibid., p. 31. 20 21 used to explain developments in our world, rather than remain a theoretical abstraction, this particular definition needs amendment in two regards. Firstly, serfs were commonly bought and sold; they were invariably transferred when the land they worked changed ownership and were typically described in charters as if the property of the owner of the land. Secondly, the relationship between a serf and the lord of a manor was not one of vassalage. A vassal owed military service to the lord in return for a fief (typically an area of land - along with its serfs - later a financial stipend), the relationship established by an act of homage between the vassal and their lord. In other words, vassalage was a relationship between senior and lesser members of the ruling class, not between lords and serfs. Once again, it is possible to bring Laibman’s schema into line with an identifiable version of feudalism as it existed historically by adjusting his definitions. It should also be possible to address the question of why feudalism after slavery. But the fact that Laibman’s current formulations are shaky plants doubts in the overall project. Are we really discovering the deep structures of history? Or is something rather more circular going on here? At this point in the book I began to lose heart that these AST levels of explanation were really illuminating the patterns of history. The links in the chain leading from one mode of production to the next seemed to me to be breakable precisely at the points where they were supposed to be demonstrating the power of the AST method. In Laibman’s discussion of the dynamics of feudalism, he convincingly demonstrates that their most important feature is that, by contrast with slavery, there is an incentive for the producers to improve the techniques of production. As a consequence, the PFs advance to what Laibman terms ‘the second-most-difficult of the revolutionary transitions: to capitalism.’23 Does the AST model have something to say about the muchdebated transition of feudalism to capitalism? Laibman believes so. He argues that an understanding of the dynamics between the PFs and the PRs in late medieval society explain why the transition is protracted and why it takes place in separate stages. Many theories notice that new markets and trade act to dissolve the manorial economy, without offering an explanation for why these markets and trading incomes should have appeared. Those which suggest or imply that the feudal ruling class themselves intentionally introduce these new forms of wealth is rejected, 23 Ibid., p. 36. correctly in my opinion, by Laibman. Instead ‘there is an inherent low-level trap in this transition, one in which the surpluses that are needed to transform merchants and artisans into capitalists is lodged in a reduced, but fortified feudal sector.’24 This blockage by a resistant feudal core is why the transition is so very long. Unless I have missed it somewhere though, Laibman does not offer an explanation of why the blockage is eventually overcome. Presumably the answer would lie in some reformulation at the level of PF – PR interaction of the position of those, such as Dobb and Brenner, who believe that the answer has to be sought in terms of the generation of new forms of wealth within the structures of feudalism. Capitalism is the next mode of production for the AST treatment. Here Laibman defends Marx’s theory of value, successfully in my opinion. He offers an account of the elements of surplus extraction with a conceptual geometrical figure to illustrate his schema.25 A passing critique of the Analytical Marxist authors is made: on the grounds of their abstracting rational actors from all social character. Laibman then turns to deriving from his model the reasons why the capitalist mode of production is doomed. When it comes to offering crisis theories for capitalism, Laibman points out that there is a long spectrum of opinion, even among Marxists, as to the nature of such crises: whether they are endemic, inevitable, or likely to lead to an ending of the system. Laibman places his theory at the extreme end of the spectrum. Crises are more than temporary resolutions of capitalism’s instability, they occur with increasing severity along a long-term path towards the inviability of the continuance of the capitalist system.26 As Laibman points out, this position corresponds most fully to the basic claim of Marxism, which sees the transcendence of capitalism and its replacement by socialism/communism, as more than merely desirable. The problem with defending the most ambitious claims of Marxism with regard to the intensification of crises, says Laibman, is that all of the theories offered, with the exception of the falling rate of profit argument, have failed to be rigorously convincing, and even the falling rate of profit position appears suspect to many observers due to the perversity of the evidence. 24 Ibid., p. 40. Ibid., p. 81. 26 Ibid., p. 93 – 4. 25 Laibman therefore, with some implied sympathy for the falling rate of profit argument, tries to offer an AST level explanation for the inevitable intensification of crises under capitalism. Another conceptual geometry proposal presents the various elements of his theory. I found this discussion and method of conducting it to be useful. If the right diagram can be constructed, it helps clarify and model complex phenomena, like capitalist crises. The author is well aware that the figure he offers does not contain all the possible linkages, without which there is a danger that ‘the entire construction will collapse once again into total reciprocity and indeterminacy, but the danger must be faced.’27 In all this I found myself closer to Laibman than at any other place in the book and, whilst tempted to be old-fashioned by trying to find a special place for the falling rate of profit argument rather than have it share importance with other roots of capitalist crisis, am willing to go along with the schema in Deep History. The discussion gets suddenly more complex, however, when Laibman wants to distinguish the capitalist mode of production from the other modes of production on the grounds that it has within it a nest of evolutionary stages, under the larger construct of the AST. The justification for this layering is that of complexity: there are long cycles at the level of AST, within which are shorter cycles of structures that still remain above the level of full historical contingency. Why, intrinsically, should capitalism deserve this treatment and not the other modes of production? Medievalists, for example, could happily point to very distinct stages within their period, with important structural dynamics operating differently at different times. So, for example, Duby amongst others has drawn attention to how, in parts of France around the year 1000, the social order of warriors crystalised into a distinct, self-consciously noble, ruling elite: marking a very distinct periodisation within the general medieval framework.28 Even allowing for a theory of sub-stages operating uniquely within the capitalist mode of production, I do not accept the particular set of stages offered by Laibman. It is interesting, but it seems overly derived from his political outlook rather than the kind of logical inferences that his method requires. I had no idea what the author’s politics were before reading the book, but at this point I think they become evident. According to the author’s system, we are in stage III of capitalism, one where there is a troubled and protracted move 27 28 Ibid., p. 115. Duby 1980, passim. from the cold war towards a totalised global capitalist world, stage IV. ‘Stage IV would involve a global, passive, state, an end to diffusion.’29 It ‘requires the global state that transnational capitalist class theorists observe as immanent in the emerging world institutions (World Bank, IMF etc.).’30 It is strange, having discussed history at a very philosophical level up until now, to find the book invoking specific historical institutions. Once again the reader is told that this model is genuinely theoretical in the sense that the move from one stage to another is chain linked. But for me the schema is flawed by the author’s belief that Islam is fundamentally more reactionary than Judaism and Christianity;31 that a very long time period must elapse before an end to the capitalist mode of production is possible;32 that the Gorbachev era represented a mature version of socialism in Soviet Russia;33 and that even now the post-Soviet Russian social formation is not capitalist.34 I happen to disagree with all these statements, but even if I did not, there is a problem. By claiming to derive these propositions from ‘the careful guidelines laid down by the PF – PR model’,35 Laibman runs the danger of wrecking his schema altogether. It hardly seems credible that such historically specific conclusions derive from the AST analysis. Surely these relatively ‘low level’ statements (compared to the book’s entire theme of deep history) have to be analysed at a much more historically concrete level, or we end up having an AST theory that threatens to become crudely determinist. A theory intended to operate over ten thousand years is suddenly applicable to decades. To judge from an introductory comment by Laibman, he is open to suggestions about alternatives to his model. ‘Am I losing track of important elements, placing them into the category of fortuitous and accidental phenomena, only to focus on an incomplete set of basic principles? Possibly! That is for critics of my account to argue. But the proof of their pudding will be in the alternative theory posed by them. To show how it can be done 29 Laibman 2007, p. 136. Ibid., p. 136. 31 Ibid., p. 139. 32 Ibid., p. 137. 33 Ibid., p. 181 – 2. 34 Ibid., p. 183. 35 Ibid., p. 183. 30 better is quite a different matter from abandoning the attempt altogether.’36 I have done my best to discuss the ideas of Deep History from within the framework set by the author. In other words, I have taken seriously the possibility that there are dynamics, understandable from the highest level, the abstract social totality, that explain the necessary development of human history. If such dynamics exist though, I do not believe, for the reasons stated above, that they are the ones given by the author. I hope that my comments have indicated the direction in which I think the various models for each mode of production, in my view, require amendment. I have to say though, that I am dubious whether ultimately the methodology will prove to be a fruitful one. Deep History keeps its focus on the issues that Laibman wanted to address by quite consciously avoiding digging for quotes by canonical Marxists. This is a welcome feature of the book because over their lifetimes and arising from very different contexts, Marx and Engels made statements that when placed against each other can look inconsistent. Moreover, being human, they changed their minds about some issues and reformulated others. Thinking about the methodology in Deep History, did, however, cause me to reach for the bookshelves in the hope that these thinkers might help me put my finger on what it was about the project that I, at some basic level, found unsatisfactory. One particular comment by Marx in the German Ideology seems so relevant and helpful that I hope Laibman will not mind my quoting it. ‘When reality is depicted, philosophy as an independent branch of knowledge loses its medium of existence. At the best its place can only be taken by a summing-up of the most general results, abstractions that arise from the observation of the historical development of humanity. Viewed apart from real history, these abstractions have in themselves no value whatsoever. They can only serve to facilitate the arrangement of historical material, to indicate the sequence of its separate strata. But they by no means afford a recipe or schema, as does philosophy, for neatly trimming the epochs of history.’37 If I am to satisfy Laibman’s request, that in rejecting his model, a critic is obliged to put forward an alternative theory, I would take inspiration from this quote of Marx’s. It seems to me that what is needed for a deep understanding of the dynamics of 36 37 Ibid., p. viii. Marx 1970, p. 48. history is not a variant of the AST schema but rather one that works the other way around, inside-out, as it were. A model derived from taking as a starting point the actual, material, sensuous, warts-and-all, experience of human history does, of course, already exist. I think that Marx’s own theoretical formulations about history form the bulk of such an alternative theory. Which might seem odd given that Laibman’s AST is also derived from Marxist concepts. But there is a fundamental difference in approach between that of Marx and that in Deep History. Marx’s generalisations about history were derived by examining particular historical moments, their contradictions, and thus arriving at powerful insights that were sometimes at a very high level of abstraction: such as his famous Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. By contrast, I have arrived at an opinion, perhaps rather harshly, that Deep History makes the methodological mistake of deriving a new recipe for trimming the epochs of history out of Marx’s highest level generalisations and loses track of the fact that a powerful truth always comes to human consciousness from practice. If we want to obtain new deep theoretical insights into a particular mode of production, or about all of human history, they will be generalisations wrung after a great deal of effort and study from an investigation of actual history and not a priori logical deductions arising from certain conceptual definitions. To finish, however, on a positive note. Deep History is a very refreshing book. It is rare these days to encounter historiographical works of any sort that deal with an entire, totalising, conception of history. Historians and political theorists failing to address such matters though, run the risk of holding to unconscious or semiconscious set of ideas about ‘larger’ matters that must inevitably affect their particular area of local expertise. It was a real pleasure to think about these topics for the first time in many years and I feel that my engagement with the book has led to a welcome enrichment of my own practice as a socialist and as an historian. Conor Kostick Trinity College, Dublin References Althusser, Louis 1970, Reading Capital, London: NLB. Childe, E. Gordon 1966, Man Makes Himself, London: Fontana. Duby, Georges 1980, The Three Orders, Feudal Society Imagined, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Harman, Chris 1999, A People’s History of the World, London: Bookmarks. Haug, Wolfgang Fritz 2006, ‘Marx’s Learning Process: Against Correcting Marx with Hegel’, Rethinking Marxism, 18, 4: 572 – 84. Laibman, David 2007, Deep History, New York: State of New York Press. Marx, Karl 1970 [1932], The German Ideology, London: Lawrence & Wishart. de Ste. Croix, G. E. M., The Class Struggle in the Ancient Greek World, London: Duckworth. Ward-Perkins, Bryan 2007, The Fall of Rome and the End of Civilization, Oxford: Oxford University Press.