Bayesian models of inductive learning Tom Griffiths Josh Tenenbaum UC Berkeley MIT Charles Kemp MIT What to expect • What you’ll get out of this tutorial: – Our view of what Bayesian models have to offer cognitive science. – In-depth examples of basic and advanced models: how the math works & what it buys you. – Some (not extensive) comparison to other approaches. – Opportunities to ask questions. • What you won’t get: – Detailed, hands-on how-to. – Where you can learn more: • http://bayesiancognition.com • Trends in Cognitive Sciences, July 2006, special issue on “Probabilistic Models of Cognition”. Outline • Morning – Introduction: Why Bayes? (Josh) – Basic of Bayesian inference (Josh) – Graphical models, causal inference and learning (Tom) • Afternoon – Hierarchical Bayesian models, property induction, and learning domain structures (Charles) – Methods of approximate learning and inference, probabilistic models of semantic memory (Tom) Why Bayes? • The problem of induction – How does the mind form inferences, generalizations, models or theories about the world from impoverished data? • Induction is ubiquitous in cognition – – – – – Vision (+ audition, touch, or other perceptual modalities) Language (understanding, production) Concepts (semantic knowledge, “common sense”) Causal learning and reasoning Decision-making and action (production, understanding) • Bayes gives a general framework for explaining how induction can work in principle, and perhaps, how it does work in the mind…. S NP VP Grammar G NP Det [ Adj ] Noun [ RelClause ] RelClause [ Rel ] NP V VP VP NP P(S | G) VP Verb Phrase structure S P(U | S) P( Utterance U P(S | U, G) ~ P(U | S) x P(S | G) Bottom-up Top-down “Universal Grammar” Hierarchical phrase structure grammars (e.g., CFG, HPSG, TAG) P(grammar | UG) Grammar P(phrase structure | grammar) Phrase structure P(utterance | phrase structure) Utterance P(speech | utterance) Speech signal (c.f. Chater and Manning, 2006) S NP VP NP Det [ Adj ] Noun [ RelClause ] RelClause [ Rel ] NP V VP VP NP VP Verb The approach • Key concepts – Inference in probabilistic generative models – Hierarchical probabilistic models, with inference at all levels of abstraction – Structured knowledge representations: graphs, grammars, predicate logic, schemas, theories – Flexible structures, with complexity constrained by Bayesian Occam’s razor – Approximate methods of learning and inference: ExpectationMaximization (EM), Markov chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) • Much recent progress! – Computational resources to implement and test models that we could dream up but not realistically imagine working with – New theoretical tools let us develop models that we could not clearly conceive of before. Vision as probabilistic parsing (Han and Zhu, 2006) Word learning on planet Gazoob “tufa” “tufa” “tufa” Can you pick out the tufas? Learning word meanings Principles Structure Data Whole-object principle Shape bias Taxonomic principle Contrast principle Basic-level bias Causal learning and reasoning Principles Structure Data Goal-directed action (production and comprehension) (Wolpert et al., 2003) Marr’s Three Levels of Analysis • Computation: “What is the goal of the computation, why is it appropriate, and what is the logic of the strategy by which it can be carried out?” • Algorithm: Cognitive psychology • Implementation: Neurobiology Alternative approaches to inductive learning and inference • • • • • • Associative learning Connectionist networks Similarity to examples Toolkit of simple heuristics Constraint satisfaction Analogical mapping Summary: Why Bayes? • A unifying framework for explaining cognition. – How people can learn so much from such limited data. – Strong quantitative models with minimal ad hoc assumptions. – Why algorithmic-level models work the way they do. • A framework for understanding how structured knowledge and statistical inference interact. – How structured knowledge guides statistical inference, and may itself be acquired through statistical means. – What forms knowledge takes, at multiple levels of abstraction. – What knowledge must be innate, and what can be learned. – How flexible knowledge structures may grow as required by the data, with complexity controlled by Occam’s razor. Outline • Morning – Introduction: Why Bayes? (Josh) – Basic of Bayesian inference (Josh) – Graphical models, causal inference and learning (Tom) • Afternoon – Hierarchical Bayesian models, property induction, and learning domain structures (Charles) – Methods of approximate learning and inference, probabilistic models of semantic memory (Tom) Bayes’ rule For any hypothesis h and data d, Posterior probability Likelihood Prior probability p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH Sum over space of alternative hypotheses Bayesian inference P ( h) P ( d | h) • Bayes’ rule: P(h | d ) P(hi ) P(d | hi ) • An example hi – Data: John is coughing – Some hypotheses: 1. John has a cold 2. John has emphysema 3. John has a stomach flu – Prior favors 1 and 3 over 2 – Likelihood P(d|h) favors 1 and 2 over 3 – Posterior P(d|h) favors 1 over 2 and 3 Coin flipping • Basic Bayes – data = HHTHT or HHHHH – compare two simple hypotheses: P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Parameter estimation (Model fitting) – compare many hypotheses in a parameterized family P(H) = q : Infer q • Model selection – compare qualitatively different hypotheses, often varying in complexity: P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = q Coin flipping HHTHT HHHHH What process produced these sequences? Comparing two simple hypotheses • Contrast simple hypotheses: – h1: “fair coin”, P(H) = 0.5 – h2:“always heads”, P(H) = 1.0 • Bayes’ rule: P ( h) P ( d | h) P(h | d ) P(hi ) P(d | hi ) hi • With two hypotheses, use odds form Comparing two simple hypotheses P( H1 | D) P( H 2 | D) D: P( D | H1 ) P( D | H 2 ) HHTHT H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/25 P(H1) = ? P(D|H2) = 0 P(H2) = 1-? P( H1 ) P( H 2 ) Comparing two simple hypotheses P( H1 | D) P( H 2 | D) D: P( D | H1 ) P( D | H 2 ) P( H1 ) P( H 2 ) HHTHT H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/25 P(H1) = 999/1000 P(D|H2) = 0 P(H2) = 1/1000 P( H1 | D) P( H 2 | D) 1 32 999 0 1 infinity Comparing two simple hypotheses P( H1 | D) P( H 2 | D) D: P( D | H1 ) P( D | H 2 ) P( H1 ) P( H 2 ) HHHHH H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/25 P(H1) = 999/1000 P(D|H2) = 1 P(H2) = 1/1000 P ( H1 | D ) P( H 2 | D) 1 999 32 1 30 Comparing two simple hypotheses P( H1 | D) P( H 2 | D) D: P( D | H1 ) P( D | H 2 ) P( H1 ) P( H 2 ) HHHHHHHHHH H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/210 P(H1) = 999/1000 P(D|H2) = 1 P(H2) = 1/1000 P ( H1 | D ) P( H 2 | D) 1 999 1024 1 1 The role of intuitive theories The fact that HHTHT looks representative of a fair coin and HHHHH does not reflects our implicit theories of how the world works. – Easy to imagine how a trick all-heads coin could work: high prior probability. – Hard to imagine how a trick “HHTHT” coin could work: low prior probability. Coin flipping • Basic Bayes – data = HHTHT or HHHHH – compare two hypotheses: P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Parameter estimation (Model fitting) – compare many hypotheses in a parameterized family P(H) = q : Infer q • Model selection – compare qualitatively different hypotheses, often varying in complexity: P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = q Parameter estimation • Assume data are generated from a parameterized model: q d1 d2 d3 d4 P(H) = q • What is the value of q ? – each value of q is a hypothesis H – requires inference over infinitely many hypotheses Model selection • Assume hypothesis space of possible models: q d1 d2 d3 d4 Fair coin: P(H) = 0.5 d1 d2 d3 P(H) = q d4 s1 s2 s3 s4 d1 d2 d3 d4 Hidden Markov model: si {Fair coin, Trick coin} • Which model generated the data? – requires summing out hidden variables – requires some form of Occam’s razor to trade off complexity with fit to the data. Parameter estimation vs. Model selection across learning and development • Causality: learning the strength of a relation vs. learning the existence and form of a relation • Language acquisition: learning a speaker's accent, or frequencies of different words vs. learning a new tense or syntactic rule (or learning a new language, or the existence of different languages) • Concepts: learning what horses look like vs. learning that there is a new species (or learning that there are species) • Intuitive physics: learning the mass of an object vs. learning about gravity or angular momentum • Intuitive psychology: learning a person’s beliefs or goals vs. learning that there can be false beliefs, or that visual access is valuable for establishing true beliefs A hierarchical learning framework model M parameters w Parameter estimation: p( w | D, M ) p( D | w, M ) p( w | M ) data D A hierarchical learning framework model class C p( D | M ) p( D | w, M ) p( w | M ) w Model selection: model M parameters w p ( M | D, C ) p ( D | M ) p ( M | C ) Parameter estimation: p( w | D, M ) p( D | w, M ) p( w | M ) data D Bayesian parameter estimation • Assume data are generated from a model: q d1 d2 d3 d4 P(H) = q • What is the value of q ? – each value of q is a hypothesis H – requires inference over infinitely many hypotheses Some intuitions • • • • D = 10 flips, with 5 heads and 5 tails. q = P(H) on next flip? 50% Why? 50% = 5 / (5+5) = 5/10. Why? “The future will be like the past” • Suppose we had seen 4 heads and 6 tails. • P(H) on next flip? Closer to 50% than to 40%. • Why? Prior knowledge. Integrating prior knowledge and data p( D | q ) p(q ) p(q | D) p( D) • Posterior distribution P(q | D) is a probability density over q = P(H) • Need to work out likelihood P(D | q ) and specify prior distribution P(q ) Likelihood and prior • Likelihood: Bernoulli distribution P(D | q ) = q NH (1-q ) NT – NH: number of heads – NT: number of tails • Prior: P(q ) ? Some intuitions • • • • D = 10 flips, with 5 heads and 5 tails. q = P(H) on next flip? 50% Why? 50% = 5 / (5+5) = 5/10. Why? Maximum likelihood: qˆ arg max P( D | q ) q • Suppose we had seen 4 heads and 6 tails. • P(H) on next flip? Closer to 50% than to 40%. • Why? Prior knowledge. A simple method of specifying priors • Imagine some fictitious trials, reflecting a set of previous experiences – strategy often used with neural networks or building invariance into machine vision. • e.g., F ={1000 heads, 1000 tails} ~ strong expectation that any new coin will be fair • In fact, this is a sensible statistical idea... Likelihood and prior • Likelihood: Bernoulli(q ) distribution P(D | q ) = q NH (1-q ) NT – NH: number of heads – NT: number of tails • Prior: Beta(FH,FT) distribution P(q ) q FH-1 (1-q ) FT-1 – FH: fictitious observations of heads – FT: fictitious observations of tails Shape of the Beta prior Shape of the Beta prior FH = 0.5, FT = 0.5 FH = 0.5, FT = 2 FH = 2, FT = 0.5 FH = 2, FT = 2 Bayesian parameter estimation P(q | D) P(D | q ) P(q ) = q NH+FH-1 (1-q ) NT+FT-1 • Posterior is Beta(NH+FH,NT+FT) – same form as prior! – expected P(H) = (NH+FH) / (NH+FH+NT+FT) Conjugate priors • A prior p(q ) is conjugate to a likelihood function p(D | q ) if the posterior has the same functional form of the prior. – Parameter values in the prior can be thought of as a summary of “fictitious observations”. – Different parameter values in the prior and posterior reflect the impact of observed data. – Conjugate priors exist for many standard models (e.g., all exponential family models) Some examples • e.g., F ={1000 heads, 1000 tails} ~ strong expectation that any new coin will be fair • After seeing 4 heads, 6 tails, P(H) on next flip = 1004 / (1004+1006) = 49.95% • e.g., F ={3 heads, 3 tails} ~ weak expectation that any new coin will be fair • After seeing 4 heads, 6 tails, P(H) on next flip = 7 / (7+9) = 43.75% Prior knowledge too weak But… flipping thumbtacks • e.g., F ={4 heads, 3 tails} ~ weak expectation that tacks are slightly biased towards heads • After seeing 2 heads, 0 tails, P(H) on next flip = 6 / (6+3) = 67% • Some prior knowledge is always necessary to avoid jumping to hasty conclusions... • Suppose F = { }: After seeing 1 heads, 0 tails, P(H) on next flip = 1 / (1+0) = 100% Origin of prior knowledge • Tempting answer: prior experience • Suppose you have previously seen 2000 coin flips: 1000 heads, 1000 tails Problems with simple empiricism • Haven’t really seen 2000 coin flips, or any flips of a thumbtack – Prior knowledge is stronger than raw experience justifies • Haven’t seen exactly equal number of heads and tails – Prior knowledge is smoother than raw experience justifies • Should be a difference between observing 2000 flips of a single coin versus observing 10 flips each for 200 coins, or 1 flip each for 2000 coins – Prior knowledge is more structured than raw experience A simple theory • “Coins are manufactured by a standardized procedure that is effective but not perfect, and symmetric with respect to heads and tails. Tacks are asymmetric, and manufactured to less exacting standards.” – Justifies generalizing from previous coins to the present coin. – Justifies smoother and stronger prior than raw experience alone. – Explains why seeing 10 flips each for 200 coins is more valuable than seeing 2000 flips of one coin. A hierarchical Bayesian model physical knowledge Coins q ~ Beta(FH,FT) FH,FT Coin 1 d1 Coin 2 q1 d2 d3 d4 d1 d2 ... q2 d3 d4 q200 Coin 200 d1 d2 d3 d4 • Qualitative physical knowledge (symmetry) can influence estimates of continuous parameters (FH, FT). • Explains why 10 flips of 200 coins are better than 2000 flips of a single coin: more informative about FH, FT. Stability versus Flexibility • Can all domain knowledge be represented with conjugate priors? • Suppose you flip a coin 25 times and get all heads. Something funny is going on … • But with F ={1000 heads, 1000 tails}, P(heads) on next flip = 1025 / (1025+1000) = 50.6%. Looks like nothing unusual. • How do we balance stability and flexibility? – Stability: 6 heads, 4 tails – Flexibility: 25 heads, 0 tails q ~ 0.5 q ~1 A hierarchical Bayesian model fair/unfair? • Higher-order hypothesis: is this coin fair or unfair? • Example probabilities: – P(fair) = 0.99 – P(q |fair) is Beta(1000,1000) – P(q |unfair) is Beta(1,1) • 25 heads in a row propagates up, affecting q and then P(fair|D) FH,FT q d1 d2 d3 d4 1 heads|fair) P(fair|25 heads) P(25 P(fair) = 9 x 10-5 P( D | fair =) P( D | q ) p (q | fair )dq P(unfair|25 heads) P(25 0 heads|unfair) P(unfair) Summary: Bayesian parameter estimation • Learning the parameters of a generative model as Bayesian inference. • Conjugate priors – an elegant way to represent simple kinds of prior knowledge. • Hierarchical Bayesian models – integrate knowledge across instances of a system, or different systems within a domain. – can represent richer, more abstract knowledge Some questions • Learning isn’t just about parameter estimation – How do we learn the functional form of a variable’s distribution? – How do we learn model structure, or theories with the expressiveness of predicate logic? • Can we “grow” levels of abstraction? A hierarchical learning framework model class C p( D | M ) p( D | w, M ) p( w | M ) w Model selection: model M parameters w p ( M | D, C ) p ( D | M ) p ( M | C ) Model fitting: p( w | D, M ) p( D | w, M ) p( w | M ) data D Bayesian model selection q d1 d2 d3 d4 Fair coin, P(H) = 0.5 vs. d1 d2 d3 d4 P(H) = q • Which provides a better account of the data: the simple hypothesis of a fair coin, or the complex hypothesis that P(H) = q ? Comparing simple and complex hypotheses • P(H) = q is more complex than P(H) = 0.5 in two ways: – P(H) = 0.5 is a special case of P(H) = q – for any observed sequence D, we can choose q such that D is more probable than if P(H) = 0.5 Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Probability P( D | q ) q n (1 q ) N n q = 0.5 D = HHHHH Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Probability P( D | q ) q n (1 q ) N n q = 1.0 q = 0.5 D = HHHHH Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Probability P( D | q ) q n (1 q ) N n q = 0.6 q = 0.5 D = HHTHT Comparing simple and complex hypotheses • P(H) = q is more complex than P(H) = 0.5 in two ways: – P(H) = 0.5 is a special case of P(H) = q – for any observed sequence X, we can choose q such that X is more probable than if P(H) = 0.5 • How can we deal with this? – Some version of Occam’s razor? – Bayes: automatic version of Occam’s razor follows from the “law of conservation of belief”. Comparing simple and complex hypotheses P(h1|D) P(h0|D) P(D|h1) = P(D|h0) P(h1) x P(h0) P( D | h0 ) (1 / 2) n (1 1 / 2) N n 1 / 2 N 1 P( D | h1 ) P( D | q ) p(q | h1 )dq 0 The “evidence” or “marginal likelihood”: The probability that randomly selected parameters from the prior would generate the data. P ( D | h1 ) log P ( D | h0 ) 1 P( D | h1 ) P( D | q ) p(q | h1 )dq 0 P( D | h0 ) 1 / 2 N q Bayesian Occam’s Razor p(D = d | M ) M1 M2 All possible data sets d For any model M, p(D d | M ) 1 all d D Law of “conservation of belief”: A model that can predict many possible data sets must assign each of them low probability. Ockham’s Razor in curve fitting p(D d | M ) 1 M1 all d D p(D = d | M ) M1 M2 M2 M3 D Observed data M1: A model that is too simple is unlikely to generate the data. M3: A model that is too complex can generate many possible data sets, so it is unlikely to generate this particular data set at random. M3 p(D d | M ) 1 M1 all d D p(D = d | M ) M1 M2 M2 M3 D Observed data p ( D | M ) p ( y | x, M ) p( y | x, q , M ) p(q | M )dq [assume Gaussian parameter priors, Gaussian likelihoods (noise)] M3 M1 For best fitting version of each model: Prior Likelihood high low medium high M2 M3 very very very very low very high (assuming Gaussian noise, and Gaussian priors on parameters) (Ghahramani) (Ghahramani) Hierarchical Bayesian learning with flexibly structured models • Learning context-free grammars for natural language (Stolcke & Omohundro; Griffiths and Johnson; Perfors et al.). • Learning complex concepts. “fruit” “fruit” <= or( and( color > 0.2, color < 0.4, size > 1, size < 4 ), and( color > 0.5, color < 0.65, size > 2, size < 7), …) Navarro (2006): Nonparametric model Goodman et al. (2006): Probabilistic context-free grammar for rule-based concepts The “blessing of abstraction” • Often easier to learn at higher levels of abstraction – Easier to learn that you have a biased coin than to learn its bias. – Easier to learn causal structure than causal strength. – Easier to learn that you are hearing two languages (vs. one), or to learn that language has a hierarchical phrase structure, than to learn how any one language works. • Why? Hypothesis space gets smaller as you go up. – But the total hypothesis space gets bigger when we add levels of abstraction (e.g., model selection). – Can make better (more confident, more accurate) predictions by increasing the size of the hypothesis space, if we introduce good inductive biases. Summary • Three kinds of Bayesian inference – Comparing two simple hypotheses – Parameter estimation • The importance and subtlety of prior knowledge – Model selection • Bayesian Occam’s razor, the blessing of abstraction • Key concepts – Probabilistic generative models – Hierarchies of abstraction, with statistical inference at all levels – Flexibly structured representations