The Intellectual Revolution That You’ve Never Heard of: The Discovery of Non-Euclidean Geometry in the Age of Enlightenment Revolutions You Have Heard Of Non-Euclidean Geometry Revolutions You Have Heard Of Copernicus and Galileo: 16th–17th C. Non-Euclidean Geometry Revolutions You Have Heard Of Copernicus and Galileo: 16th–17th C. Darwin: Mid 19th C. Non-Euclidean Geometry Revolutions You Have Heard Of Copernicus and Galileo: 16th–17th C. Darwin: Mid 19th C. Einstein: Early 20th C. Non-Euclidean Geometry One More! Copernicus and Galileo: 16th–17th C. Non-Euclidean Geometry: Early 19th C. Darwin: Mid 19th C. Einstein: Early 20th C. Non-Euclidean Geometry So What? Non-Euclidean Geometry So What? The physical and biological sciences have repeatedly had revolutions, but mathematics usually builds upon what was already proved—this revolution is one of the few cases in mathematics where previously held views were overturned Non-Euclidean Geometry So What? The physical and biological sciences have repeatedly had revolutions, but mathematics usually builds upon what was already proved—this revolution is one of the few cases in mathematics where previously held views were overturned You might say this revolution is just about mathematics, whereas the others are science, and as such are about the real world Non-Euclidean Geometry So What? The physical and biological sciences have repeatedly had revolutions, but mathematics usually builds upon what was already proved—this revolution is one of the few cases in mathematics where previously held views were overturned You might say this revolution is just about mathematics, whereas the others are science, and as such are about the real world To the thinkers of early part of the Age of Enlightenment, and before, mathematics is not separate from the sciences and philosophy Non-Euclidean Geometry Plato, “Republic” book VII Non-Euclidean Geometry Plato, “Republic” book VII “Then, my noble friend, geometry will draw the soul towards truth, and create the spirit of philosophy, and raise up that which is now unhappily allowed to fall down.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Plato, “Republic” book VII “Then, my noble friend, geometry will draw the soul towards truth, and create the spirit of philosophy, and raise up that which is now unhappily allowed to fall down.” “Nothing will be more likely to have such an effect.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Plato, “Republic” book VII “Then, my noble friend, geometry will draw the soul towards truth, and create the spirit of philosophy, and raise up that which is now unhappily allowed to fall down.” “Nothing will be more likely to have such an effect.” “Then nothing should be more sternly laid down than that the inhabitants of your fair city should by all means learn geometry.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo You have learned about his role in supporting the heliocentric view Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo You have learned about his role in supporting the heliocentric view “Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems” Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo You have learned about his role in supporting the heliocentric view “Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems” He did something even more important Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo You have learned about his role in supporting the heliocentric view “Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems” He did something even more important Though it is not as well known, because there was no confrontation with the church Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo You have learned about his role in supporting the heliocentric view “Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems” He did something even more important Though it is not as well known, because there was no confrontation with the church “Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Relating to Two New Sciences” Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo You have learned about his role in supporting the heliocentric view “Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems” He did something even more important Though it is not as well known, because there was no confrontation with the church “Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Relating to Two New Sciences” Galileo virtually invented modern science Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo, “Opere Il Saggiatore” Non-Euclidean Geometry Galileo, “Opere Il Saggiatore” “[The universe] cannot be read until we have learnt the language and become familiar with the characters in which it is written. It is written in mathematical language, and the letters are triangles, circles and other geometrical figures, without which means it is humanly impossible to comprehend a single word.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Descartes Non-Euclidean Geometry Descartes In an appendix to “Discourse on Method,” Descartes develops what we now call analytic geometry, using x and y coordinates to describe the plane, and relates geometry to algebra Non-Euclidean Geometry From “The Autobiography of Charles Darwin” Non-Euclidean Geometry From “The Autobiography of Charles Darwin” During the three years which I spent at Cambridge my time was wasted, as far as the academical studies were concerned, as completely as at Edinburgh and at school. I attempted mathematics, and even went during the summer of 1828 with a private tutor (a very dull man) to Barmouth, but I got on very slowly. The work was repugnant to me, chiefly from my not being able to see any meaning in the early steps in algebra. This impatience was very foolish, and in after years I have deeply regretted that I did not proceed far enough at least to understand something of the great leading principles of mathematics, for men thus endowed seem to have an extra sense. Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Shelley, “Frankenstein” Chapter 3 Non-Euclidean Geometry Shelley, “Frankenstein” Chapter 3 “ ‘I am happy,’ said M. Waldman, ‘to have gained a disciple; and if your application equals your ability, I have no doubt of your success. Chemistry is that branch of natural philosophy in which the greatest improvements have been and may be made: it is on that account that I have made it my peculiar study; but at the same time I have not neglected the other branches of science. A man would make but a very sorry chemist if he attended to that department of human knowledge alone. If your wish is to become really a man of science, and not merely a petty experimentalist, I should advise you to apply to every branch of natural philosophy, including mathematics.’ ” Non-Euclidean Geometry Mathematics in the Age of Enlightenment Non-Euclidean Geometry Mathematics in the Age of Enlightenment Great progress was made in mathematics in this period Non-Euclidean Geometry Mathematics in the Age of Enlightenment Great progress was made in mathematics in this period The greatest advance in mathematics in this period—and one of the greatest achievements of the human mind ever—was the invention of the calculus in the late 17th C. by Newton and Leibniz Non-Euclidean Geometry Mathematics in the Age of Enlightenment Great progress was made in mathematics in this period The greatest advance in mathematics in this period—and one of the greatest achievements of the human mind ever—was the invention of the calculus in the late 17th C. by Newton and Leibniz The invention of the calculus was the culmination of an evolutionary process, not a revolution Non-Euclidean Geometry Mathematics in the Age of Enlightenment Great progress was made in mathematics in this period The greatest advance in mathematics in this period—and one of the greatest achievements of the human mind ever—was the invention of the calculus in the late 17th C. by Newton and Leibniz The invention of the calculus was the culmination of an evolutionary process, not a revolution The roots of the calculus go back to Ancient Greece, and in the process of inventing calculus, the strict Euclidean approach was sidestepped, though not overturned Non-Euclidean Geometry Mathematics in the Age of Enlightenment Great progress was made in mathematics in this period The greatest advance in mathematics in this period—and one of the greatest achievements of the human mind ever—was the invention of the calculus in the late 17th C. by Newton and Leibniz The invention of the calculus was the culmination of an evolutionary process, not a revolution The roots of the calculus go back to Ancient Greece, and in the process of inventing calculus, the strict Euclidean approach was sidestepped, though not overturned The discovery of non-Euclidean geometry was a true revolution Non-Euclidean Geometry The Context for the Non-Euclidean Revolution Non-Euclidean Geometry The Context for the Non-Euclidean Revolution Just as Galileo and Darwin fought against a doctrine based in a text—the Bible—that was viewed as without error, the non-Euclidean revolution fought against another such text—Euclid’s “Elements” Non-Euclidean Geometry The Context for the Non-Euclidean Revolution Just as Galileo and Darwin fought against a doctrine based in a text—the Bible—that was viewed as without error, the non-Euclidean revolution fought against another such text—Euclid’s “Elements” Euclid wasn’t viewed as divinely inspired, presumably, but was viewed as nonetheless absolutely true, both in terms of what he said and how he argued Non-Euclidean Geometry The Context for the Non-Euclidean Revolution Just as Galileo and Darwin fought against a doctrine based in a text—the Bible—that was viewed as without error, the non-Euclidean revolution fought against another such text—Euclid’s “Elements” Euclid wasn’t viewed as divinely inspired, presumably, but was viewed as nonetheless absolutely true, both in terms of what he said and how he argued It might seem amazing that people took geometry so seriously back then, but ideas were valued back then—perhaps they should be today as well—and mathematics was viewed as an integral part of our conception of the world Non-Euclidean Geometry The Origins of Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Origins of Geometry Geometry was not discovered by the Ancient Greeks Non-Euclidean Geometry The Origins of Geometry Geometry was not discovered by the Ancient Greeks Geometrical ideas are found in a variety of ancient cultures, for example Egypt, Babylon and China prior to the rise of ancient Greece Non-Euclidean Geometry The Origins of Geometry Geometry was not discovered by the Ancient Greeks Geometrical ideas are found in a variety of ancient cultures, for example Egypt, Babylon and China prior to the rise of ancient Greece Geometry was originally an empirical matter, and arose in order to solve practical problems Non-Euclidean Geometry The Origins of Geometry Geometry was not discovered by the Ancient Greeks Geometrical ideas are found in a variety of ancient cultures, for example Egypt, Babylon and China prior to the rise of ancient Greece Geometry was originally an empirical matter, and arose in order to solve practical problems The singular contribution of the ancient Greeks to the study of geometry is the understanding that empirical justification of geometric statements is not sufficient, and that it is necessary to prove statements if we want to be sure that they are true Non-Euclidean Geometry Ancient Greek Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Ancient Greek Geometry The first person generally attributed with proving theorems in geometry is Thales of Miletus, about 624–547 BCE Non-Euclidean Geometry Ancient Greek Geometry The first person generally attributed with proving theorems in geometry is Thales of Miletus, about 624–547 BCE The next great figure is Pythagoras of Samos, about 569–475 BCE Non-Euclidean Geometry Ancient Greek Geometry The first person generally attributed with proving theorems in geometry is Thales of Miletus, about 624–547 BCE The next great figure is Pythagoras of Samos, about 569–475 BCE Ancient Greek mathematics was put into its ultimate deductive form by Euclid of Alexandria, about 325–265 BCE Non-Euclidean Geometry Euclid Non-Euclidean Geometry Euclid In his work “The Elements,” Euclid took an already developed large body of geometry, and gave it logical order by isolating a few basic definitions and axioms, and then deducing everything else from these definitions and axioms Non-Euclidean Geometry Euclid In his work “The Elements,” Euclid took an already developed large body of geometry, and gave it logical order by isolating a few basic definitions and axioms, and then deducing everything else from these definitions and axioms Euclid, and the ancient Greeks generally, viewed geometry rather differently than we currently do Non-Euclidean Geometry Euclid In his work “The Elements,” Euclid took an already developed large body of geometry, and gave it logical order by isolating a few basic definitions and axioms, and then deducing everything else from these definitions and axioms Euclid, and the ancient Greeks generally, viewed geometry rather differently than we currently do The only quantities that were of interest were geometric ones, and of those, geometric quantities that could be constructed with straightedge and compass were of particular interest Non-Euclidean Geometry Example: The Pythagorean Theorem Non-Euclidean Geometry Example: The Pythagorean Theorem In contemporary language, the Pythagorean Theorem states that if three numbers a, b and c correspond to the two sides and hypotenuse of a right triangle, then a2 + b2 = c2 Non-Euclidean Geometry Example: The Pythagorean Theorem In contemporary language, the Pythagorean Theorem states that if three numbers a, b and c correspond to the two sides and hypotenuse of a right triangle, then a2 + b2 = c2 To Euclid, such a statement about numbers would have made no sense Non-Euclidean Geometry Example: The Pythagorean Theorem In contemporary language, the Pythagorean Theorem states that if three numbers a, b and c correspond to the two sides and hypotenuse of a right triangle, then a2 + b2 = c2 To Euclid, such a statement about numbers would have made no sense Euclid’s version: “In right-angled triangles the square on the side subtending the right angle is equal to the squares on the sides containing the right angle.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Example: The Pythagorean Theorem In contemporary language, the Pythagorean Theorem states that if three numbers a, b and c correspond to the two sides and hypotenuse of a right triangle, then a2 + b2 = c2 To Euclid, such a statement about numbers would have made no sense Euclid’s version: “In right-angled triangles the square on the side subtending the right angle is equal to the squares on the sides containing the right angle.” When Euclid says that two planar figures (such as squares) are equal, he is not making a statement about the numerical values of their areas, but is saying that one figure can be cut up into triangles, and reassembled into the other figure Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Importance of Euclid Non-Euclidean Geometry The Importance of Euclid “The Elements” is one of the most important, and influential, works of mathematics ever written—it is arguably one of the most influential intellectual achievements of human civilization as a whole, not just of mathematics Non-Euclidean Geometry The Importance of Euclid “The Elements” is one of the most important, and influential, works of mathematics ever written—it is arguably one of the most influential intellectual achievements of human civilization as a whole, not just of mathematics Euclid’s treatment of geometry became the universally accepted method of doing geometry for almost two millenia, up till the 19th century Non-Euclidean Geometry The Importance of Euclid “The Elements” is one of the most important, and influential, works of mathematics ever written—it is arguably one of the most influential intellectual achievements of human civilization as a whole, not just of mathematics Euclid’s treatment of geometry became the universally accepted method of doing geometry for almost two millenia, up till the 19th century Not only was Euclidean geometry accepted as an unquestionably true description of the real world, but Euclid’s method of deductive reasoning was considered a model of logical argumentation, and an example of reasoning that produced theorems that were unquestionably true Non-Euclidean Geometry However Non-Euclidean Geometry However Without discounting from the enormous intellectual and historical importance of Euclid’s work, from a modern vantage point we can identify three fundamental flaws in Euclid, the resolutions of which did not take place until roughly two millenia after Euclid’s time Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Euclid tried to prove all other results in geometry in a rigorous fashion based only on his definitions and axioms Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Euclid tried to prove all other results in geometry in a rigorous fashion based only on his definitions and axioms There are flaws in Euclid’s definitions Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Euclid tried to prove all other results in geometry in a rigorous fashion based only on his definitions and axioms There are flaws in Euclid’s definitions Euclid’s axioms are neither complete nor necessarily true Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Euclid tried to prove all other results in geometry in a rigorous fashion based only on his definitions and axioms There are flaws in Euclid’s definitions Euclid’s axioms are neither complete nor necessarily true Some of Euclid’s proofs have gaps Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Euclid tried to prove all other results in geometry in a rigorous fashion based only on his definitions and axioms There are flaws in Euclid’s definitions Euclid’s axioms are neither complete nor necessarily true Some of Euclid’s proofs have gaps From a modern point of view, Euclid did not really achieve the level of rigor that has traditionally been ascribed to him Non-Euclidean Geometry The Flaws in Euclid Euclid tried to give precise definitions for geometric concepts Euclid tried to give a set of axioms that describe geometry Euclid tried to prove all other results in geometry in a rigorous fashion based only on his definitions and axioms There are flaws in Euclid’s definitions Euclid’s axioms are neither complete nor necessarily true Some of Euclid’s proofs have gaps From a modern point of view, Euclid did not really achieve the level of rigor that has traditionally been ascribed to him None of this is to deny the greatness—and importance—of Euclid’s achievement Non-Euclidean Geometry Some Definitions From Book I of “The Elements” Non-Euclidean Geometry Some Definitions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. A point is that which has no part Non-Euclidean Geometry Some Definitions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. A point is that which has no part 2. A line is breadthless length Non-Euclidean Geometry Some Definitions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. A point is that which has no part 2. A line is breadthless length 3. The extremities of a line are points Non-Euclidean Geometry Some Definitions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. A point is that which has no part 2. A line is breadthless length 3. The extremities of a line are points 4. A straight line is a line that lies evenly with the points on itself Non-Euclidean Geometry Nice Try Non-Euclidean Geometry Nice Try Euclid wanted define all the mathematical terms that he uses, such as point and line Non-Euclidean Geometry Nice Try Euclid wanted define all the mathematical terms that he uses, such as point and line By modern standards, Euclid’s definitions are meaningless Non-Euclidean Geometry Nice Try Euclid wanted define all the mathematical terms that he uses, such as point and line By modern standards, Euclid’s definitions are meaningless And no other definitions would have accomplished what Euclid wanted Non-Euclidean Geometry The Modern Approach Non-Euclidean Geometry The Modern Approach In the modern axiomatic approach to geometry, we start with some undefined terms (for example, “point” and “line”), though we hypothesize various axiomatic properties for these undefined terms (for example, we assume that every two distinct points are contained in a unique line) Non-Euclidean Geometry The Modern Approach In the modern axiomatic approach to geometry, we start with some undefined terms (for example, “point” and “line”), though we hypothesize various axiomatic properties for these undefined terms (for example, we assume that every two distinct points are contained in a unique line) Although Euclid’s definitions do not work as stated, there are modern axiom schemes, such as the ones by Hilbert in 1899 and Birkhoff in 1932, in which the definitions are worked out properly, with the caveat that some terms are left undefined Non-Euclidean Geometry The Common Notions From Book I of “The Elements” Non-Euclidean Geometry The Common Notions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. Things that are equal to the same things are equal to one another Non-Euclidean Geometry The Common Notions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. Things that are equal to the same things are equal to one another 2. If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal Non-Euclidean Geometry The Common Notions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. Things that are equal to the same things are equal to one another 2. If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal 3. If equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal Non-Euclidean Geometry The Common Notions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. Things that are equal to the same things are equal to one another 2. If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal 3. If equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal 4. Things that coincide with one another are equal to one another Non-Euclidean Geometry The Common Notions From Book I of “The Elements” 1. Things that are equal to the same things are equal to one another 2. If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal 3. If equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal 4. Things that coincide with one another are equal to one another 5. The whole is greater than the part. Non-Euclidean Geometry The Postulates From Book I of “The Elements” Non-Euclidean Geometry The Postulates From Book I of “The Elements” 1. To draw a straight line from any point to any point Non-Euclidean Geometry The Postulates From Book I of “The Elements” 1. To draw a straight line from any point to any point 2. To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line Non-Euclidean Geometry The Postulates From Book I of “The Elements” 1. To draw a straight line from any point to any point 2. To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line 3. To describe a circle with any center and radius Non-Euclidean Geometry The Postulates From Book I of “The Elements” 1. To draw a straight line from any point to any point 2. To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line 3. To describe a circle with any center and radius 4. That all right angles are equal to one another Non-Euclidean Geometry The Postulates From Book I of “The Elements” 1. To draw a straight line from any point to any point 2. To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line 3. To describe a circle with any center and radius 4. That all right angles are equal to one another 5. That, if a straight line falling on two straight lines makes the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, the straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? The common notions are not about geometry per se Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? The common notions are not about geometry per se The first three postulates involve straightedge and compass constructions Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? The common notions are not about geometry per se The first three postulates involve straightedge and compass constructions The First Postulate states that, given two different points, we can construct (using a straightedge) a line segment from one point to the other Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? The common notions are not about geometry per se The first three postulates involve straightedge and compass constructions The First Postulate states that, given two different points, we can construct (using a straightedge) a line segment from one point to the other The Second Postulate states that if we are given a line segment (which is finite in length), we can extend the line segment Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? The Third Postulate states that given a point, and given a radius, we can draw the circle that has the given point as its center, and has the given radius Non-Euclidean Geometry What Do the Common Notions and Postulates Say? The Third Postulate states that given a point, and given a radius, we can draw the circle that has the given point as its center, and has the given radius The Fourth Postulate says that any two right angles, no matter where they are located in the plane, are equal to one another Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate The Fifth Postulate is much more complicated than the other four Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate The Fifth Postulate is much more complicated than the other four Suppose we are given a line, say k, and two lines that intersect k, say m and n Non-Euclidean Geometry m A B k Non-Euclidean Geometry n The Fifth Postulate The Fifth Postulate is much more complicated than the other four Suppose we are given a line, say k, and two lines that intersect k, say m and n Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate The Fifth Postulate is much more complicated than the other four Suppose we are given a line, say k, and two lines that intersect k, say m and n Let α and β be the angles shown in the figure Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate The Fifth Postulate is much more complicated than the other four Suppose we are given a line, say k, and two lines that intersect k, say m and n Let α and β be the angles shown in the figure The Fifth Postulate states that if α + β < 180◦ , then the lines m and n will eventually intersect on the same side of k as α and β Non-Euclidean Geometry More Problems Non-Euclidean Geometry More Problems It turns out that the Euclid’s axioms are not sufficient to prove his propositions Non-Euclidean Geometry More Problems It turns out that the Euclid’s axioms are not sufficient to prove his propositions However, two thousand years after Euclid, mathematicians have showed that the problems with Euclid’s definitions and axioms can be fixed, and that Euclid’s arguments were essentially correct, just missing some details Non-Euclidean Geometry More Problems It turns out that the Euclid’s axioms are not sufficient to prove his propositions However, two thousand years after Euclid, mathematicians have showed that the problems with Euclid’s definitions and axioms can be fixed, and that Euclid’s arguments were essentially correct, just missing some details The real problem in Euclid is with the Fifth Postulate Non-Euclidean Geometry More Problems It turns out that the Euclid’s axioms are not sufficient to prove his propositions However, two thousand years after Euclid, mathematicians have showed that the problems with Euclid’s definitions and axioms can be fixed, and that Euclid’s arguments were essentially correct, just missing some details The real problem in Euclid is with the Fifth Postulate The first four are simple to state, and immediately believable Non-Euclidean Geometry More Problems It turns out that the Euclid’s axioms are not sufficient to prove his propositions However, two thousand years after Euclid, mathematicians have showed that the problems with Euclid’s definitions and axioms can be fixed, and that Euclid’s arguments were essentially correct, just missing some details The real problem in Euclid is with the Fifth Postulate The first four are simple to state, and immediately believable The fifth is much longer to state, and, while certainly believable, does not seem as immediately obvious as the first four Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Mathematicians throughout the centuries after Euclid noticed this problem Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Mathematicians throughout the centuries after Euclid noticed this problem If Euclid is to be viewed as demonstrating definitively true knowledge, then his axioms must be indisputably true Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Mathematicians throughout the centuries after Euclid noticed this problem If Euclid is to be viewed as demonstrating definitively true knowledge, then his axioms must be indisputably true The first four postulates seem quite convincing—The Fifth Postulate, by contrast, does not seem quite as indisputable Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Mathematicians throughout the centuries after Euclid noticed this problem If Euclid is to be viewed as demonstrating definitively true knowledge, then his axioms must be indisputably true The first four postulates seem quite convincing—The Fifth Postulate, by contrast, does not seem quite as indisputable It cannot simply be dropped—it is definitely used in some of Euclid’s proofs Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Mathematicians throughout the centuries after Euclid noticed this problem If Euclid is to be viewed as demonstrating definitively true knowledge, then his axioms must be indisputably true The first four postulates seem quite convincing—The Fifth Postulate, by contrast, does not seem quite as indisputable It cannot simply be dropped—it is definitely used in some of Euclid’s proofs A number of people after Euclid tried to deduce the Fifth Postulate from the other four, and some claimed success Non-Euclidean Geometry The Fifth Postulate, Again Mathematicians throughout the centuries after Euclid noticed this problem If Euclid is to be viewed as demonstrating definitively true knowledge, then his axioms must be indisputably true The first four postulates seem quite convincing—The Fifth Postulate, by contrast, does not seem quite as indisputable It cannot simply be dropped—it is definitely used in some of Euclid’s proofs A number of people after Euclid tried to deduce the Fifth Postulate from the other four, and some claimed success They were all mistaken Non-Euclidean Geometry A Good Mistake Non-Euclidean Geometry A Good Mistake One person who attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate from the other four was Giovanni Girolamo Saccheri 1667–1733 Non-Euclidean Geometry A Good Mistake One person who attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate from the other four was Giovanni Girolamo Saccheri 1667–1733 He attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate by assuming that it was false, and trying to reach a logical contradiction Non-Euclidean Geometry A Good Mistake One person who attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate from the other four was Giovanni Girolamo Saccheri 1667–1733 He attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate by assuming that it was false, and trying to reach a logical contradiction He proved many interesting things about geometry with the Fifth Postulate false Non-Euclidean Geometry A Good Mistake One person who attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate from the other four was Giovanni Girolamo Saccheri 1667–1733 He attempted to prove the Fifth Postulate by assuming that it was false, and trying to reach a logical contradiction He proved many interesting things about geometry with the Fifth Postulate false He thought that he had eventually reached a logical contradiction, but he was mistaken Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Saccheri’s problem was conceptual—he couldn’t admit that by assuming the Fifth Postulate is false, he obtained an alternative, but perfectly good, geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Saccheri’s problem was conceptual—he couldn’t admit that by assuming the Fifth Postulate is false, he obtained an alternative, but perfectly good, geometry The first person who seems to have realized that negating the Fifth Postulate could lead to a perfectly good geometry was Carl Friedrich Gauss, 1777–1855 Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Saccheri’s problem was conceptual—he couldn’t admit that by assuming the Fifth Postulate is false, he obtained an alternative, but perfectly good, geometry The person who realized that negating the Fifth Postulate could lead to a perfectly good geometry was Carl Friedrich Gauss, 1777–1855 Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Saccheri’s problem was conceptual—he couldn’t admit that by assuming the Fifth Postulate is false, he obtained an alternative, but perfectly good, geometry The person who realized that negating the Fifth Postulate could lead to a perfectly good geometry was Carl Friedrich Gauss, 1777–1855 Gauss is widely viewed as one of the three greatest mathematicians of all time Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Saccheri’s problem was conceptual—he couldn’t admit that by assuming the Fifth Postulate is false, he obtained an alternative, but perfectly good, geometry The person who realized that negating the Fifth Postulate could lead to a perfectly good geometry was Carl Friedrich Gauss, 1777–1855 Gauss is widely viewed as one of the three greatest mathematicians of all time He seems to have had this realization about geometry by 1817, and he worked out what a non-Euclidean geometry would be like Non-Euclidean Geometry The Revolution will not be Publicized Saccheri’s problem was conceptual—he couldn’t admit that by assuming the Fifth Postulate is false, he obtained an alternative, but perfectly good, geometry The person who realized that negating the Fifth Postulate could lead to a perfectly good geometry was Carl Friedrich Gauss, 1777–1855 Gauss is widely viewed as one of the three greatest mathematicians of all time He seems to have had this realization about geometry by 1817, and he worked out what a non-Euclidean geometry would be like He kept his views about geometry secret Non-Euclidean Geometry Letter of Gauss to Bessel, 27 January 1829 Non-Euclidean Geometry Letter of Gauss to Bessel, 27 January 1829 ...There is another topic, one which for me is almost 40 years old, that I have thought about from time to time in isolated free hours, I mean the first principles of geometry; I dont know if I have ever spoken to you about this. Also in this I have further consolidated many things, and my conviction that we cannot completely establish geometry a prioir has become stronger. In the meantime it will likely be quite a while before I get around to preparing my very extensive investigations on this for publication; perhaps this will never happen in my lifetime since I fear the cry of the Boetians if I were to voice my views. ... Non-Euclidean Geometry Meanwhile Non-Euclidean Geometry Meanwhile Gauss’ ideas were independently discovered by two young mathematicians: János Bolyai, 1802–1860, and Nikolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky, 1792–1856 Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Bolyai Non-Euclidean Geometry Bolyai Bolyai made his discoveries by 1824, though it was published only in 1831 as an appendix to a book by his father, a friend of Gauss Non-Euclidean Geometry Bolyai Bolyai made his discoveries by 1824, though it was published only in 1831 as an appendix to a book by his father, a friend of Gauss One the one hand Non-Euclidean Geometry Bolyai Bolyai made his discoveries by 1824, though it was published only in 1831 as an appendix to a book by his father, a friend of Gauss One the one hand Letter of Gauss to Gerling, 14 February 1832 Non-Euclidean Geometry Bolyai Bolyai made his discoveries by 1824, though it was published only in 1831 as an appendix to a book by his father, a friend of Gauss One the one hand Letter of Gauss to Gerling, 14 February 1832 I consider this young geometer, v. Bolyai, to be a genius of the first class.... Non-Euclidean Geometry Bolyai Bolyai made his discoveries by 1824, though it was published only in 1831 as an appendix to a book by his father, a friend of Gauss One the one hand Letter of Gauss to Gerling, 14 February 1832 I consider this young geometer, v. Bolyai, to be a genius of the first class.... On the other hand Non-Euclidean Geometry Letter of Gauss to Bolyai’s father, 6 March 1832 Non-Euclidean Geometry Letter of Gauss to Bolyai’s father, 6 March 1832 ....Now for some remarks about the work of your son. If I start by saying I cannot praise it then you will most likely be taken aback; but I cannot do otherwise; to praise it would be to praise myself; the entire contents of the work, the path that your son has taken and the results to which it leads, are almost perfectly in agreement with my own meditations, some going back 30 35 years. In truth I am astonished. My intention was not to release any of my own work in my lifetime. Non-Euclidean Geometry Lobachevsky Non-Euclidean Geometry Lobachevsky Lobachevsky published his work in an obscure Russian journal in 1829, which neither Bolyai nor Gauss saw Non-Euclidean Geometry Lobachevsky Lobachevsky published his work in an obscure Russian journal in 1829, which neither Bolyai nor Gauss saw He published his work in French in 1837, and in German in 1840, at which point it because more widely known Non-Euclidean Geometry Lobachevsky Lobachevsky published his work in an obscure Russian journal in 1829, which neither Bolyai nor Gauss saw He published his work in French in 1837, and in German in 1840, at which point it because more widely known Gauss was impressed Non-Euclidean Geometry Simultaneity Non-Euclidean Geometry Simultaneity What do we make of the fact that three people independently made the same astonishing discovery? Non-Euclidean Geometry Simultaneity What do we make of the fact that three people independently made the same astonishing discovery? Nothing Non-Euclidean Geometry Simultaneity What do we make of the fact that three people independently made the same astonishing discovery? Nothing It is not very unusual in mathematics Non-Euclidean Geometry Simultaneity What do we make of the fact that three people independently made the same astonishing discovery? Nothing It is not very unusual in mathematics Sometimes the field has developed to a point where new ideas are waiting to be discovered Non-Euclidean Geometry Simultaneity What do we make of the fact that three people independently made the same astonishing discovery? Nothing It is not very unusual in mathematics Sometimes the field has developed to a point where new ideas are waiting to be discovered And perhaps it is not a coincidence that this mathematical revolution happened in a generally revolutionary period Non-Euclidean Geometry What did Gauss, Bolyai and Lobachevsky Accomplish? Non-Euclidean Geometry What did Gauss, Bolyai and Lobachevsky Accomplish? There had never been a proof that Euclid’s axioms are consistent—that is, that they have no internal contradictions Non-Euclidean Geometry What did Gauss, Bolyai and Lobachevsky Accomplish? There had never been a proof that Euclid’s axioms are consistent—that is, that they have no internal contradictions Gauss, Bolyai and Lobachevsky also did not prove that their type of geometry was consistent, they simply asserted that there is such geometry, and deduced various consequences Non-Euclidean Geometry What did Gauss, Bolyai and Lobachevsky Accomplish? There had never been a proof that Euclid’s axioms are consistent—that is, that they have no internal contradictions Gauss, Bolyai and Lobachevsky also did not prove that their type of geometry was consistent, they simply asserted that there is such geometry, and deduced various consequences Later in the 19th C., it was proved that non-Euclidean geometry is no more or less consistent than Euclidean geometry, so that if one accepts Euclidean geometry, one has to accept the alternatives as well Non-Euclidean Geometry Playfair’s Axiom Non-Euclidean Geometry Playfair’s Axiom If m is a line, and A is a point not on m, then there is one and only one line through A that is parallel to m Non-Euclidean Geometry Playfair’s Axiom If m is a line, and A is a point not on m, then there is one and only one line through A that is parallel to m “Playfair’s Axiom” in not an axiom at all, but a theorem in Euclidean geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Playfair’s Axiom If m is a line, and A is a point not on m, then there is one and only one line through A that is parallel to m “Playfair’s Axiom” in not an axiom at all, but a theorem in Euclidean geometry Playfair’s Axiom is not only a theorem in Euclidean geometry, but, more strongly, it is equivalent to Euclid’s Fifth Postulate Non-Euclidean Geometry A m Non-Euclidean Geometry A n m Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Suppose that m is a line, and A is a point not on m Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Suppose that m is a line, and A is a point not on m If Playfair’s Axiom were not true, then there are two possible cases Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Suppose that m is a line, and A is a point not on m If Playfair’s Axiom were not true, then there are two possible cases (1) There is more than one line through A that is parallel to m Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Suppose that m is a line, and A is a point not on m If Playfair’s Axiom were not true, then there are two possible cases (1) There is more than one line through A that is parallel to m That is called hyperbolic geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Suppose that m is a line, and A is a point not on m If Playfair’s Axiom were not true, then there are two possible cases (1) There is more than one line through A that is parallel to m That is called hyperbolic geometry (2) There is no line through A that is parallel to m Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean geometry results from taking Euclid’s first four postulates, but replacing the Fifth Postulate by something else It is easier to understand what happens in non-Euclidean geometry if we consider alternatives to Playfair’s Axiom Suppose that m is a line, and A is a point not on m If Playfair’s Axiom were not true, then there are two possible cases (1) There is more than one line through A that is parallel to m That is called hyperbolic geometry (2) There is no line through A that is parallel to m That is called spherical geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Redux Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Redux Euclid’s Fifth Postulate implies that the sum of the angles in any triangle is 180◦ Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Redux Euclid’s Fifth Postulate implies that the sum of the angles in any triangle is 180◦ In hyperbolic geometry, the sum of the angles in a triangle is always less than 180◦ (the precise sum can vary from triangle to triangle) Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Redux Euclid’s Fifth Postulate implies that the sum of the angles in any triangle is 180◦ In hyperbolic geometry, the sum of the angles in a triangle is always less than 180◦ (the precise sum can vary from triangle to triangle) In spherical geometry, the sum of the angles in a triangle is always greater than 180◦ (again, the precise sum can vary from triangle to triangle) Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Once Again Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Once Again It is hard to imagine how hyperbolic or spherical geometry would work if we use the familiar sort of straight lines found in the plane Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Once Again It is hard to imagine how hyperbolic or spherical geometry would work if we use the familiar sort of straight lines found in the plane But why restrict ourselves only to the most familiar situation? Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Once Again It is hard to imagine how hyperbolic or spherical geometry would work if we use the familiar sort of straight lines found in the plane But why restrict ourselves only to the most familiar situation? On the surface of a sphere, where “straight lines” are great circles, it is seen that the sum of the angles in a triangle is greater than 180◦ , and hence is spherical geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Once Again It is hard to imagine how hyperbolic or spherical geometry would work if we use the familiar sort of straight lines found in the plane But why restrict ourselves only to the most familiar situation? On the surface of a sphere, where “straight lines” are great circles, it is seen that the sum of the angles in a triangle is greater than 180◦ , and hence is spherical geometry Models for hyperbolic geometry can also be found Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Geometry Liberated Non-Euclidean Geometry Geometry Liberated If geometry is not necessarily as Euclid said, then many other possibilities open up Non-Euclidean Geometry Geometry Liberated If geometry is not necessarily as Euclid said, then many other possibilities open up Even staying within the realm of Euclidean geometry, new approaches were developed soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Geometry Liberated If geometry is not necessarily as Euclid said, then many other possibilities open up Even staying within the realm of Euclidean geometry, new approaches were developed soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry One new approach was via the recently developed theory of groups Non-Euclidean Geometry Geometry Liberated If geometry is not necessarily as Euclid said, then many other possibilities open up Even staying within the realm of Euclidean geometry, new approaches were developed soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry One new approach was via the recently developed theory of groups This approach led to a thorough study of symmetry Non-Euclidean Geometry Geometry Liberated If geometry is not necessarily as Euclid said, then many other possibilities open up Even staying within the realm of Euclidean geometry, new approaches were developed soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry One new approach was via the recently developed theory of groups This approach led to a thorough study of symmetry Three-dimentional crystallographic symmetry was classified in the 1880’s Non-Euclidean Geometry Variable Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Variable Geometry Euclidean, spherical and hyperbolic geometries are constant geometries Non-Euclidean Geometry Variable Geometry Euclidean, spherical and hyperbolic geometries are constant geometries It is also possible to have variable geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Variable Geometry Constant Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Higher Dimensions Non-Euclidean Geometry Higher Dimensions Euclid discusses planar and spatial geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Higher Dimensions Euclid discusses planar and spatial geometry Soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry, the idea of higher dimensional geometry arose in the work of a few authors Non-Euclidean Geometry Higher Dimensions Euclid discusses planar and spatial geometry Soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry, the idea of higher dimensional geometry arose in the work of a few authors The most important contributor to the development of higher-dimensional geometry was Georg Friedrich Bernhard Riemann, 1826-1866, a student of Gauss Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Higher Dimensions Euclid discusses planar and spatial geometry Soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry, the idea of higher dimensional geometry arose in the work of a few authors The most important contributor to the development of higher-dimensional geometry was Georg Friedrich Bernhard Riemann, 1826–1866, a student of Gauss Non-Euclidean Geometry Higher Dimensions Euclid discusses planar and spatial geometry Soon after the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry, the idea of higher dimensional geometry arose in the work of a few authors The most important contributor to the development of higher-dimensional geometry was Georg Friedrich Bernhard Riemann, 1826–1866, a student of Gauss Riemann’s ideas on higher-dimensional geometry were delivered in the inaugural lecture “Über die Hypothesen welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen” (On the hypotheses that lie at the foundations of geometry), delivered on 10 June 1854 Non-Euclidean Geometry Riemann’s Inaugural Lecture Non-Euclidean Geometry Riemann’s Inaugural Lecture Riemann introduced the notion of variable geometry in higher dimensions Non-Euclidean Geometry Riemann’s Inaugural Lecture Riemann introduced the notion of variable geometry in higher dimensions Riemann introduced the idea of the metric tensor and the curvature tensor Non-Euclidean Geometry Riemann’s Inaugural Lecture Riemann introduced the notion of variable geometry in higher dimensions Riemann introduced the idea of the metric tensor and the curvature tensor We now refer to Riemann’s type of geometry as Riemannian geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Riemann’s Inaugural Lecture Riemann introduced the notion of variable geometry in higher dimensions Riemann introduced the idea of the metric tensor and the curvature tensor We now refer to Riemann’s type of geometry as Riemannian geometry “Among Riemann’s audience, only Gauss was able to appreciate the depth of Riemann’s thoughts. ... The lecture exceeded all his expectations and greatly surprised him. Returning to the faculty meeting, he spoke with the greatest praise and rare enthusiasm to Wilhelm Weber about the depth of the thoughts that Riemann had presented.” Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Differential geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Differential geometry Algebraic geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Differential geometry Algebraic geometry Topology Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Differential geometry Algebraic geometry Topology Hyperbolic three-manifolds and the Poincaré Conjecture Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Differential geometry Algebraic geometry Topology Hyperbolic three-manifolds and the Poincaré Conjecture String theory and other aspects of mathematical physics Non-Euclidean Geometry The Impact Continues into the 20th C. Geometry and its descendants are flourishing—the golden era of mathematics research is now! Differential geometry Algebraic geometry Topology Hyperbolic three-manifolds and the Poincaré Conjecture String theory and other aspects of mathematical physics One person in the 20th C. who thought about the nature of the real world geometrically was Albert Einstein, 1879–1955 Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein There are two parts to the theory of relativity: special relativity in 1905, and general relativity in 1916 Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein There are two parts to the theory of relativity: special relativity in 1905, and general relativity in 1916 Special relativity does not use sophisticated mathematics Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein There are two parts to the theory of relativity: special relativity in 1905, and general relativity in 1916 Special relativity does not use sophisticated mathematics Einstein was not a big fan of mathematics Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein There are two parts to the theory of relativity: special relativity in 1905, and general relativity in 1916 Special relativity does not use sophisticated mathematics Einstein was not a big fan of mathematics “I don’t believe in mathematics.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein There are two parts to the theory of relativity: special relativity in 1905, and general relativity in 1916 Special relativity does not use sophisticated mathematics Einstein was not a big fan of mathematics “I don’t believe in mathematics.” “As far as the laws of mathematics refer to reality, they are not certain; and as far as they are certain, they do not refer to reality.” Non-Euclidean Geometry Einstein There are two parts to the theory of relativity: special relativity in 1905, and general relativity in 1916 Special relativity does not use sophisticated mathematics Einstein was not a big fan of mathematics “I don’t believe in mathematics.” “As far as the laws of mathematics refer to reality, they are not certain; and as far as they are certain, they do not refer to reality.” “Reading after a certain time diverts the mind too much from its creative pursuits. Any man who reads too much and uses his own brain too little falls into lazy habits of thinking.” Non-Euclidean Geometry General Relativity Non-Euclidean Geometry General Relativity General relativity deals with gravity Non-Euclidean Geometry General Relativity General relativity deals with gravity Einstein at first had the intuitive idea for general relativity, which involves the idea of curved space-time, but he did not have the mathematical tools to formulate his ideas Non-Euclidean Geometry General Relativity General relativity deals with gravity Einstein at first had the intuitive idea for general relativity, which involves the idea of curved space-time, but he did not have the mathematical tools to formulate his ideas He sought help from a mathematician, who brought Riemannian geometry to his attention Non-Euclidean Geometry General Relativity General relativity deals with gravity Einstein at first had the intuitive idea for general relativity, which involves the idea of curved space-time, but he did not have the mathematical tools to formulate his ideas He sought help from a mathematician, who brought Riemannian geometry to his attention General relativity was then formulated in the framework of Riemannain geometry, which Riemann had initiated 50 years earlier Non-Euclidean Geometry General Relativity General relativity deals with gravity Einstein at first had the intuitive idea for general relativity, which involves the idea of curved space-time, but he did not have the mathematical tools to formulate his ideas He sought help from a mathematician, who brought Riemannian geometry to his attention General relativity was then formulated in the framework of Riemannain geometry, which Riemann had initiated 50 years earlier Without the non-Euclidean revolution, the mathematical tools for general relativity would not have existed for Einstein to use Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Up till the non-Euclidean revolution, it was thought that there was only one type of geometry, and that this geometry described the real world Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Up till the non-Euclidean revolution, it was thought that there was only one type of geometry, and that this geometry described the real world If there are actually many possible geometries, then they cannot all describe the real world Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Up till the non-Euclidean revolution, it was thought that there was only one type of geometry, and that this geometry described the real world If there are actually many possible geometries, then they cannot all describe the real world In his inaugural lecture, Riemann raised the question of the relation between mathematical space and physical space Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Up till the non-Euclidean revolution, it was thought that there was only one type of geometry, and that this geometry described the real world If there are actually many possible geometries, then they cannot all describe the real world In his inaugural lecture, Riemann raised the question of the relation between mathematical space and physical space Mathematics can describe the possible geometries of the world Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Up till the non-Euclidean revolution, it was thought that there was only one type of geometry, and that this geometry described the real world If there are actually many possible geometries, then they cannot all describe the real world In his inaugural lecture, Riemann raised the question of the relation between mathematical space and physical space Mathematics can describe the possible geometries of the world To determine which geometry describes our world, Riemann concludes his lecture by saying: “This leads us into the domain of another science, of physic, into which the object of this work does not allow us to go to-day.” Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry There are also a variety of 3-dimensional geometries Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry There are also a variety of 3-dimensional geometries We assume that the universe has three physical dimensions Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry There are also a variety of 3-dimensional geometries We assume that the universe has three physical dimensions Mathematics can say something about the possible types of geometry that the 3-dimensional universe can have Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry There are also a variety of 3-dimensional geometries We assume that the universe has three physical dimensions Mathematics can say something about the possible types of geometry that the 3-dimensional universe can have Would it be possible to know the geometry of the universe? Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry There are also a variety of 3-dimensional geometries We assume that the universe has three physical dimensions Mathematics can say something about the possible types of geometry that the 3-dimensional universe can have Would it be possible to know the geometry of the universe? Some people, such as Jeffrey Weeks, are actively trying to find out Non-Euclidean Geometry The Shape of the Universe The original non-Euclidean revolution was about 2-dimensional geometry There are also a variety of 3-dimensional geometries We assume that the universe has three physical dimensions Mathematics can say something about the possible types of geometry that the 3-dimensional universe can have Would it be possible to know the geometry of the universe? Some people, such as Jeffrey Weeks, are actively trying to find out If they succeed, it will be an achievement on par with the work of Copernicus Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Part II Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Part II It led to a flourishing of new approaches to geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Part II It led to a flourishing of new approaches to geometry It changed our understanding of the relation of mathematics to the physical world Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Part II It led to a flourishing of new approaches to geometry It changed our understanding of the relation of mathematics to the physical world And yet, it did not undermine the belief in the certainty of mathematics, in the knowability of mathematics, nor of the value of mathematics in the study of the physical world Non-Euclidean Geometry The Nature of the Non-Euclidean Revolution Part II It led to a flourishing of new approaches to geometry It changed our understanding of the relation of mathematics to the physical world And yet, it did not undermine the belief in the certainty of mathematics, in the knowability of mathematics, nor of the value of mathematics in the study of the physical world The non-Euclidean Revolution was a product of the Enlightenment mindset Non-Euclidean Geometry The Next Revolution in Mathematics Non-Euclidean Geometry The Next Revolution in Mathematics There was a revolution that undermined our faith in the knowability of mathematics, due to Kurt Gödel, 1906–1978 Non-Euclidean Geometry Non-Euclidean Geometry The Next Revolution in Mathematics There was a revolution that undermined our faith in the knowability of mathematics, due to Kurt Gödel, 1906–1978 Non-Euclidean Geometry The Next Revolution in Mathematics There was a revolution that undermined our faith in the knowability of mathematics, due to Kurt Gödel, 1906–1978 Gödel showed, essentially, that in any mathematical system that contains arithmetic, there are facts that can be proved neither true nor false Non-Euclidean Geometry The Next Revolution in Mathematics There was a revolution that undermined our faith in the knowability of mathematics, due to Kurt Gödel, 1906–1978 Gödel showed, essentially, that in any mathematical system that contains arithmetic, there are facts that can be proved neither true nor false Gödel’s result, which was a very precise mathematical theorem, seems to fit in with other questions that have been raised in the 20th C. about the limits of knowledge Non-Euclidean Geometry And Yet Non-Euclidean Geometry And Yet The non-Euclidean revolution, which did not change our understanding of the limits of knowledge of mathematics, caused a great flourishing of new mathematical activity Non-Euclidean Geometry And Yet The non-Euclidean revolution, which did not change our understanding of the limits of knowledge of mathematics, caused a great flourishing of new mathematical activity The revolution of Gödel, which had great philosophical impact, had little practical effect upon the work of research mathematicians Non-Euclidean Geometry And Yet The non-Euclidean revolution, which did not change our understanding of the limits of knowledge of mathematics, caused a great flourishing of new mathematical activity The revolution of Gödel, which had great philosophical impact, had little practical effect upon the work of research mathematicians What is the relation between our understanding of how knowledge is gained with the actual pursuit of knowledge? Non-Euclidean Geometry And Yet The non-Euclidean revolution, which did not change our understanding of the limits of knowledge of mathematics, caused a great flourishing of new mathematical activity The revolution of Gödel, which had great philosophical impact, had little practical effect upon the work of research mathematicians What is the relation between our understanding of how knowledge is gained with the actual pursuit of knowledge? An important question, but, to paraphrase Riemann Non-Euclidean Geometry And Yet The non-Euclidean revolution, which did not change our understanding of the limits of knowledge of mathematics, caused a great flourishing of new mathematical activity The revolution of Gödel, which had great philosophical impact, had little practical effect upon the work of research mathematicians What is the relation between our understanding of how knowledge is gained with the actual pursuit of knowledge? An important question, but, to paraphrase Riemann This leads us into the domain of another science, of philosophy, into which the object of this work does not allow us to go to-day. Non-Euclidean Geometry The End