EPILOGUE Skepticism versus fallibilism for achieving reliable science and wise policy decisions Victor R. Baker The many chapters in this volume summarize what glaciers are telling us about how Earth’s climate is changing. To use a very simple analogy, the observed changes in Earth’s glaciers are functioning in the same manner that small caged birds functioned when carried by coal miners into their dangerous underground workplaces. The observed distress of the birds provided a message, if it was properly understood, that indicated phenomena that could cause problems for the miners. In contrast to the mining example, however, the message provided by Earth’s glaciers is complex, and, as documented in this book, it needs to be understood scientifically in terms of the many interacting controls on glacier advances and retreats. Nature is not obligated to be simple. The climate models that are commonly used to simulate the effects of anthropogenic carbon dioxide on climate warming provide simplified mathematical statements about climate change, essentially presenting pronouncements about what is happening to the climate and how its changes might continue into the future. By contrast, however, the many observations summarized in this volume on the global changes of glaciers present nature’s realities for phenomena that are very closely related to climate. In essence, and unlike the models that present what is being said about Earth’s changing climate, the glacier observations reported in this book are providing Earth’s own statements about what is hap- pening. In this case the science is all about reading and interpreting those statements. As pointed out in the Prologue, the history of glaciological theory development illustrates how reliable knowledge has been developed for understanding both glaciology and climate change, even though there has always been (and always will be) uncertainty about many of the specific details. Though dedicated scientists can never be absolutely certain about any specific predictions in the science of global climate change, that reality should not lead to distrust of the generally reliable positions developed by the long and distinguished history of glaciological scientific inquiry. And, of course, the reality of anthropogenic climate change, the global pattern of glacial mass balance changes, etc., are all very timely examples of such reliable (though not infallible) knowledge. Unfortunately climate change is one of many polarizing issues in modern political discourse, and it is even proving to be a decisive factor for some elections. The most recent example is the Australian election of September 6, 2013, in which the conservative politician Tony Abbott replaced, as Prime Minister, the Labor Party leader, Kevin Rudd. According to an opinion piece in the September 8 Wall Street Journal (Switzer 2013), a key to the Australian election was Mr. Abbott being, ‘‘. . . sceptical about alarmist claims of man-made global warming.’’ In further comments Switzer 842 Epilogue (2013) observes that prior to the election, ‘‘. . . the global warming debate had been conducted in a heretic-hunting and illiberal environment. It was deemed blasphemy for anyone to dare question not only the climate science but the policy consensus to decarbonize the economy.’’ As of this writing the climate change debate among political factions is about to become even more heated. Even some who admit to the realities of global warming are invoking skepticism in regard to the scientific consensus about the magnitude and consequences of that warming. The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) published the first of three volumes of the Fifth Assessment Report on September 27, 2013, and its conclusions are already fueling new debate. Writing in the September 13 Wall Street Journal, Matt Ridley (2013) observes that the new report, ‘‘. . . dials back the alarm. It states that the temperature rise we can expect as a result of man-made emissions of carbon dioxide is lower than the IPCC thought in 2007.’’ Ridley emphasizes that the new result is significant, ‘‘. . . because it points to the very real possibility that, over the next several generations, the overall effect of climate change will be positive for humankind on the planet.’’ He continues that the new estimate of warming, ‘‘. . . most of which is predicted to happen in cold areas in winter and at night, would extend the range of farming further north, improve crop yields, slighty increase rainfall (especially in arid areas), enhance forest growth and cut winter deaths (which far exceed summer deaths in most places).’’ Science and politics make for an uneasy mix. Politicians know that electoral success derives from the ability to convince voters of the truth and certainty of political positions. At least in the U.S. politicians are mainly trained in the methods of lawyers, who tend to think of cases in the abstract, with one set of arguments marshaled against an alternative set of arguments. The most efficient and readily understandable means for doing this is not to consider the complexity of multiple working hypotheses, acknowledging the real-world uncertainties associated with each. Rather, it is to cite the absolute authority of scientific certainty as a basis for action. This means that those opposed to the proposed action will seek all possible means for undermining that authority. In the resulting political debate science comes to be viewed either as a source of authority and certainty or as a reasoning process that requires absolute skepticism to counter the dogmatic appeal to authority. Both viewpoints badly misrepresent science, and both rely upon public ignorance in regard to the misrepresentation, as well as a lack of guidance by the scientific community making it clear that both dogmatic authority and skepticism are inherently anti-scientific. Let us first consider the problem of dogmatism. Though the politician considers scientific consensus on an issue to be the authoritative basis for taking public action, and dogmatically equates that consensus to factual truth, such an attitude does not sit well with the instincts of true scientists. Albert Einstein, for example, famously observed that he had questioned authority throughout his scientific career, and that in later life he was punished for this by being made an authority. The need by politicians to argue from authority is associated with demands by the public and political sectors for certainty, or at least for reduced uncertainty in regard to potential actions, neither of which is consistent with the nature of science (Pollach 2003). These related demands seem to arise from the false definition that holds science to be a body of absolute facts and truths about the natural world, which is a most unfortunate misrepresentation of science. Science is above all an activity and an attitude, held by a community of like-minded investigators, who are passionately driven by their desire to uncover the truths of nature. In order to pursue this inquiry into nature it is actually necessary to have uncertainty, not to suppress it. How could one possibly do science, as just defined, if its subject matter consisted of facts and absolute truths? There would be nothing to pursue. Science is a living, dynamic process of inquiry, not a dead collection of presumed factual truths. Scientific inquiry is open ended. Questions (hypotheses) are pursued to generate understanding that makes for more and more reliable knowledge. Science should not be confused with engineering, which employs many of the same kinds of models as those used in science. Engineering is the application of current understanding, not the discovery of new truths about nature. Engineering seeks reduced uncertainties in order to produce solutions to problems, but those solutions are severely limited by available time and resources. Moreover, they apply to very limited circumstances, and they can be totally invalidated because of unknown factors or changing conditions relative to the assumptions that are necessary for generating the proposed solutions. Because science seeks to discover previously unknown factors by concentrating on the Epilogue 843 uncertainties, it provides a necessary complement to engineering. The basic definition of science outlined above is not the one perceived by much of the general public, and it certainly is not the one that politicians find useful when they cite science as authority for their proposed actions. Thus, the important issue for the public perception of science is not so much the widely bemoaned lack of public understanding of scientific ‘‘facts’’ (what is commonly termed the ‘‘scientific literacy’’ issue). Instead, the critical issue is a lack of public understanding of how science works as a process of inquiry. Science literacy problems involving factual knowledge are real, of course, but this is a red herring in the debates over climate change, because, barring a true and longterm revolution in our education system, there will always be a lack of public understanding of scientific facts. The big problem with scientific facts is that they are being manipulated by the so-called ‘‘climate skeptics’’. As with all such manipulations, arguing over uncertainties relating to authoritative pronouncements about the appearances of nature is exactly the game that the manipulators want to play. There is a sense in which the emphasis on climate models in the political debate over global warming provides an ideal opportunity for misrepresentation. The model predictions convey a sense of certainty that fits the need for justifying action on the basis of authority. However, scientists know well that the predictions from their climate models are not authoritative truths, but are instead tools for generating understanding. Models cannot act as the unerring oracles for prophesy in regard to future events that politicians wish to claim as authoritative bases for action (Sarewitz et al. 2000). Trying to use models in this way is precluded by severe limitations of logic and practical realities (Oreskes et al. 1994, Pilkey and Pilkey-Jarvis 2007). Models are most appropriately viewed as making predictions only in the logical sense, such that, if certain premises are held, various outcomes will necessarily follow. The goal of science is to learn from nature about the realities that such logical predictions seek to represent, and then to apply the results to yield the greater understanding that will improve the premises for revised models. The second misrepresentation of science in modern political discourse is more nuanced than that of dogmatism. Indeed, skepticism is actually argued by some philosophers to be necessary as a part of doing science. This view arises from a long tradition in philosophical discourse and the associated rhetorical argumentation that juxtapositions dogmatism versus skepticism. The argument from authority relies upon the view that we can know some things with absolute certainty (e.g., scientific ‘‘facts’’). In contrast, the argument from skepticism begins by disputing claims to absolute certainty, commonly by demonstrating that there are specific dogmatic claims about which certainty can be disproven. Then, the skeptic takes this common-sense observation one step further by holding that the lack of certainty about specific beliefs leads to the conclusion that many or all of the related, more general beliefs should be dismissed or severely discounted as untrustworthy. Note how this type of skepticism fits with the goal of denying anthropogenic climate change based on the lack of certainty about various details in model formulations or observations of the natural world. There will always be uncertainty about various details, so, as long as one buys into the logic of skepticism, the climate skeptic will always win the argument. But should our uncertain knowledge really make us into skeptics? The question is important because some philosophers and even many scientists claim that, like open-mindedness, skepticism needs to be an attitude cultivated for the doing of science. The critics of global warming rely upon this perception to act as though a skeptical attitude is the appropriate one to hold in being scientific (e.g., Lumborg 2001). Many scientists, including the late Carl Sagan (1997), one of the greatest science communicators of the modern era, advocate skepticism as a means of countering dubious claims by individuals that purport to be ‘‘scientific’’ but instead are actually pseudoscience. Note the paradox here. The global warming critics are invoking skepticism in their questioning of the scientific consensus that has been achieved about global warming (Oreskes and Conway 2010), but some mainstream scientists would invoke skepticism as the means to question dubious claims made by the global warming skeptics that purport to be scientific. Skepticism per se does not seem to be an effective means for distinguishing valid from invalid science, at least to a degree that would be readily apparent to the general public and their political representatives. There is an alternative to this dogmatism/ skepticism dichotomy, which is to consider the attitudes and reasoning processes of the claimants, as opposed to the uncertain truths of the claims. It is a sad commentary that there are those claiming to 844 Epilogue speak for science in the global climate change debates for whom the goal of finding out how things really are is not the primary motivation for their inquiry. The logician Susan Haack (2007) terms this kind of reasoning ‘‘fake’’. If authentic science involves a kind of reasoning pursued with the overriding motive of getting to the truth of things, craving to know how things really are, then in fake science the goal is not so much to seek truth as to use the appearances of scientific inquiry to achieve some other end, such as to make lots of money, to advance a cherished ideology, or to gain fame. Moreover, there is a closely related dysfunctional reasoning, recognized more than a century ago by the great American logician and geophysicist, Charles Sanders Peirce. This is ‘‘sham reasoning’’ which Peirce defined as when it is not the reasoning that determines what the conclusion will be, but it is the conclusion that determines what the reasoning will be. Thus, the skeptic, who already believes that global warming is a myth and fraud, may employ sham reasoning to provide a pretense of scientific reasoning toward that predefined conclusion. It was also Charles Sanders Peirce who recognized the scientific attitude that effectively replaces skepticism (see de Waal 2001). While it is true that one should discount dogmatic claims to absolute certainty for various individual beliefs, this does not justify the claim of the skeptic that one should then distrust all the related beliefs. Peirce pointed out that the proper attitude of the scientist is fallibilism, not skepticism. Fallibism holds that one can trust an assemblage of related beliefs that have been shown generally to work in practice, experiment, etc., even though we cannot be absolutely certain about the validity of any one belief in isolation. As was later pointed out by the logician William Van Orman Quine (1951), scientific knowledge works like an interconnected web in which some aspects near the core of the web, like rules of logic or basic laws of physics, are so trustworthy that it would be an immense waste of time to question them. In essence, science operates at the outer edges of the interconnected web of generally reliable beliefs, always working toward a more reliable total structure that is continually being refined. Science is not about developing and conveying knowledge that is absolutely certain in all its details. Arguing about the certainty of those details is an invitation to engage in the skeptical games employed by the practitioners of fake reasoning. Instead, science is about the continual achieving of knowledge that becomes more and more ‘‘reliable’’, a term applied to science by Ziman (1978). In a lecture delivered on August 19, 1872, the brilliant English mathematician polymath William Kingdon Clifford observed, ‘‘Remember that [scientific thought] is the guide to action; and that the truth which it arrives at is not that which we can ideally contemplate without error, but that which we may act upon without fear; and you cannot fail to see that scientific thought is not an accompaniment or condition of human progress, but human progress itself ’’ (Stephen and Polloch 1901, p. 109). What the glaciers are telling us, as reliably reported in this volume, should definitely be considered to be a source of guidance for future policy decisions. But the interpretations made of the messages from the glaciers are not absolute truths. They are something upon which we can reliably act, but the basis for that action is not some static and unchanging factual truth. Rather, the basis, as stated by Clifford, is the dynamic process of scientific thought itself, pursued by investigators like this volume’s chapter authors, who are totally dedicated to continuing to improve upon understanding the realities of what is actually happening. Recognition of these realities and effective communication of the same to the public is much more likely to promote belief than are dogmatic pronouncements as to what the future will be. There may be minor uncertainties in some of the details, but this does not justify wholesale skepticism. Neither the sham nor fake reasoning invoked to question the authentic progression of scientific reasoning can provide a basis for action. Though the only certainty is that science will always be fallible, its continuing and authentic pursuit assures that it will be the most reliable guide to action that humankind has ever devised. REFERENCES de Waal, C. (2001) On Peirce, Wordsworth, Belmont, CA. Haack, S. (2007) Defending Science—Within Reason: Between Scientism and Cynicism, Prometheus Books, Buffalo, NY. Lumborg, B. (2001) The Skeptical Environmentalist, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K. Oreskes, N., and Conway, E.M. (2010) Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming, Bloomsbury Press, New York. Epilogue 845 Oreskes, N., Schrader-Frechette, K., and Belitz, K. (1994) Verification, validation and confirmation of numerical models in the earth sciences. Science, 263, 641–646. Pilkey, O.H., and Pilkey-Jarvis, L. (2007) Useless Arithmetic: Why Environmental Scientists Can’t Predict the Future, Columbia University Press, New York, 230 pp. Pollach, H.N. (2003) Uncertain Science . . . Uncertain World, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K. Quine, W.V.O. (1951) Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43. Ridley, M. (2013) Dialing back the alarm on climate change. Wall Street Journal, September 13, 2013. Sagan, C. (1997) Billions and Billions: Thoughts on Life and Death at the Brink of the Millennium, Random House, New York. Sarewitz, D., Pielke, R.A., Jr., and Byerly, R., Jr. (Eds.) (2000) Prediction: Science, Decision Making, and the Future of Nature, Island Press, Washington, D.C. Stephen, L., and Polloch, F. (Eds.) (1901) Lectures and Essays, by the Late William Kingdon Clifford, Macmillan, London. Switzer, T. (2013) The triumph of Tony Abbott. Wall Street Journal, September 8, 2013. Ziman, J. (1978) Reliable Knowledge: An Exploration for the Grounds for Belief in Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K.