PUBLIC GOODS Snyder and Nicholson, Copyright ©2008 by Thomson South-Western. All rights reserved. Public Goods • Public goods are nonrival – the use of the good does not prevent others from using it e.g. knowledge • Pure Public goods are nonexclusive – once they are produced, they provide benefits to an entire group – it is impossible to restrict these benefits to the specific groups of individuals who pay for them Attributes of Public Goods • A good is nonrival if consumption of additional units of the good involves zero social marginal costs of production Attributes of Public Goods • A good is exclusive if it is relatively easy to exclude individuals from benefiting from the good once it is produced • A good is nonexclusive if it is impossible, or very costly, to exclude individuals from benefiting from the good Attributes of Public Goods • Some examples of these types of goods include: Exclusive Yes Rival No Yes Hot dogs, cars, houses Bridges, swimming pools No Fishing grounds, clean air National defense, mosquito control Public Good • A good is a pure public good if, once produced, no one can be excluded from benefiting from its availability and if the good is nonrival -- the marginal cost of an additional consumer is zero Public Goods and Resource Allocation • We will use a simple general equilibrium model with two individuals (A and B) • There are only two goods – good y is an ordinary private good • each person begins with an allocation (yA and yB) – good x is a public good that is produced using y x = f(ysA + ysB) Public Goods and Resource Allocation • Resulting utilities for these individuals are UA[x,(yA - ysA)] UB[x,(yB - ysB)] • The level of x enters identically into each person’s utility curve – it is nonexclusive and nonrival • each person’s consumption is unrelated to what he contributes to production • each consumes the total amount produced Public Goods and Resource Allocation • The necessary conditions for efficient resource allocation consist of choosing the levels of ysA and ysB that maximize one person’s (A’s) utility for any given level of the other’s (B’s) utility • The Lagrangian expression is L = UA(x, yA - ysA) + [UB(x, yB - ysB) - K] Public Goods and Resource Allocation • The first-order conditions for a maximum are L/ysA = U1Af’ - U2A + U1Bf’ = 0 L/ysB = U1Af’ - U2B + U1Bf’ = 0 • Comparing the two equations, we find U2B = U2A Public Goods and Resource Allocation • We can now derive the optimality condition for the production of x • From the initial first-order condition we know that U1A/U2A + U1B/U2B = 1/f’ MRSA + MRSB = 1/f’ • The MRS must reflect all consumers because all will get the same benefits Failure of a Competitive Market • Production of x and y in competitive markets will fail to achieve this allocation – with perfectly competitive prices px and py, each individual will equate his MRS to px/py – the producer will also set 1/f’ equal to px/py to maximize profits – the price ratio px/py will be too low • it would provide too little incentive to produce x Failure of a Competitive Market • For public goods, the value of producing one more unit is the sum of each consumer’s valuation of that output – individual demand curves should be added vertically rather than horizontally • Thus, the usual market demand curve will not reflect the full marginal valuation Inefficiency of a Nash Equilibrium • Suppose that individual A is thinking about contributing ysA of his initial yA endowment to the production of x • The utility maximization problem for A is then choose ysA to maximize UA[f(ysA + ysB),yA - ysA] Inefficiency of a Nash Equilibrium • The first-order condition for a maximum is U1Af’ - U2A = 0 U1A/U2A = MRSA = 1/f’ • Because a similar argument can be applied to B, the efficiency condition will fail to be achieved – each person considers only his own benefit The Roommates’ Dilemma • Suppose two roommates with identical preferences derive utility from the number of paintings hung on their walls (x) and the number of chocolate bars they eat (y) with a utility function of Ui(x,yi) = x1/3yi2/3 (for i=1,2) • Assume each roommate has $300 to spend and that px = $100 and py = $0.20 The Roommates’ Dilemma • We know from our earlier analysis of Cobb-Douglas utility functions that if each individual lived alone, he would spend 1/3 of his income on paintings (x = 1) and 2/3 on chocolate bars (y = 1,000) • When the roommates live together, each must consider what the other will do – if each assumed the other would buy paintings, x = 0 and utility = 0 The Roommates’ Dilemma • If person 1 believes that person 2 will not buy any paintings, he could choose to purchase one and receive utility of U1(x,y1) = 11/3(1,000)2/3 = 100 while person 2’s utility will be U2(x,y2) = 11/3(1,500)2/3 = 131 • Person 2 has gained from his free-riding position The Roommates’ Dilemma • We can show that this solution is inefficient by calculating each person’s MRS U i / x yi MRSi U i / y i 2 x • At the allocations described, MRS1 = 1,000/2 = 500 MRS2 = 1,500/2 = 750 The Roommates’ Dilemma • Since MRS1 + MRS2 = 1,250, the roommates would be willing to sacrifice 1,250 chocolate bars to have one additional painting – an additional painting would only cost them 500 chocolate bars – too few paintings are bought The Roommates’ Dilemma • To calculate the efficient level of x, we must set the sum of each person’s MRS equal to the price ratio y1 y 2 y1 y 2 px 100 MRS1 MRS2 2x 2x 2x py 0.20 • This means that y1 + y2 = 1,000x The Roommates’ Dilemma • Substituting into the sum of budget constraints, we get 0.20(y1 + y2) + 100x = 600 x=2 y1 + y2 = 2,000 • The allocation of the cost of the paintings depends on how each roommate plays the strategic financing game The Roommates’ Dilemma • If each person buy 1 painting Person 1’s utility is U1(x,y1) = 21/3(1,000)2/3 126 Person 2’s utility is U2(x,y2) = 21/3(1,000)2/3 126 The Roommates’ Dilemma Person 2 Buy Buy Not Buy 126,126 100,131 Person 1 Not Buy 131,100 0,0 Lindahl Pricing of Public Goods • Swedish economist E. Lindahl suggested that individuals might be willing to be taxed for public goods if they knew that others were being taxed – Lindahl assumed that each individual would be presented by the government with the proportion of a public good’s cost he was expected to pay and then reply with the level of public good he would prefer Lindahl Pricing of Public Goods • Suppose that individual A would be quoted a specific percentage (A) and asked the level of a public good (x) he would want given the knowledge that this fraction of total cost would have to be paid • The person would choose the level of x which maximizes utility = UA[x,yA*- Af -1(x)] Lindahl Pricing of Public Goods • The first-order condition is given by U1A - AU2B(1/f’)=0 MRSA = A/f’ • Faced by the same choice, individual B would opt for the level of x which satisfies MRSB = B/f’ Lindahl Pricing of Public Goods • An equilibrium would occur when A+B = 1 – the level of public goods expenditure favored by the two individuals precisely generates enough tax contributions to pay for it MRSA + MRSB = (A + B)/f’ = 1/f’ Shortcomings of the Lindahl Solution • The incentive to be a free rider is very strong – this makes it difficult to envision how the information necessary to compute equilibrium Lindahl shares might be computed • individuals have a clear incentive to understate their true preferences Important Points to Note: • Externalities may cause a misallocation of resources because of a divergence between private and social marginal cost – traditional solutions to this divergence includes mergers among the affected parties and adoption of suitable Pigouvian taxes or subsidies Voting • Voting is used as a social decision process in many institutions – direct voting is used in many cases from statewide referenda to smaller groups and clubs – in other cases, societies have found it more convenient to use a representative form of government Majority Rule • Throughout our discussion of voting, we will assume that decisions will be made by majority rule The Paradox of Voting • In the 1780s, social theorist M. de Condorcet noted that majority rule voting systems may not arrive at an equilibrium – instead, they may cycle among alternative options The Paradox of Voting • Suppose there are three voters (Smith, Jones, and Fudd) choosing among three policy options – we can assume that these policy options represent three levels of spending on a particular public good [(A) low, (B) medium, and (C) high] – Condorcet’s paradox would arise even without this ordering The Paradox of Voting • Preferences among the three policy options for the three voters are: Smith Jones Fudd A B C B C A C A B The Paradox of Voting • Consider a vote between A and B – A would win • In a vote between A and C – C would win • In a vote between B and C – B would win • No equilibrium will ever be reached Single-Peaked Preferences • Equilibrium voting outcomes always occur in cases where the issue being voted upon is one-dimensional and where voter preferences are “singlepeaked” Single-Peaked Preferences We can show each voters preferences in terms of utility levels Utility A Fudd Jones B C For Smith and Jones, preferences are singlepeaked Fudd’s preferences have two local maxima Smith Quantity of public good Single-Peaked Preferences If Fudd had alternative preferences with a single peak, there would be no paradox Utility A Fudd Jones Option B will be chosen because it will defeat both A and C by votes 2 to 1 B C Smith Quantity of public good The Median Voter Theorem • With the altered preferences of Fudd, B will be chosen because it is the preferred choice of the median voter (Jones) – Jones’s preferences are between the preferences of Smith and the revised preferences of Fudd The Median Voter Theorem • If choices are unidimensional and preferences are single-peaked, majority rule will result in the selection of the project that is most favored by the median voter – that voter’s preferences will determine what public choices are made A Simple Political Model • Suppose a community is characterized by a large number of voters (n) each with income of yi • The utility of each voter depends on his consumption of a private good (ci) and of a public good (g) according to utility of person i = Ui = ci + f(g) where fg > 0 and fgg < 0 A Simple Political Model • Each voter must pay taxes to finance g • Taxes are proportional to income and are imposed at a rate of t • Each person’s budget constraint is ci = (1-t)yi • The government also faces a budget constraint n g ty i tny A i 1 A Simple Political Model • Given these constraints, the utility function of individual i is Ui(g) = [yA - (g/n)]yi /yA + f(g) • Utility maximization occurs when dUi /dg = -yi /(nyA) + fg(g) = 0 g = fg-1[yi /(nyA)] • Desired spending on g is inversely related to income A Simple Political Model • If G is determined through majority rule, its level will be that level favored by the median voter – since voters’ preferences are determined solely by income, g will be set at the level preferred by the voter with the median level of income (ym) g* = fg-1[ym/(nyA)] = fg-1[(1/n)(ym/yA)] A Simple Political Model • Under a utilitarian social welfare criterion, g would be chosen so as to maximize the sum of utilities: A g y i SW U i y A f g ny A g nf g n y 1 n • The optimal choice for g then is g* = fg-1(1/n) = fg-1[(1/n)(yA/yA)] – the level of g favored by the voter with average income Voting for Redistributive Taxation • Suppose voters are considering a lumpsum transfer to be paid to every person and financed through proportional taxation • If we denote the per-person transfer b, each individual’s utility is now given by Ui = ci + b Voting for Redistributive Taxation • The government’s budget constraint is nb = tnyA b = tyA • For a voter with yi > yA, utility is maximized by choosing b = 0 • Any voter with yi < yA will choose t = 1 and b = yA – would fully equalize incomes Voting for Redistributive Taxation • Note that a 100 percent tax rate would lower average income • Assume that each individual’s income has two components, one responsive to tax rates [yi (t)] and one not responsive (ni) – also assume that the average of ni is zero, but its distribution is skewed right so nm < 0 Voting for Redistributive Taxation • Now, utility is given by Ui = (1-t)[yi (t) + ni] + b • The individual’s first-order condition for a maximum in his choice of t and g is now dUi /dt = -ni + t(dyA/dt) = 0 ti = ni /(dyA/dt) • Under majority rule, the equilibrium condition will be t* = nm /(dyA/dt) The Groves Mechanism • Suppose there are n individuals in a group – each has a private and unobservable valuation (ui) for a proposed taxationexpenditure project The Groves Mechanism • The government states that, if undertaken, the project will provide each person with a transfer given by t i v i i • If the project is not undertaken, no transfers are made The Groves Mechanism • The problem for voter i is to choose his or her reported net valuation so as to maximize utility utility u i t i u i v i i The Groves Mechanism • Each person will wish the project to be undertaken if it raises utility • This means u i v i 0 i • A utility-maximizing strategy is to set vi = ui The Clarke Mechanism • This mechanism also envisions asking individuals about their net valuation of a public project – focuses on “pivotal voters” • those whose valuations can change the overall evaluation from positive to negative of vice versa The Clarke Mechanism • For these pivotal voters, the Clarke mechanism incorporates a Pigouvian-like tax (or transfer) to encourage truth telling – for all other voters, there are no special transfers Important Points to Note: • Public goods provide benefits to individuals on a nonexclusive basis no one can be prevented from consuming such goods – such goods are usually nonrival in that the marginal cost of serving another user is zero Important Points to Note: • Private markets will tend to underallocate resources to public goods because no single buyer can appropriate all of the benefits that such goods provide Important Points to Note: • A Lindahl optimal tax-sharing scheme can result in an efficient allocation of resources to the production of public goods – computing these tax shares requires substantial information that individuals have incentives to hide Important Points to Note: • Majority rule voting may not lead to an efficient allocation of resources to public goods – the median voter theorem provides a useful way of modeling the outcomes from majority rule in certain situations Important Points to Note: • Several truth-revealing voting mechanisms have been developed – whether these are robust to the special assumptions made or capable of practical application remain unresolved questions