Law, ethics and medicine The case for re-thinking incest laws C Farrelly ABSTRACT The recent case of German siblings Patrick Stübing (age 30 years) and his sister Susan Karolewski (age 22 years) has reignited debate over the criminalisation of sexual intercourse among consanguine descendants. The primary justification for criminalising incest is the purported increased risk of genetic disabilities among offspring, but is criminalising sexual intercourse an empirically sound and proportionate response to this increased risk? To answer this question we must consider the specifics of the harm in question (eg, is it a harm to the child or a societal harm) and the magnitude of the harms of the intervention. The example of incest law has important implications for liberal societies. If we can justify imprisoning consenting adults for choosing partners who will increase the risk of having children with disabilities, then we set a troubling precedent for all couples who may pass on genetic disorders to their children. Imagine the following scenario: Patrick and Susan are consenting adults who are in love with each other. They decide to start a family. However, recent advances in our understanding of human genetics give us reason to believe that this particular couple will have an increased risk of having a child with a disease or disability. For example, if Patrick has been diagnosed with Huntington’s disease, a late-onset neurological disorder, then there is a 50% chance that any child he fathers would also be born with this disorder. Alternatively, if Patrick and Susan are both carriers of the cystic fibrosis gene then there is a 25% chance that any child they have will be born with cystic fibrosis, a genetic disorder that can reduce life expectancy by more than 50%. Suppose now that law-makers decided that the increased risk of disease in this case was intolerable. So intolerable that the government has threatened to imprison Patrick and Susan if they are together. The justification given for such a stringent, intrusive intervention is that the government wants to reduce the likelihood of children being born with genetic abnormalities. How would we react to this kind of scenario? The case of Patrick and Susan is not a fictional one, nor is the example of the intrusive state intervention I mentioned something taken from the history books of past eugenic policies. In the real life case of Patrick and Susan neither carries the gene for Huntington’s disease or cystic fibrosis, but their offspring do face an increased risk of disability and this risk stems from the fact that Patrick and Susan are siblings. Incest has long been a social taboo in many parts of the world. The recent case of German siblings Patrick Stübing (age 30 years) and his sister Susan Karolewski (age 22 years) has reignited debate over the criminalisation of sexual intercourse among consanguine descendants. The couple have four children and Patrick Stübing has already spent 2 years in prison. On 13 March 2008 Germany’s constitutional court rejected Patrick Stübing’s request that section 173 of Germany’s Criminal Code be invalidated. This section of the Criminal Code covers ‘‘sexual intercourse between relatives’’ and section 1 states, ‘‘whoever completes an act of sexual intercourse with a consanguine descendant shall be punished with imprisonment for not more than three years or a fine’’. The primary justification for criminalising incest is the purported increased risk of genetic disabilities among offspring, but is criminalising sexual intercourse an empirically sound and proportionate response to this increased risk? To answer this question we must consider the specifics of the harm in question (eg, is it a harm to the child or a societal harm) and the magnitude of the harms of the intervention. With respect to the harm of incest (when the sexual relations occur among consenting adults), the most commonly identified harm is the increased risk of genetic disabilities among offspring. It is important, however, to distinguish between the purported harm to the children themselves and the purported harm that a population could experience from a decline in genetic diversity brought about by inbreeding en masse. Neither of these purported harms justify the intrusive and severe punishment that section 173 of the German Criminal Code sanctions. Indeed, incest laws are best viewed as a legacy of the illinformed and unfair eugenic practices of the past, and to reaffirm the validity of such laws is particularly dangerous given the advances that are being made with respect to genetic testing for disease and disability. Whatever one might say about the harms of incest, it cannot be said to harm the children that are born from an incestuous relationship. This is so because the only alternative for these children would have been non-existence. Assuming the disability in question is not so severe that these children would not have a life worth living, we cannot say that their parents’ actions have harmed them in some way. For their parent’s actions result in their existing in the first place. The other obvious harm to consider is the ‘‘third party’’ societal harm that could result from permitting inbreeding. Widespread practices of inbreeding could threaten genetic diversity and thus lead to an increase in genetic disease and abnormalities, which could in turn place significant pressures on scarce medical resources. In order to make this case it would have to be true that genetic diversity would be under serious threat if incest J Med Ethics 2008;34:e11 (http://jme.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/34/9/e11). doi:10.1136/jme.2008.025346 1 of 2 Queen’s University, Kingston, Canada Correspondence to: Dr C Farrelly, University of Waterloo, 200 University Avenue West, Waterloo, Canada N2L 3G1; farrelly@queensu.ca Received 25 March 2008 Revised 25 March 2008 Accepted 16 May 2008 Law, ethics and medicine was de-criminalised, and there is no credible empirical basis for believing this to be the case. France and Sweden, for example, do not have laws against incest and yet neither society has been plagued by mass inbreeding. This suggests that less intrusive measures (eg, social disapproval, education, genetic counselling, etc) can be effective in terms of minimising the likelihood of inbreeding. The government should only pursue the most intrusive violations of reproductive freedom in those cases in which less restrictive measures are ineffective at promoting a very pressing and substantial aim, but incest laws are not necessary to protect genetic diversity. The danger with lowering the threshold for rational connection in this instance is that whatever one takes that threshold to be, the same standards could be used for other reproductive choices, such as parents 2 of 2 who are at risk of passing on a genetic disease or disorder through sexual intercourse with someone who is not a family member. The example of incest law has important implications for liberal societies, for the stakes go much further than our disapproval of incest. Such laws also set a precedent for our attitudes concerning the scope and limitations of reproductive freedom. If we can justify imprisoning consenting adults for choosing partners who will increase the risk of having children with disabilities, then we set a troubling precedent for all couples who may pass on genetic disorders to their children. Competing interests: None. J Med Ethics 2008;34:e11 (http://jme.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/34/9/e11). doi:10.1136/jme.2008.025346