Comments on Frank’s paper “Corporate Responsibility and Judgment Aggregation” Christian List, LSE Introduction • Frank discusses both Pettit and Copp on corporate responsibility. • Given time constraints (and my personal involvement with Pettit’s work), I will here focus on Frank’s discussion of Pettit’s arguments. Pettit’s argument (1) • In a 2007 article in Ethics, Philip Pettit argues that corporate agents can be held responsible over and above their individual members. • In particular, Pettit suggests, there can be gaps of responsibility between the individual and the corporate level, where (i) the group as a whole bears corporate responsibility for some action, e.g., some harm done, (ii) but none of the members are individually responsible for it. Pettit’s argument (2) • One of Pettit’s key pieces of evidence for the claim that there can be such responsibility gaps involves a particular discursive dilemma: => namely one in which a group, using a premisebased procedure for making its decisions, comes to reach a conclusion that no group member individually supports. Pettit’s argument (3) • Suppose, for example, that three premises, p, q and r, are jointly necessary and sufficient for some conclusion c. • If individual judgments are as shown, then the group, through the pbp, accepts c even though no individual does. p q r c Ind. 1 Ind. 2 Ind. 3 Group (premisebased) Pettit’s argument (3) • If the acceptance of c by the group now leads to some harmful Ind. 1 outcome, the question Ind. 2 is whether any of the individuals can be Ind. 3 held responsible. • After all, they all individually rejected c. Group (premisebased) p q r c Pettit’s argument (4) • The responsibility gap arises once we assume, as Pettit seems to do, that [E] An individual member of an organization cannot be blamed for a decision made by that organization if s/he disagrees with it. (This is Frank’s formulation.) • (N.B.: [E] is sufficient, not necessary, for the occurrence of the responsibility gap.) Frank’s response (1) • Now Frank argues that condition [E] (“Pettit’s excusing condition”) is too broad. • Instead, he proposes a more restrictive excusing condition: [E*] An individual’s disagreement with the decision of the organization of which s/he is a member affects the extent to which s/he can be blamed for that decision only if s/he disagrees with it for the right reasons. Frank’s response (2) • Frank then argues that: – IF we only have condition [E*] but not [E] as a sufficient condition for excusing individuals from responsibility, – THEN some of Pettit’s examples for the responsibility gap go away, and further, the group’s responsibility in the questionable cases can be distributed back to the members, using a fairly general recipe. Some thoughts • • For the present purposes, let me grant most of the claims in Frank’s detailed analysis, especially his IF-THEN claim summarized on my previous slide. Even so, I do not think that it undermines (a) the thesis that group agents can be held responsible independently of their members, and (b) the thesis that a responsibility gap between the individual level and the collective level is a possibility. (a) Why the claim that group agents can be held responsible in their own right is unaffected • The capacity of some groups to be held responsible in their own right does not depend on the discursive dilemma. • Rather, it stems from the fact that, under suitable conditions, groups can satisfy the conditions for rational agency, even in a rather complex sense. • Once we have a sufficiently complex system satisfying certain conditions of agency, it is an agent and, if sophisticated enough, it can prima facie be a candidate for responsibility. (a) Why the claim that group agents can be held responsible in their own right is unaffected • Now the presence of such corporate responsibility leaves entirely open the question of whether or not corporate responsibility can be redistributed back to the group members (and if it can, under what conditions). • Either answer to the latter question is consistent with the presence of corporate responsibility. • So even if Frank could conclusively undermine the possibility of a responsibility gap, this would not undermine the possibility of corporate responsibility as such. • (– Though admittedly corporate responsibility becomes more interesting and surprising if there can be genuine responsibility gaps. So let’s briefly turn to responsibility gaps.) (b) Why responsibility gaps remain a possibility • Frank argues that some of Pettit’s examples for responsibility gaps are a bit too quick. • Again, for the sake of argument, let me grant Frank’s claim that simple discursive dilemma cases (the so-called “Disagreement” cases) do not provide sufficiently compelling instances of responsibility gaps. (b) Why responsibility gaps remain a possibility (ctd.) • • However, I think that the general case for the possibility of a responsibility gap goes well beyond simple discursive dilemma examples. The general claim is that (i) what a group agent thinks and does supervenes on what the members think and do, (ii) however, the supervenience relation can be very complex and indirect and need not be a simple propositionwise function, by which the group’s intentional attitude towards any given proposition is a straightforward function of the members’ attitudes towards that proposition. (b) Why responsibility gaps remain a possibility (ctd.) • In particular, it can not only happen that the group democratically accepts p while I disagree in full awareness (a simple discursive-dilemma-style Disagreement case as discussed by Frank). • But it can also happen that a group agent ventures into terrains of attitudes and actions (as complex epiphenomena of large numbers of individual inputs) that no member individually follows, understands and endorses. (Think of really large and complex organizations.) • This is where the possibility of a responsibility gaps arises. It is a product of dramatic complexity of social organization. (Simple discursive dilemma examples don’t quite capture this complexity – and in these simple cases Frank’s strategy for redistributing responsibility may indeed often work.) (b) Why responsibility gaps remain a possibility (ctd.) • Bear in mind that principle [E] (which Frank rejects) and principle [E*] (which he accepts) give sufficient, but not necessary, conditions for excuses from responsibility on the grounds of disagreement. • There could still be many other sufficient conditions for excuses on other grounds, including ignorance due to complexity, unawareness, lack of influence or control etc., and those may well kick in in complex group agents. My conclusion • For this reason, I would conclude that: – Wherever and whenever there are sufficiently complex group agents, there can be corporate responsibility, and – It is ultimately a contingent question whether in real-world cases of corporate responsibility redistribution to the level of individuals is possible, or whether there are real-world cases of genuine responsibility gaps. Conceptually, such gaps are possible.