This article was downloaded by:[Brandeis University] On: 7 August 2007 Access Details: [subscription number 731923898] Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Journal of Jewish Education Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t714578333 OPENNESS AND COMMITMENT: Hans-Georg Gadamer and the Teaching of Jewish Texts Jon A. Levisohn Online Publication Date: 01 March 2001 To cite this Article: Levisohn, Jon A. (2001) 'OPENNESS AND COMMITMENT: Hans-Georg Gadamer and the Teaching of Jewish Texts', Journal of Jewish Education, 67:1, 20 - 35 To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/0021624010670106 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0021624010670106 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article maybe used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. © Taylor and Francis 2007 Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 OPENNESS AND COMMITMENT: Hans-Georg Gadamer and the Teaching of Jewish Texts JON A. LEVISOHN INTRODUCTION Among the foremost goals of Jewish education is the teaching of Jewish texts, and the fostering of the abilities among students to enable them to read the texts themselves, and to read them well. Teaching texts involves certain interpretive judgments, about which texts to include and which to exclude, about which interpretations of those texts to integrate and which to set aside, and about the image of interpretive competence which we hold as an ideal. These issues are, at least in part, subject to philosophical deliberation; empirical inquiry has much to contribute, but ultimately the decisions that we make must be made on normative, rather than empirical, grounds. One way to enter into these broad philosophical questions is to do so through the particular prism of a leading theorist. This paper takes up this strategy, considering the issues in light of a central figure in the contemporary discussion of hermeneutics, HansGeorg Gadamer. Gadamer was born in Marburg, Germany, in 1900, and spent his academic career at various German universities, ending up at Heidelberg in 1949.1 He retired in 1968, only a few years after the publication of his major work, WahrheitundMethode, in 1960. Translated as Truth and Method (Gadamer 1989/ 1960; hereafter TM), this work has been enormously influential in the field of hermeneutics Jon A. Levisohn is a doctoral candidate in Philosophy of Education at Stanford University. andbeyond, and since his retirement, Gadamer has experienced a second career as a "travelling scholar,"2 participating actively in philosophical debates, publishing widely, and travelling around the world to teach and discuss his work.3 In Truth and Method, Gadamer sets out a description of how interpretation works that stands in opposition to the view that, to that point, had dominated philosophical discussion of literary and historical interpretation. The prior view, following in the tradition of Droysen and the Historical School, held that good interpretation involves the systematic effort to eliminate the subjective influences of the interpreter, in orderto reproduce the original meaning of a text.4 Gadamer's stand in opposition to this conservative view has led some to misread him as throwing open the doors to subjectivity in interpretation. This position — that the interpreter has free rein to play with the text — is associated with the radical camp in hermeneutics, represented by Derrida and Foucault. 5 But this is not Gadamer's view. A more attentive reading makes it clear that he preserves a place for normativity in interpretation—the sense that our best interpretations are not just our own whimsical creations, but rather that they represent responsible readings of the text — and that he is concerned primarily with providing an explanation of how this works. Indeed, much of his later work is concerned to show how radical subjectivist hermeneutics fails to account for important features of interpretation as it is actually practiced. This paper is not, of course, the place to offer a comprehensive critique or defense of 20 Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMER AND THE TEACHING OF TEXTS Gadamer's view. Instead, my initial objective is to offer an introductory reading of his view, addressed to the non-specialist. Then, following that presentation (Part One), and some subsequent clarifications (Part Two), I want to offer some reflections about the connections between Gadamer's hermeneutics and Jewish education. Those reflections will come in two flavors. In a section that I have called "Jewish Education in Light of Gadamer" (Part Three), I will describe three ways in which Gadamer's view parallels the process of interpretation of Jewish texts within a normative Jewish context (such as that providedby a Jewish school). If these arguments are sound — if Gadamer can indeed help us to think about Jewish education — this suggests a kind of descriptive accuracy to his view. Furthermore, it implies something else: that the project of Jewish educational interpretation is not fundamentally different from other kinds of academic or scholarly interpretation, despite claims to the contrary (e.g., Alter, 1974; Yerushalmi, 1982).6 But following that section is another set of reflections, entitled "Gadamer in Light of Jewish Education" (Part Four) in which some of the weaknesses of his view are thrown into relief. Gadamer's view is not Torah min haShamayim, and thinking about real world interpretive processes helps us to see some of the problems and tensions within his view. So it should be clear that this paper will not, and cannot, offer a tidy theoretical solution to the various problems in the teaching of Jewish texts. What I hope to do, rather, is to introduce a philosophical framework which helps articulate some of those issues, which helps draw out the complications and nuances, and which helps us to see the philosophical implications of the interpretive choices that we make. PART ONE: GADAMER'S VIEW In one crucial section of Truth and Method, 21 Gadamer lays out his own view of interpretation in contrast with two alternative views in a particularly helpful way.7 In order to do so, he uses a rhetorical device, presenting three competing views of the nature of hermeneutic experience as parallels to three kinds of human relationships — relationships between one person, an /, and another person, a Thou. It might seem strange to compare interpreting a text to relating to another person, but the comparison highlights the way in which Gadamer conceives of interpretation as a kind of dialogue. In what sense can a text be in dialogue with an interpreter? Here it is important to note that, for Gadamer, the text as object of interpretation is never taken in isolation, but always stands at the same time within a tradition of which that text is a constitutive part. To interpret a text is to be in dialogue with a tradition; andby virtue of that dialogue, the tradition is not something we merely accept or reject but something to which we belong." The first kind of inter-personal relationship that Gadamer describes is when we consider another person to be an It rather than a Thou (see Appendix A). That is, we sometimes relate to the Thou as an object, a thing that is subject to predictable laws. We sometimes avoid engaging with other human beings as people, as individuals, and instead try to discover typical behavior and the psychological or sociological laws that govern that behavior. Now, there maybe times when this approach is defensible — for example when we are conducting social scientific research for noble purposes.9 But it can certainly be morally problematic, for when we do this, we treat people as means towards other ends rather than as ends in themselves, and by. doing so, we may rob them of their autonomy and individuality. In the second form of relationship, we do manage to see the other as a Thou, as an individual person rather than just a data point—but we still do not fully acknowledge Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 22 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCATION our connection to the person. In this interaction, the other person is not merely taken to be an object whose behavior is subject to prediction; instead, the/genuinely desires to understand the Thou. But there is still something missing, because the first person is unable to listen with an open mind. So the first person claims to understand the second person, but by doing so, he loses out on the possibility of genuine dialogue. Instead, what one gets is a kind of pre-digestion of the claim of the other person. For Gadamer, the key element in this second form of inter-personal encounter is that "by understanding [the other], by claiming to know him, one robs his claims of their legitimacy" (TM, p. 360). How can trying to understand another person be a bad thing? The problem lies with the claim of complete understanding of the other person, complete explanation of his position. This attempt robs the claims of the other of legitimacy — the claim is "co-opted and pre-empted" (TM, p. 359) —by saying, in effect, I know why you said what you said, and therefore I know what you really meant. Imagine, as an example, a particular kind of doctor-patient relationship: the doctor is respectful of the patient's individuality, but she is not really interested in the truth of what the patient says. She's not interested in the patient as a real person; the only reason to listen to the patient is to figure out the cause of the symptoms. There's no real inter-personal connection, and no dialogue. The thirdkindof human relationship makes up for the deficiencies in the first two. The / acknowledges the individuality of the other person, and allows for the possibility of hearing something new. In other words, this kind of interpersonal relationship is characterized not merely by how we conceptualize the other person, but more importantly, by the fundamental openness of our own stance. And according to Gadamer, together with this kind of openness comes mutual involvement and mutual responsibility; each side has made an open-ended commitment to hearing what the other has to say.10 Here, then, we find the pinnacle of interpersonal encounter: genuine openness, genuine belonging and commitment, genuine dialogue. Some of this terrain may be familiar from other philosophers, especially Martin Buber. But where Buber uses these insights into the dynamics of human relationships to construct his theology, Gadamer uses them for the purpose of his hermeneutics. So, turning now to the three kinds of hermeneutic experience, the parallel to the./»-.!tf level of human relationship is to treat the text as an It and not as a Thou.u What does this mean? The key is to notice the role of generalization and prediction: when we treat the Thou as an //, we drain the Thou of its particular features in order to consider the Thou as nothing other than an instance of a general rule. An extreme structuralist approach, for example, would take a particular poem as, first and foremost, an instance of a general linguistic structure. Or, a determinist view of history would take an historical event to be significant only in terms of the way that it confirms the "laws of history." In this way, all meaning and significance of 'theparticular text, or particular event, is lost. We could even say that the text loses its voice. Instead, the text is merely a datum, as disconnected from the interpreter as the electron is disconnected from the physicist who observes it.12 In the parallel to the second level of human relationship, the interpreter does not simply take the text as an instantiation of a general principle but considers the text itself, as a unique historical artifact worthy of inquiry. The Thou is taken as a genuine Thou, not merely as an //. We care about understanding this particular text or this particular historical event, not just constructing some global theory of literature or history. So far, so good. However, this second conception of the hermeneutic experience does not yet suffi- Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMER AND THE TEA CHING OF TEXTS ciently engage the claims of the text itself, in genuine dialogue. Instead, it seeks to understand the text in its historical context, to articulate the claims of the text in terms of an explanation of why this text, or this author, would make such claims. Gadamer calls this conception "historical consciousness." Significantly, lurking behind this conception is what Gadamer calls the "ideal of perfect enlightenment," the notion that an inquirer can methodically free herself from all of her prejudices in order to achieve pure objectivity. According to this conception, the goal of an interpretation is to construct the correct explanation of what a text means in terms of what the original author really meant to say and why he meant to say it. Note that, according to this conception, the author or the text may be understood as historically contingent, as a product of a particular time and place, but the explanation of the text is considered to be a fixed, trans-historical object, waiting to be discovered and reproduced.13 Finally, the parallel to the third level of human relationship is Gadamer's own view, what he calls "historically effected consciousness." This third form approaches a text with openness, acknowledges atext as possessinga "claim to validity... in such a way that it has something to say to me" (TM, p. 361). That is, good interpretation allows for the possibility that the claims of the text — claims which have "asserted [themselves] in [their] own separate validity" — may "provoke" me, may help me to see that my own beliefs and assumptions are wrong (TM, p. 299). The easiest way to think about this contrast between the second conception and the third is to consider the case of philosophical texts. For some, the history of philosophy is simply a history of errors, and the only possible interest that one could take in such texts is historical: for example, why did Plato say what he said, and howwas it understoodat the time. But this is not a satisfactory way of dealing with the 23 major texts of the philosophical tradition. Instead, we engage philosophical texts in genuine dialogue, taking their claims seriously, making the best arguments possible on their behalf in order to make them intelligible, and to allow them to challenge our own conceptions. This does not mean that we simply accept Plato's arguments, of course, because often our own conceptions withstand the challenge. (Nor does it mean that we can do without historical scholarship, which clarifies ambiguous terms and elucidates contextdependent meanings.) But in the course of the encounter, our views are changed. Gadamer, in fact, would suggest that our own views are developed, through the process of interpretive dialogue, in a way that they could never have developed on their own (TM, p. xxii). Significantly, Gadamer critiques the second conception, "historical consciousness," as a foolhardy attempt to rely on a critical methodology, a way of insulating the interpreter and the interpretation from historical contingency. For Gadamer, interpreting from within a particular tradition is not a philosophical embarrassment, and does not represent a failure; in fact, it is the only option open to us. He writes: "to be situated within a tradition does not limit the freedom of knowledge but makes it possible" (TM, p. 361). Only when we are embedded in a tradition do we have the kind of interests that motivate us to inquire into the meanings of a text. So what he calls "historical consciousness" fails to apply its historicism to its own stance, so to speak, because it fails to examine its own assumptions and does not allow them to be challenged. It is, therefore, never really open. PART TWO: SOME CLARIFICATIONS OF GADAMER'S VIEW It should be clear, by this point, that the object of interpretation is not a single, fixed Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 24 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCA TION meaning of the text. What, then, is the goal of interpretation, in Gadamer's view? Thisquestion is particularly important for thinking about the teaching of texts, but it has to be answered on three different levels. On the first level, the goal of interpretation is to clarify the meaning of the text from the perspective of a particular historical situation. That is, while there can never be one correct reading of a text based on the correct reproduction of the original meaning, there can, on the other hand, be interpretations which capture some of the meaning of the text given the set of assumptions of a particular interpreter living at a particular time. So the first goal of interpretation is to get at some of these meanings; this is what it means to interpret responsibly. On a second level, the goal of interpretation is to bring our assumptions and beliefs, both about the text and general beliefs as well, into a situation where they will be challenged and transformed. Gadamer writes: "How then can we foreground [our assumptions]? It is impossible to make ourselves aware of a prejudice while it is operating unnoticed, but only when it is, so to speak, provoked. The encounter with a traditionary text can provide this provocation" (TM, p. 299). But then, on athird level, Gadamer argues that the goal of interpretation is a deepening of the kind of openness that should characterize the interpretive encounter in the first place. Gadamer writes: The henneneutical consciousness culminates not in methodological sureness of itself, but in the same readiness for experience that distinguishes the experienced man from the man captivated by dogma (TM, p. 362). So at this level, what is primary for Gadamer is not the knowledge that is achieved by interpretive inquiry, but the openness that is both the prerequisite for interpretation and (as is now seen) its "culmination." The conclu- sion or pinnacle of interpretation is not really a conclusion at all, but in some sense a gateway, opening up towards further inquiry, further experience, and further insight.14 But if interpretation culminates in something intensely personal, and if the meaning of the text is historically contingent, does this not suggest that all interpretation is subjective? In other words, if my meaning — the meaning that / find in the text — is different than your meaning, what possible objective standard or criterion can be found to adjudicate between the two? Indeed, Bernstein argues that this concern is what motivates theorists in the "conservative" camp (Bernstein, 1985). But Gadamer believes he can have it both ways. He's intensely critical of any reliance on methodology — what he sometimes calls "objectivism"— in which the interpreter believes that strict adherence to some scholarly method will eliminate all traces of historical influence on his interpretation.15 Yet, in contrast to fashionable denigrations of objectivity, Gadamer's work is also replete with affirmations of the possibility of achieving a correct interpretation of a text, and denials that interpretation is arbitrary.16 Indeed, Truth and Method is equally about the illegitimacy of method in interpretation and about the legitimacy of truth; perhaps a better title would have been "Truth without Method."17 At this point, we may find ourselves confused by the ways in which the historical situation of the interpreter is supposed to affect the interpretation, even as, at the same time, it apparently does not undermine the truth of interpretation. On the one hand, the interpreter cannot avoid the historical situatedness of her own interpretation. Because of this, she must not deceive herself into thinking that her object is the transhistorical meaning of the text, for this will lead her into the historicist trap of explaining away the truth claims of the text rather than encounter- Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMER AND THE TEA CHING OF TEXTS ing them herself. On the other hand, we also know that her interpretation cannot merely relyuponherarbitraryprejudices,forGadamer is not willing to abandon normativity in interpretation. How is this supposed to work? In one place, Gadamer asks us to consider an example of historical interpretation: the way in which the history of certain Eskimo tribes will be written differently in fifty years from the way in which it is written today (TM, p. xxxii). The reason for this is not, primarily, because we will have collected more artifacts, or because we will have a better understanding of environmental factors, or because we will have more knowledge of the patterns of cultural interaction. All of these things maybe true, but in the end, the human sciences are not progressive or cumulative in this way. The primary reason that historical interpretations come to be outdated has to do with the ongoing development of our interests and our questions. It is simply impossible to eliminate these questions and interests altogether, in order to write a 'plain' history that would approximate the 'real' interpretation of that history, and that would be appropriate for all historical epochs.18 These questions and interests are just one part of the contribution of the interpreter to the interpretation. This contribution — what Heidegger calls "fore-meaning"19—includes also the entire totality of our linguistic environment, which determines what it is that we can say and think, and also our specific preconceptions of the meaning of the text. But in bringing these fore-meanings to the text, Gadamer believes that we do not merely impose them. The encounter is, again, rather like a dialogue. Thus, we discover that our preconception is inadequate "in the experience of being pulled up short by the text" (TM, p. 268); the text itself seems to tell us that our understanding is wrong.20 What is significant here is the way in which preconceptions can go hand in hand with openness: on the one 25 hand, one approaches a text with an hypothesis about its meaning, but on the other hand, one is open to the text to disconfirm that hypothesis. In terms of the earlier discussion, one assumes from the outset that the text makes a truth claim that has validity — i.e., a claim that coheres with those beliefs that one holds to be true — while remaining open to the possibility that its claim may differ from, and in fact may challenge, one's own beliefs.21 Finally, then, we should ask the looming question: how do we know when we've got the correct interpretation of a text? There's no methodological guarantee, to be sure, but in two places in Truth and Method Gadamer does talk about criteria—a criterion of objectivity in the process of interpretation, and a criterion of objectivity in the outcome of interpretation. The first criterion is openness and questioning: when one is open to what the text has to say, one is willing not only to question the text but also to question one's own beliefs (TM, pp. 268-9). All genuine interpretation takes place in the context of openness, and conversely, if one is not open, then one cannot achieve a correct interpretation. The second criterion involves the outcome of interpretation, rather than the process: that outcome is "harmony."22 What is harmonized is the interpretation and the text itself, as the hermeneutic circle is traversed. Correct interpretations are harmonious, while incorrect interpretations are characterized by disunity, disconfirmation, the over-prominence of the interpretation distinct from the text itself. We might desire more; we might hope to translate these criteria into methodological guidelines; but ultimately that desire cannot be fulfilled. PART THREE: JEWISH EDUCATION IN THE LIGHT OF GADAMER At this point, it is time to consider how Gadamer's theory of interpretation help us to think about what it is that we do in Jewish education. In this section, I will try to articu- Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 26 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCATION late three ways in which Gadamer's view is generative for thinking about the teaching of texts within a normative Jewish context. First, Gadamer's notion of tradition provides a theoretical framework which both validates and informs an approach to Jewish texts within a normative Jewish context, an approach which often seems to stand in tension with scientific or scholarly or critical approaches. This does not deny that a critical approach to Jewish texts may have a place in Jewish education; I will return to this point later on. However, by showing how the process of interpretation always takes place within a tradition, and always represents a dialogic interaction with that tradition, Gadamer helps make sense of reading traditional texts in traditional ways. Why should we teach the sometimes dated, sometimes difficult interpretations of an eleventh century French exegete? Because it is undeniable that Rashi's commentary has shaped the way that Jews have read Torah up to our own day. To take another example, a similar approach holds, at least to a certain extent, in thinking about the teaching of Mishnah. A critical study of Mishnah may very well have its place; we may certainly want to ask what the Mishnah, itself, seems to be saying. But we also want to ask how the Mishnah has been read within the tradition, and this will lead u s first and foremost to the views expressed in the Talmud. If we use the interpretive criterion of "original intent," some of these views may seem difficult, and perhaps philosophically unjustifiable. But if our interest is that of investigating (and teaching) the Mishnah together with its interpretive history — what Gadamer calls the "history of effect" — then we are led to the conclusion that engaging with the text within a Jewish context requires engaging with the way that the tradition has read this text through time. To do otherwise is to lack awareness of our own historical moment, to pretend that we can achieve a non- historical, non-prejudiced, de-contextualized interpretation.23 Remember, here, that the interpreter is always embedded within atradition, but never merely accepts that tradition. That is, the tradition is both the partner in dialogue and the environment that makes dialogue possible. So it may be that we want to engage the interpretive history of the Mishnah in dialogue, a dialogue in which we challenge the tradition — and allow ourselves to be challenged —on the question of the correct way to read the Mishnah. This is the force of Gadamer's focus on normativity in interpretation. For while our interpretations are conditioned by our tradition and by our historical moment, they are determined by neither. In contrast to those for whom recourse to "interpretive communities" provides the last word in matters of interpretation (e.g., Fish, 1980), Gadamer's view preserves the sense in which, even within those communities, we evaluate — and cannot fail to evaluate — interpretations as better and worse. A second important theme in Gadamer is his model of dialogue itself. Engaging with someone — or, as Gadamer helps us to see, with some thing — in dialogue entails confronting that person as an interlocutor whose assertions are to be taken seriously. That is, we begin from an assumption that the person is saying something correct, or at least claiming to say something correct; we are open to that possibility. That claim then functions as a question for us; it challenges us. We may accept the claim or reject it, but we may not ignore it, so that even //we reject it, we are changed by the encounter with it, by the demand to provide a response. Dialogue is therefore predicated not only upon openness but also upon mutual commitment; without such a commitment, a person whose beliefs are challenged will simply walk away. This is, I think, the kind of commitment that we have towards foundational aspects of Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMERAND THE TEACHING OF TEXTS 27 general culture. Not everyone agrees, of course, Third, and finally, recall Gadamer's view on what those foundational aspects are. But of interpretation — or, of the hermeneutic consider the role of Shakespeare in our cul- experience — as the kind of experience which ture; consider the way that colleges teach terminates not only in understanding of the courses on Shakespeare, and students attend text but in readiness for further and richer them, because they believe that an educated experience, as one's understanding becomes person ought to engage with these texts. Even richer and more mature. The previous paraif they don't end up taking the course, and graph focused on openness as a characteristic even if they sleep through the lectures, the of interpretation itself, but Gadamer also has very suggestion represents a kind of commit- a view about the way that engaging in interment to the texts, a promise (which may go pretive dialogue opens one up still further, unfulfilled) to engage in dialogue. They prob- transforms one, develops one's capacity to ably don'tbelieve that Shakespeare possesses encounter certain aspects of experience more some kind of propositional knowledge which deeply. The caricature of Jewish study holds they want to have, and which is available on that it closes off possibilities for participating the basis of critical historical scholarship; and in the world. Seen through a Gadamerian they almost certainly don't believe that the perspective, however, engagingin dialogue — goal of reading Shakespeare is merely to play even with one's own tradition— represents with the text. But, to the extent that they an opening up of possibilities through the way participate in this kind of commitment, they that one's assumptions are challenged and may indeed hold open the possibility that the one's horizons are broadened. In a larger text has something to say to them, that it is sense than previously discussed, this reprerelevant to their lives. sents the goal of the teaching of Jewish texts: This is the relationship that we want Jew- opening up students to the possibilities of ish students to have towards the Jewish tradi- further experience — with Jewish texts and tion, and towards its texts. That is, these twin with Jewish life. aspects of dialogue — openness and commitment —maybe seen as normative goals in the PART FOUR: GADAMER IN THE teaching of Jewish texts. Students ought to LIGHT OF JEWISH EDUCATION confront the text as making a claim upon Just as Gadamer's view of interpretation is them, and must have an openness to that generative for thinking about the teaching of claim — though not, of course, an unquesJewish texts, it is also the case that comparing tioning acceptance of that claim, any more his theory to the real-world educational situthan one unquestioningly accepts the stateation highlights some weaknesses of, or tenments of a partner in dialogue. This kind of sions within, the position. In what follows, I openness implies, in turn, a commitment to will outline three of these tensions. the text, a commitment to the process of First, there is the question of defining a ongoing dialogue with this particular partner. Beyond the transmission of information, tradition, for at times there seems to be an beyond the fostering of technical skills of assumption that the tradition — the tradition interpretation (such as historical methodol- of the text and its interpretation, in which we ogy or linguistic proficiency), Jewish educa- are embedded— is fundamentally unitary tion aims for a kind of interpretive compe- and coherent. But this seems questionable. tence characterized by openness and commit- Consider Torah. In fact, the interpretive history of Torah is, like everything else, varied, ment. Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 28 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCATION plural, and non-linear. Even if we restrict ourselves to considering just one religious or cultural tradition, is it correct to see this tradition — including rationalists and mystics, halakhists and theologians — as an integrated whole? Furthermore, and more importantly, in the modern period one must consider a new tradition, namely the historicocritical tradition itself. After all, there is certainly a strong sense in which academic schol arship on the Bible represents its own tradition stretching back for two centuries, with its own set of questions and interests. To be sure, aspects of this tradition of interpretation stand in tension with traditional Jewish interpretation —and yet, in various subtle ways, we are heirs to both of them. One way to try and deal with the multiplicity of traditions is to suggest that, in fact, a Gadamerian view can accommodate them by pointing to the unification of traditions within the historical situation of the interpreter herself. That is, there may be several traditions of interpretation in the world, but it is still descriptively correct that any one individual interpreter is heir to everything that contributed to her historical situation, and that her interpretation is carried out—and may achieve insight and capture meaning—in the context of her "tradition" in this sense. Butthis doesn't solve the problem. On the one hand, this interpretation of Gadamer gains something by softening his rhetoric of a unitary tradition. But on the other hand, it will still have a problem dealing with the basic tensions between those traditions. How is it possible to account for the interpretive practice of one individual who operates within two traditions? And how, then, are we to conceive of the interpretive practice of a community which tries to do so? Even more interestingly, how can we account for the ways in which those two traditions subtly influence each other in the hermeneutic experience of the individual interpreter? Without considering these challenges, we run the risk of simply assuming that the tradition in which we are embedded is exclusively, for lack of a better word, the "traditional" one. This can lead to the kind of interpretive conservatism of which Gadamer has sometimes been accused.24 But to do so would represent exactly the kind of avoidance of one's historical situation that Gadamer decries. The historical situation that we find ourselves in, and which conditions our interpretations, is as obviously a product of modernity as it is a product of the Jewish tradition. What this suggests, for the teaching of Jewish texts, is that we need to confront our historical situation more straightforwardly, and to recognize the ways in which our community is embedded within a complicated mixture of traditions. One of these is the Jewish tradition, to be sure, but we are also heirs to certain Enlightenment criteria about prioritizing "plain" readings of the text, for example. And those criteria influence the ways that we select from among the various interpretive approaches that make up the Jewish tradition. This means, for example, that we cannot be quite so sanguine about teaching Talmud as the interpretive tradition of the Mishnah; we must also consider the ways in which Talmudic readings of the Mishnah stand in tension with plain readings. Or consider again the case of Rashi' s commentary on Torah, and especially the question of "Mah kasheh le-Rashi? made famous by Nechama Leibowitz. By asking, "What troubles Rashi [about the text?", not only do we generate a deeper understanding of his interpretive technique but we place ourselves in the position of probing the interpretive merits of that technique relative to others. And while Leibowitz' approach may be masterfully constructed to facilitate engagement rather than skepticism (Deitcher, 2000), it also seems fair to say that her approach is unavoidably a product of the conditions of modernity. Finally, and more Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMERAND THE TEACHING OF TEXTS generally, we cannot assume that the traditional curriculum is as appropriate for us as it may have been in the past. For example, when we teach Rabbinic literature, should we teach the Babylonian Talmud exclusively, or are there particular reasons — reasons generated by our own interpretive situations — to teach the Talmud of the Land of Israel, or perhaps the Tosefta? Obviously, this does not amount to a rejection of the traditional curriculum, but it does suggest that our curricular choices require stronger and more nuanced justifications, justifications which confront our historical situation as modern Jews rather than standing in self-conscious opposition to it. The second point, related to the first, involves the question of the assumptions or preconditions that we bring to our interpretations of a text. Some of these pre-conditions have to do with the entire linguistic background in which we operate, while others have to do with our prior hypotheses about the meaning of a specific text to be interpreted. But other assumptions, such as the questions and interests that we bring to the text, are products of our historical context and, therefore, of the traditions in which we are embedded. On Gadamer's view, this latter set of assumptions is supposed to be public property, since others share our cultural moment. But if we think about actual interpretive situations, such as those that educators face, we might wonder whether Gadamer is sensitive enough to the diversity of assumptions that people can bring to a text — even among people who apparently share a faith tradition. Perhaps such rigid homogeneity once obtained, but in our culture and our ideologically diverse Jewish community, we cannot assume that it does. To take an obvious example, a passage in Torah that is traditionally understood to be the source for normative law will be taken in different ways by others. And lest we think that this is only a problem faced in those institutions that attempt to bridge de- 29 nominations, it should not be hard to recognize that, even within denominations, similarities of observance may mask profound interpretive discrepancies. If this is so —if we question the possibility of interpretive agreement — this raises again the problem of how we are to approach the text within an educational context. For Jewish educators, this issue is not simply an academic one about interpretive normativity; it's a very real one about what kinds of approaches to the text ought to be fostered among students. What Gadamer helps us to see is that appeals to pluralism can only go so far before they must confront interpretive diversity head on, precisely because schools are the places where students are embedded in the interpretive traditions which enable interpretation in the first place. Third, and finally: it is clear that for Gadamer, every text — in fact, every object of interpretation, including works of art — is supposed to make a truth claim.25 As noted, the paradigm for this are philosophical texts: we should readPlato not merely as a representative of a particular time and place, but also and more importantly as presenting a view of, for example, the well-ordered republic, with which an interpreter must engage. But what if we turn to Torah? What is the truth claim of the text?26 If one is to think of Torah in terms of the claims that it makes, the claims with which an interpreter is confronted, the first kind of claim that comes to mind is mitzvah, commandment. The Torah seems to be making practical demands upon its reader, making claims regarding performances rather than regardingtheology. But immediately one hesitates, for that kind of claim assumes a particular conception of commandment based on Rabbinic interpretation. In addition, it seems equally correct to say, for us, that the claim of the text is something like an existential one — a claim about what it is like to experience Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 30 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCATION history in a particular way — or perhaps a literary claim. As a fourth alternative, the text at times makes a set of historical claims, about when and where certain events occurred. It therefore seems that one can endorse the theoretical framework which asks the interpreter to engage in genuine dialogue with the text, to see the text as making a claim, while at the same time recognizing that it may not be obvious what kind of claim that is. This question is the question of genre. A philosophical text makes a philosophical claim, a literary text makes a literary claim, an historical text makes an historical claim (TM, p. 163). But genre itself is a category that is proposed by the interpreter, and may never be as smooth as Gadamer seems to hope. What this tension within Gadamer suggests is that a heightened awareness of the workings of genre — a kind of meta-cognitive reflection on how the text does whatever it is that we interpret the text as doing27 — ought to be a fundamental component of our approach to the teaching of texts, as a way of accessing those "fore-meanings" which form the context for (thougli, again, do not determine) our prioritization of interpretations. The challenge for Jewish educators is to articulate their (or their communities') understanding of the genre of the traditionary text, and of their own historical situations, so that the truth claims of the text can amount to more than just vague admonitions. CONCLUSION It should be clear that we should not expect any philosophical viewto solve the theoretical problems of Jewish education. But the intended effect of this paper is to suggest that the insight that Gadamer brings to thinking about the interpretation of texts may help us to think: more deeply about what we do, and about the interpretive choices that we make. In this respect, even the problems embedded within Gadamer's view are generative, for they point towards a series of philosophical questions about the teaching of Jewish texts. And the consideration of these questions — about the multiplicity of, and interactions among, interpretive traditions; about the role of the assumptions that we bring to the text; and about the possibility and variety of truth claims — will contribute to the improvement of our educational practice. In Gadamer's own terms: We should leain to understand ourselves better and recognize that in all understanding, whether we are expressly aware of it or not, the efficacy of history is at work (TM, p. 301). It may very well be that the "efficacy of history" is at work in all understanding, whether we are aware of it or not. But at the same time, if we hope to understand ourselves better— and, by extension, achieve better understanding of the interpretations of our texts — then we ought to do what we can to raise this effect to consciousness. We should certainly do no less for our students. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS For their comments on earlier drafts—not all of which I was wise enough to incorporate— I wish to acknowledge Mara Benjamin, Jennifer Glaser, Rami Wernik, and especially Richard Palmer. ENDNOTES 'In the 1920s, Gadamer was a student of Martin Heidegger, who remained the most significant influence on his thought. Given Heidegger's wellknown Nazi sympathies (for a helpful review essay, see Sheehan, 1993), what do we know about Gadamer's activities during the Nazi period? In general, the facts are not in dispute: Gadamer was not a Nazi, but was also not a hero. During the Nazi period, Gadamer did not speak out publicly— but Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMER AND THE TEACHING OF TEXTS also did not join the party. He did willingly accept an academic position made available when Richard Kroner, a friend, was dismissed for being a Jew— but he also took Kroner in as a house guest. He continued to teach and conduct his research during the war years in a university system compromised by the elimination of Jews and the fostering of fascism— but he maintained contact with Jews during the war, and following its conclusion, worked on behalf of their re-integration into the German university system. Gadamer's own description of the Nazi period appears in Gadamer 1997 (and see also his contribution to a symposium on Heidegger and Nazism in Gadamer, 1989). Richard Wolin has recently written a harshly critical account (Wolin, 2000), but Richard Palmer critiques Wolin's interpretation of the facts and of the political significance of Gadamer's philosophical work (Palmer, unpublished). 2 Gadamer, 1997, p. 18. 3 The secondary literature on Gadamer is vast. For an accessible book-length source on Gadamer, see Wamke, 1987. For an influential account in which Gadamer figures as a central figure, see Bernstein, 1985. For a collection of critical essays, together with Gadamer's replies, see Hahn, 1997. 4 It can equally be said that Gadamer develops his position in opposition to the tradition of Scheiermacher and Dilthey, theorists who attempted (but, in Gadamer's view, failed) to come to terms with subjectivity in interpretation. 5 Gallagher, 1992 offers a four-fold taxonomy of hermeneutical approaches, including (i) conservative, (ii) moderate, (iii) radical, and (iv) critical. For a critical review of Gallagher, see Kerdeman, 1998. This kind of claim has the potential to be misunderstood. It should be clear that there are important differences between various contexts of interpretation; in fact, understanding those differences is essential if we are to understand the interpretive processes at work. Rather, the claim is that there is no sharp and clear divide between these spheres. See Gadamer, 1987/1963, p. 114. 'These passages appear at TM, pp. 358-362, at the end of the section entitled, "The Concept of Experience (Erfahrung) and the Essence of the Hermeneutic Experience." The value and centrality of this section is noted by Gadamer himself, in 31 his Foreword to the Second Edition: "The section on experience (Part Two, U.3.B) takes on a systematic and key position in my investigations. There the experience of the Thou throws light on the concept of historically effected experience" (TM, p. xxxv). 8 See TM, pp. 262 ff, in which Gadamer argues that belonging to a tradition is a condition of any historical interest whatsoever. 'For example, one can certainly make a strong case that social scientific inquiry, which aims to improve the lives of humans, is justified in (temporarily) considering people as mere data points. And in fact, while Gadamer is sometimes read as an opponent of naturalistic social science, his attitude is not exclusively negative. He writes: "[My work] does not in the slightest prevent the methods of modern natural science from being applicable to the social world....Therefore I did not remotely intend to deny the necessity of methodical work within the human sciences" (TM, p. xxix). See also Gadamer, 1976, p. 26 ff. 10 "To reach an understanding in a dialogue is not merely a matter of putting oneself forward and successfully asserting one's own point of view, but being transformed into a communion in which we do not remain what we were" (TM, p. 379). Note, however, that this kind of openness operates alongside a set of expectations or anticipations; indeed, if we did not have such anticipations (of what the other person is going to say, of what makes sense in a particular situation, of the meaning of a text), we would not need to be open to the possibility that we are wrong! So the openness that Gadamer is talking about is not a know-nothing absence of beliefs and opinions, and in the case of interpersonal relationships, it is not an absence of selfhood. "hi my discussion of this passage, I will simply follow Gadamer's lead and chart the parallels between the three forms of interpersonal experience and the three forms of hermeneutic experience. But it should be noted that there is a significant tension dormant within the analogy, and within Gadamer's text. Very briefly, consider the fact that the three forms of interpersonal relationship are all familiar to us; they all exist in the world. And of the three, the third is "highest." But of the three forms of hermeneutic experience, Gadamer's implicit argument is that, as a matter of Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 32 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCATION descriptive accuracy, only the third is an adequats characterization of what actually occurs in inteipretation. In one sense, therefore, the third form is the "highest" of the three — but it is more correct to see it as the only correct description. On my reading, Gadamer is insufficiently sensitive to this tension embedded within his analogy. "Gadamer, in general, adopts the neo-Kantian Verstehen tradition of separating the physical sciences, which search for laws, from the human sciences, which search for understanding. However, at another level, interpretation is fundamental to all human experience. His position on physical science underwent some revision in light of post-Kuhnian philosophy of science; see for example TM, p. 283 n. 209. 13 Clearly, Gadamer is thinking here of nineteenth-century historicism, which may be understood as his central philosophical target. But it is worth acknowledging that any straightforward theory of authorial intent would suffer from this same flaws. And indeed, Gadamer elsewhere is critical of such theoretical stances: "the sense of a text in general reaches far beyond what its author originally intended" (TM, p. 372). Similarly, this suggestion that the object of interpretation ought to be to recover the meaning of the text to the original audience suffers from the same malady, "the real meaning of a text...does not depend on the contingencies of the author and his original audience" (TM, p. 296). Such an interpretive stance denies the truth claims of the text itself, substituting instead an explanation of why the text says what it say. 14 This may sound reminiscent of Dewey's view about education and growth, where the goal is; simply more growth. However, unlike Dewey, Gadamer tends to focus on the negative quality of experience, the way in which experience is marked by the disturbance of expectations and disruption of prior assumptions. "Consider the following passage: "In relying, on its critical method, historical objectivism conceals the fact that historical consciousness is itself situated in the web of historical effects.... Historical objectivism resembles statistics, which are such excellent means of propaganda because they let the "facts" speak and hence simulate an objectivity that in reality depends on the legitimacy of the questions asked" (TM, p. 300-301). "For example: "Because the important thing is communicating the text's true meaning, interpreting it is already subject to the norm of the subject matter" (TM, p. 394), or "Being bound by a situation [that is, the fact that all interpretation must necessarily take place within an historical hermeneutical situation] does not mean that the claim to correctness that every interpretation must make is dissolved into the subjective or the occasional" (TM, p. 397). Elsewhere, he makes it clear that his goal, in his account of the human sciences, is to put forward "an entirely different notion of knowledge and truth" (Gadamer, 1987/1963, p. 92). Are these examples of hyperbole? Perhaps. And in any case, we should certainly be wary of importing incompatible notions of truth and correctness which make these claims look patently inconsistent. Yet, it seems clear that Gadamer is demanding that we attend to the ways in which interpretations are evaluated according to their responsiveness to the text. "Richard Palmer (in a private communication) objects to this formulation, arguing that the relationship between truth and method in Gadamer is a complicated one. Instead, Palmer would emphasize the utility of method, within certain bounded spheres. His point is well taken; compare my notes 9 and 12. ls Similarly, Gadamer writes elsewhere that "when we read Mommsen's History of Rome, we know who alone could have written it, that is, we can identify the political situation in which this historian organized the voices of the past in a meaningful way" (Gadamer, 1976, p. 6). "In TM, Gadamer's main discussion of Heidegger is at pp. 265 ff. But it may be the case that Gadamer would have been better served by articulating that relationship between his "prejudices" and Heidegger's "fore-structure" more clearly. Heidegger's fore-structure has three parts: the fore-having, the entire linguistic environment; the fore-sight, the particular aspect of the object which is brought into view (which is clearly related to the questions that one asks about the object); and the fore-conception, the provisional hypothesis about the meaning of the object with which one starts (Heidegger, 1962/1927, pp. 188 ff.) Gadamer writes as if all three of these aspects Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 GADAMER AND THE TEACHING OF TEXTS operate in the same fashion; they are all part of our "prejudices," a product of our historical contingency and embeddedness within tradition. But it may be that they operate quite differently. The fore-having can never be questioned because it can never be brought into consciousness; on the other hand, as a product of culture, it is clearly not subjective either. The fore-conception, on the other hand, clearly can be questioned, and is most susceptible to confirmation or especially disconfirmation by examination of the object itself. That leaves the fore-sight, which one may associate with Gadamer's "questions and interests." These too are susceptible to conscious change— we can become feminist or Marxist interpreters — but the criteria for doing so are the hardest to articulate. 20 Elsewhere, Gadamer writes dramatically that "a person trying to understand something will not resign himself from the start to relying on his own accidental fore-meanings, ignoring consistently and stubbornly as possible the actual meaning of the text until the latter becomes so persistently audible that it breaks through what the interpreter imagines it to be" (TM, p. 269). Note, however, that the counter-factual syntax of the sentence makes it unclear whether Gadamer actually thinks that the meaning of the text ever does "break through" and coerce the interpreter in this way. 21 In another passage, Gadamer identifies no fewer than four contributors to the meaning of a text. He writes: "Every age has to understand a transmitted text in its own way, for the text belongs to the whole tradition whose content interests the age and in which it seeks to understand itself. The real meaning of a text, as it speaks to the interpreter, does not depend on the contingencies of the author and his original audience. It certainly is not identical with them, for it is always co-determined also by the historical situation of the interpreter and hence by the totality of the objective course of history" (TM, p. 296). That is, the "real meaning" is, in a sense, a product of (a) the author, (b) the original audience, (c) the historical situation of the interpreter, and (d) the total history of the tradition of interpretation. 22 "The harmony of all the details with the whole is the criterion of correct understanding" (TM, p. 291). Harmony, too, reappears in various 33 guises: as unity (TM, p. 267 and elsewhere), as confirmation of the interpretation by the text (TM, p. 267), and most interestingly, as the "disappearance" of the interpretation (TM, pp. 398-400). "Compare Levenson's argument about the ways that interpretive contexts affect how we teach Bible even in higher education: "There is no neutral ground on which to locate [the study of the] Hebrew Bible. Each model favors one context...over another. None can claim pure objectivity. Every act of periodicization or categorization implies a normative claim" (Levenson, 1986, p. 44). 24 This is the basic objection of Jiirgen Habermas, with whom Gadamer engaged in a series of debates in the 1970s. Habermas believes that Gadamer is far too solicitous of tradition, and far too hesitant to criticize it (Habermas, 1992/1970). This is certainly an important critique, but Gadamer is primarily concerned not with prescribing our interpretive practices but with describing them. He is simply trying to tell us what happens all (or most of) the time, unreflectively. Furthermore, there is room within Gadamer's conception for reforms of the status quo. As he writes elsewhere, "the confrontation of our historical tradition is always a critical challenge of this tradition" (Gadamer, 1987/1963, p. 87). On the Gadamer-Habermas debate, see Teigas, 1995. "While Gadamer generally refers to "truth claims," he infrequently offers different formulations, such as (the somewhat more flexible) "meaning claim" (Gadamer, 1987/1963, p. 87). "One might wonder whether Gadamer has in mind this kind of text at all. But in fact, it is clear that he does. Part of the thrust of his view is to challenge the assumptions of the historico-critical method of research in the Bible; what Gadamer hopes to articulate is the sense in which what the Bible weans, to us as inheritors of the text and the tradition of its interpretation, is not adequately captured by, for example, research into the historical account of its composition. And more directly, Gadamer has a suggestion for how to consider the Bible: he holds that both a Jewish and a Christian interpretation of the Bible presuppose a concern with "the question of God" (TM, pp. 331-332). But is this helpful? In what sense does Torah, for a Jew, provide an answer to "the question of God?" 34 JOURNAL OF JEWISH EDUCA TION Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 "Sam Wineburg suggests something similar, on the basis of his empirical research into the ways that expert historians read historical texts (Wineburg, 1991). REFERENCES Alter, Robert. "What Jewish Studies Can Do." Commentary 58:4 (1974). Bernstein, Richard J. Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1985. Deitcher, Howard. "Between angels and mere mortals: Nechama Leibowitz's approach to the study of Biblical characters." Journal of Jewish Education 66:1-2 (2000), 8-22. Fish, Stanley. Is There a Text in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. Second revised edition. Translation revised by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. New York: Continuum Publishing Co., 1989. Originally published in German as Wahrheit und Methode, 1960. First translated into English in 1975. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Philosophical Hermeneutics. Translated and edited by David E. Linge. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. "The problem of historical consciousness." In Interpretive Social Science: A Second Look, edited by Paul Rabinow and William Sullivan. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987. Originally published in German in 1963. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. "Back from Syracuse." Critical Inquiry 15:2 (1989). Gadamer, Hans-Georg. "Reflections on my philosophical journey." Translated by Richard Palmer, in The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XXIV, edited by Lewis E. Hahn. Chicago: Open Court, 1997. Gallagher, Shaun. Hermeneutics and education. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1992. Habermas, Jürgen. "On hermeneutics' claim to universality." In The Hermeneutics Reader, edited by Kurt Mueller-Vollmer. New York: Continuum, 1992. Originally published in German in 1970. Hahn, Lewish E., ed. The Philosophy ofHans-Geo phers, Vol. XXIV. Chicago: Open Court, 1997. Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarie and Edward Robinson. San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1962. Originally published in German as Sein und Zeit in 1927. Kerdeman, Deborah. "Hermeneutics and education: Understanding, control, and agency." Educational Theory 48:2 (1998), 241-267. Levenson, Jon. "Hebrew Bible in Colleges and Universities, "Religious Education 81 (1986), 37-45. Palmer, Richard. "Richard Wolin's Misrepresentation of Gadamer: Setting the Record Straight." Unpublished. See <www.mac.edu/ ~rpalmer/articles.html> Sheehan, Thomas. "A Normal Nazi." New York Review of Books XL, 1-2 (Jan. 14, 1993), 30-35. See <www.stanford.edu/dept/relstud/ faculty/pdf/NormalNa.pdf> Teigas, Demetrius. Knowledge and Hermeneutic Understanding: A Study of the HabermasGadamer Debate. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 1995. Warnke, Georgia. Gadamer: Hermeneutics, Tradition and Reason. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1987. Wineburg, Samuel S. "On the reading of historical texts: Notes on the breach between school and academy." American Educational Research Journal 28:3 (Fall 1991), 495-519. Wolin, Richard. "Nazis and the Complicities of Hans-Georg Gadamer." The New Republic. May 15, 2000. Yerushalmi, Yosef Hayim. Zakhor: Jewish History and Jewish Memory. Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1982. GADAMERAND THE TEACHING OF TEXTS 35 Downloaded By: [Brandeis University] At: 21:19 7 August 2007 Appendix A. Gadamer's Analogy (TM.pp. 358-362) Three types of human relationship: Three types of interpretation: Level 1:1-It Level 1: Text as an It • treats the other person as an object, not as subject • lack ofrespectfortheotherperson's individuality • expects the other person to act in accordance with patterns or laws • goal is to discover typical behavior or to control typical behavior • lack of concern for the specific texts in its particularity • interpretation of text merely as instance of a general pattern or rule • interpreter is detached from text and detached from historical situation • example: some kinds of structuralism • example: social scientific research Level 2:1-Thou (a) Level 2: Text as an Historical Thou • other person is treated as a full subject • genuine desire to understand the person • but: no real listening; no connection to person; onesided conversation • claim of complete understanding of the other; robs claims of legitimacy • example: doctor-patient relationship • text has significance of its own • text is understood as making a claim, but not one that is relevant to the interpreter • text is explained by recourse to historical circumstances, rather having truth claims listened to (and evaluated) Level 3:1-Thou (b) Level 3: Text as Partner in Dialogue • • • • • unavoidable prior assumptions drawn from the tradition and historical situation • but: openness to the possibility that those assumptions will be undermined by the text's claims • Gadamer's label: "historically effected consciousness" acknowledges individuality of other openness to the possibility of hearing something new commitment to the process of dialogue result is (potentially) transformation into something new • ideal interpretation is product of elimination of all subjective bias • example: historicism