Money Money is not merely a denominator of value, but a mediating function through which all individual commodities are exchanged, and through which the value-relation among all commodities is constantly adjusted and readjusted. For this precise reason, money exists as an organizer of the system of commodities, namely, a transcendental apperception X of human exchange (22). Value—classical, neoclassical, ex ante facto, ex post facto, --- difference between communities, value corresponds to the difference between the relational systems (230) --- M--C—M ---circulation process ---credit ---crisis—money > commodity --worker as consumer has to buy back his products Surplus value …one has to be cautious about surplus value. This is usually ascribed to Marx, but it derived from the Left Ricardians. That is to say that Marx’s critique of classical economy implied the critique of the surplus value theory, which considers the production process as the only place where the exploitation of surplus value takes place (285). Different from profit---surplus value (essence), profit (historical starting point) (242-43)---S/v (surplus value) vs. S/c+v (profit) Against a unitary system(227)---Against the equilibrium between supply and demand(227)--Against equilibrium price (228) Circulation process (224)---Marx sought to reconsider surplus value from the vantage point of circulation (235). antinomy—in and not in (224)---the realization of surplus value is completed in the process of circulation, but the process of circulation is not enough for the realization. To solve this aporia, the being of manifold systems must be introduced again (237). different value systems (227)---only where there are heterogeneous systems can money transform into capital that gains surplus value from the exchange between systems.(227)---the surplus value arises from the differences between manifold systems. (228) In the manner of Kant, Marx points out an antinomy. He says, on the one hand, that surplus value (for industrial capital) cannot be attained in the process of production in itself, and, on the other hand, that it cannot be attained in the process of circulation in itself…this antinomy can be undone, that is, only by proposing that the surplus value (for industrial capital) comes from the difference of value systems in the circulation process (like in the merchant capital), and yet that the difference is created by technological innovation in the production process (11). The process M—C—M is split---M-C and C-M occur in different times and places. (231) Worker as consumer---surplus value is engendered only in totality by worker selling their labor power and with the money buying back the commodities they produced (239). Relative surplus value—Only where there is a difference in price between value systems: A (when they sell their labor power) and B (when they buy the commodities), is surplus value realized. This is so-called relative surplus value (239). Total surplus value-----When Marx assumed that total surplus value was being distributed to individual capitalists, he conceptualized it within a synchronic, equilibrium system. This can be grasped only on the transcendental level (not on the empirical level). Rather now the spatial coexistence of branches should be transposed back into temporal succession once more (247). Distributed between workers of different industrial branches (246-47) Surplus value cannot be realized only as total social capital. Here is a vital important implication: Inasmuch as surplus value can only be realized globally, the movement to terminate it must be transnational (292). State The absolutist monarchical states conspired with the merchant class, monopolized the means of violence by toppling feudal lords (aristocracy), and finally abolished feudal domination (extra-economic domination) entirely. This was the very story of the wedding between state and capital (14). The amalgamation of absolutist state and mercantilism. (270) what is called liberalism is also a form of the absolutist-mercantilist agenda, an economic policy that hegemonic states always adopt (269). The state is essentially mercantilist (270). Relationship with other states---In order to grasp the state as an autonomous entity, we have to see it as existing in relationship with other states (275). …absolutist states appeared amid the competition with each other in world capitalism (275). No matter how social democratic the state appears within itself, it is hegemonic to its exteriority—namely, even under the slogan of “humanitarian intervention” (275). Nation The nation is based on principles of exchange different from those of state and capital (277). 1) Protected by the absolutist state, merchant capital (bourgeoisie) grew up and nurtured the identity of the nation for the sake of creating a unified market. Yet this was not all in terms of the formation of the nation….(2) While individual agrarian communities that had been autarkic and autonomous were decomposed by the osmosis of money, their communalities—mutual aid and reciprocity—themselves were recovered imaginarily within the nation (278). It was amid the bourgeois revolution that these three were officially married (278). …capital(liberty), state(equality), and nation(fraternity) copulated and amalgamated themselves into a force that was inseparable ever after (278-79). Association This is a form of mutual aid, yet neither exclusive nor coercive like community. Associationism can be considered as an ethico-economic form of human relation that can appear only after a society that once passes through the capitalist market economy. It was thought that Proudhon was the first to have totalized it; according to my reading, however, Kant’s ethics already contained it (13). I think the possibility lies in associationism: to develop a circulation system using local currency, and thereby to nurture producers/consumers’ cooperatives and connect them to those in the First World. This would be noncapitalist trade and could form a network without the mediation of states (295), The association of associations is far from the organization of the tree structure, while at the same time it would remain isolated, dispersed, and conflicting, if it did not have a center. So it needs a center, but the center should exist as a function just like transcendental apperception X and not something substantial (306). Ethics The movement against capitalism is an ethical and moral one (287). Consumers’ civil acts, including the problematization of environmental and minority issues, are moral, but the reason they have achieved a certain success is that a consumers’ boycott is the most dreadful thing capital can imagine. In other words, the success of the moralist intervention is guaranteed not only by the power of morality in itself, but more crucially, because it is the embodiment of the asymmetric relation between commodity and money. There, in order to begin an oppositional movement against capital, it is imperative to discover a new context where labor movements and consumers’ movements meet, and this not as a political coalition between existing movements but as a totally new movement itself (294). Transposition The movements of consumers’ boycotts have long existed empirically, but the attain a radical implication comparable to the Copernican turn only when they are posited in the context of the theory of value form and seen as a transposition from relative value form to equivalent value form(from seller of labor-power commodity to buyer of a commodities); and further in the context of the capital’s metamorphosis: M-C-M’ (296). …it is in the transcritical position where workers appear as consumers, namely, at the front of circulation (300). Marxists failed to grasp the transcritical moment where workers and consumers intersect (21). Worker as subject Those who sell their labor-power commodity have no other choice but to be passive; yet again there is an exception in the structure: this is a topos where workers appear to be the subject—the place where the products of capitalist production are sold. This is the place of consumption. This is the only position where workers can stand as buyers, with their own money (288). For capital, consumption is the place where surplus value is finally realized, thus the only place where it is subordinated to the will of the other, that is, the workers qua consumers (288). With respect to our position, however, the consumer position is something that should be rediscovered and redefined. All in all, surplus value that sustains industrial capital can exist, in principle, only thanks to this mechanism that worker in totality buy back what they produce. Surplus value is finally realized on the consumption point, the place where capital is confronted by alterity and compelled into a salto mortale as a seller of commodiites (289). …value is fully realized only in the process of circulation. Therefore, it is only here that the moment for workers to be subject exists (291)….In our context, we rather have to find the moment for class struggle in the theory of value form in capital(291). ….The split between production and consumption constitutes capital, while it is also this moment that can terminate capital (291). Those who are in the position of capital are subjective (active), while those who are in the position of having to sell their labor power are inevitably passive. Therefore, it is only a matter of inevitability that workers can only engage in the economic struggle where they negotiate with capitalists over their commodity value. In Capital, the moment for workers to be subjective is found when the shift of workers’ position in the categories—commodity-money—takes place: from the labor-power commodity to being the money en masse that buys commodities (293). Futur anterieur What we perceive as constituted in production (value) is in truth the product of exchange: The temporality is that of the future anterieur: value “is” not immediately, it only “will have been,” it is retroactively actualized, performatively enacted. In production, value is generated “in itself,” while only through the completed circulation process does it become “for itself.” (zizek, 2006b 52) Transcendental apperception (illusion) Borrowing from Kant’s paradigmatic notion of transcendental apperception, Karatani claims that in itself the value of a commodity does not exist, since it is determined in a system of relations with other commodities – which is why the price of the same product differs from country to country, or even within the same country (Karatani, 228) Surplus value is thus conceived as the invisible transcendental link between two different surface phenomenon: M-C (production) and C-M’ (circulation). What one should add here is that, precisely because value is purely formal determination, in itself nonexistent, it always-already operates reflexively, i.e., within each of the two surface phenomena (production and circulation) from whose tension it results Instead of elections (democratic parliamentarism), he suggests instituting a lottery to decide who is temporarily in charge of associations. The solution would take us beyond the capitalist state and not yet answer the need for centralized power to coordinate operations. The function of this centre would be “just like transcendental apperception X and not something substantial[…] the associations would be united by a central committee consisting of a representative of each dimension (Karatani, 306) Karatani discusses at great length the various parallax shifts in Marx’s argument; as Marx moved from Germany to France to England, he also moves from the critique of German idealism (Hegel and young Hegelians), to the critique of French “utopian” socialism and political theory, to the critique of British empiricism and political economy. Karatani argues that Marx’s critique of political economy operates precisely in the antinomy, or parallax, between the labor theory of value, on the one hand, and Bailey’s (and the neoclassical economists’) positivistic dismissal of value theory altogether on the other. According to Karatani, Marx rejects Ricardian essentialism (the labor theory of value in its classical form), but also insists, against Bailey’s (and later, neoclassical) nominalism, that a “transcendental reflection on value” (6) is necessary in order to make sense of capitalism as a system….In a parallel way to how the empty, transcendental form of the “I” keeps subjectivity together through time, so the transcendental category that Marx calls the “value-form” keeps the capitalist economy together….Marx is making a Kantian “transcendental” argument, when he posits the double value-form of the commodity (use-value and exchange-value) against both Ricardo’s essentialist (substantive) labor theory of value, and against the nominalist, positivist and ultimately neoclassical rejection of the very category of “value”. Karatani here argues that value and surplus value, as posited in volume 1 of Capital, are the transcendental conditions of possibility of capitalism. Value and surplus value are the preconditions that make it possible, empirically, for capitalist profit. But value and surplus value are themselves never encountered empirically. Empirically, we only encounters prices and profits. …a transcendental condition of experience. We only encounter “surplus value” in and for itself in the way that we encounter time, space, and causality in and for themselves. They are conditions of experience, rather than things that we encounter within experience. This is why, Karatani says, “Marx’s labor theory of value and Ricardo’s are fundamentally different”; for Marx, “it is not that input labor time determines the value, but conversely that the value form (system) determine the social[ly] necessary labor time” (244) Transcendental and value form: “all the enigmas of capital’s drive are inscribed in the theory of value form….Value form is a kind of form that people are not aware of when they are placed within the monetary economy; this is the form that is discovered transcendentally” (9) Transcendental and money: Money, Karatani says, “is like a Kantian transcendental apperception X, as it were…money as substance is an illusion, but more correctly, it is a transcendental illusion, in the sense that it is hardly possible to discard it.” (6). Marx contrasts money as a transcendental form with “the substantial aspect of money such as gold or silver. To take it substantially it, to Marx, fetishism (196). Since its use-value is purely formal or transcendental, money doesn’t have to take the form of precious metals; it can be made of paper, or even be entirely virtual….”Anything – anything – that is exclusively placed in the general equivalent form becomes money; that is, it achieves the right to attain anything in exchange” (7)…. As a universal equivalent or transcendental form, money does not merely put external terms (objects sold as commodities) into relation; it molds and alters those terms by the very fact of equating them (money as universal equivalent is what transforms things into commodities in the first place). Transcritique For Karatani, such “trans-critique” is made possible by, and exercised through, the reflexive movement in-between cultures, communities, and cognitive perspectives. …Kant and Marx’s outsider-position vis-à-vis their subject matter and context. Karatani illustrates this by Kant’s refusal to become a state philosopher by remaining in Konigsberg, and through Marx’s outsider-postion vis-à-vis the German, the French, and the British cultures respectively. More importantly, he suggests that Kant oscillates between, rather than “sublates”, rationalism and empiricism, while Marx is taken to stand in between Ricardo (emphasizing the producer sphere of capitalism) and the unjustly forgotten Bailey (emphasizing the circulation sphere as value-gererating)….This was to see things neither from his own viewpoint, nor from the viewpoint of others, but to face reality that is exposed through difference (parallax) (3)…..Such a methodological outsider-or in-between position allows both thinkers to radically question the existing presuppositions shared by their contemporaries. From parallax to transcendental In Karatani’s account, Marx delineates the “transcendental conditions” of a capitalist economy. But these conditions involve antinomies, which can only be traversed (since they are never definitely resolved) by a process of continual “parallax,” or shifting of focus between one position and another. A Kantian “transcendental deduction” occurs in the form of what Karatani calls “transcritique”, a shuttling back and forth between the disparities generated by the shifts in perspective. Karatani suggests, therefore, that the often-alleged “discrepancy” between Volumes 1 and 3 of Capital is actually quite similar to what happens in Kant, “whose first critique tackles the issue of subject in general, but whose third critique engages in the issue of plural subjects” (243)….In Volume 3, “Marx deals with plural capitals, while at the same time transcendentally asking how it is empirically possible that they realize profit or the rate of profit” (243) Just as the Third Critique involves an antinomy between 1) the universal nature of aesthetic judgment (the fact that it demands to be accepted universally) and 2) the ungrounded singularity of an individual aesthetic judgment( the fact that it cannot appeal to any preexisting concepts for justification), so Marx’s Volume 3 involves an antinomy between 1) the grounding of price in value, and of profit in surplus value (Thesis: Ricardo); and 2) the independence of price from value and of profit from surplus value (Antithesis: Bailey) Surplus—parallax—transcendental Surplus value itself, as a transcendental form, is predicated on a discontinuity, or incommensurability, between heterogeneous registers of value. In Marx’s most direct formulation of the theory, there is a discontinuity in the realm of production between the value of the worker’s labor-power as a commodity, and the value of the commodities produced by that labor power. But when surplus value is realized in the realm of circulation, the incommensurability is one between the two circuits C-M-C and M-C-M’ Regulative idea A regulative idea, as defined by Kant, s “an ideal which constantly offers the ground to criticize reality” (Karatani, 217). Karatani considers modes of exchange D, association, a regulative idea….Unlike constitutive concepts, regulative ideas “are concepts of what would be the final state of a practice according to some absolute standard” (6). They do not need to be considered as if they already occur or even will exist….nourishing association as a regulative idea is essential because one must have a theoretical faith to imagine the possibility for transcending the capitalist nation state. Salto Mortale The emphasis falls on what Marx called salto mortale performed by the commodity the moment it is sold, thus realizing its value which, as Marx stressed through his reading of Bailey, enjoys a purely relational status; thus it does not exist in itself but only if inserted into a system of equivalence with other commodities From Parallax to ethical When in his little known text ‘Dreams of a visionary Explained by Dreams of Metaphysics” Kant wrote of the “pronounced parallax” resulting from adding to my perspective “the notion of another’s reason outside of myself,” he was attempting to prevent “optical delusion”, thus rectifying the meaning of human knowledge (Kant quoted in Karatani, 47)….Kant’s stance, Karatani argues, ought to be measured against his groundbreaking notion of parallax….Karatani’s next step concerns the effort to solve what he sees as the Kantian problem broached by Marx. Following Kant, he argues that mortality is the only solution to the ontological deadlock of thought. From a Marxian angle, Kant’s moral law provides a potential way out of the epistemological impasse embodied by capital. Karatani goes so far as to claim that for Marx, “communism was a Kantian categorical imperative, that is, practical and moral par excellence’ Karatani resorts to the image of the parallax to locate not only the origins of Kant’s critical thought but especially the surplus that drives capital forward and demands the intervention of a moral stance to realize an alternative economic model Ethical and exchange The other can come from an outside community that does not share a common set of rules (125). Yet this morality will never be achieved so long as we live in a society dominated by commodity exchange (viii) Ethical—others as ends---communism [For Kant] becoming moral was less a question of good and evil than of being causa sui and hence free, and this compels us to treat other people as free agents. The ultimate message of Kantian moral law lies in the imperative: “Act so that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in any other person, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means….” (Karatani, vii, viii) In the context of a capitalist economy where people treat each merely as a means to an end, the Kantian “kingdom of freedom” or “Kingdom of ends” clearly comes to entail another new meaning, that is, communism (Karatani, vii, viii) In this gap between appearance and the thing-in-itself resides an essential possibility to challenge, revise, and transcend the current order. Moreover, Kant addresses the need to go beyond the mere experience of appearances in the ethical domain, where his categorical imperative gives immediate proof of the law of reason. The Kantian path to ethical transcendence is crucial, first, since it suggests the content of the categorical imperative, i.e., never to treat another merely as a means, but always also as an end. Moreover, Karatani maintains that this shows that Kant situates this ethical demand squarely in the emerging capitalistic order, as the imperative to treat another never merely as a means is clearly taking into account the capitalistic mode of instrumental reason, in which others are economically reduced to mere means. State---different Gramsci and Foucault The problem with Gramsci and Foucault, Karatani argues, is that they see the state as either civil society or immanent power because they only see it from within, i.e., they miss the crucial detail that the state exists in competition with other states, and the competition is about capital: “No matter how social democratic the state appears within itself, it is hegemonic to its exteriority – namely, even under the slogan of “humanitarian intervention’ (Karatani, 275) Bailey and Hume Karatani notes that Bailey’s skepticism [regarding the labor theory of value] is similar to Hume’s criticism that there is nothing like a Cartesian ego cogito (5) Credit One can here think of the role of credit. Money and finance/credit allow the separation of acts of exchange (purchase and sale) in time and space. “C-M(selling) and M-C (buying) are separate, and precisely for this reason, the sphere of exchange is infinitely expandable in both space and time. State and others as means Karatani analyzes the modern social formation as the result of three modes of exchange – reciprocity of gift and return, plunder and redistribution, and commodity exchange—which combine to form the capitalist nation state. Through the examination of Kant’s moral imperative, Karatani contends that so long as we live within the confines of the capitalist nation state, we will treat others merely as means to an end. Nation—state—capital With the protection of the state, the bourgeoisie cultivated the national identity, which allowed for the creation of a unified market (278). Reciprocity and gift return (mode of exchange A) that used to be practiced within the agrarian communities was fictitiously recovered in the form of the nation.