Chapter X Chaos as a Bridge between Determinism and Probability in Quantum Mechanics Wm. C. McHarris Departments of Chemistry and Physics/Astronomy Michigan State University mcharris@cem.msu.edu X.1 Introduction Quantum mechanics is fundamentally a probabilistic science, whereas classical mechanics is deterministic. This dichotomy has led to numerous disputes and confusion, ranging from the Einstein-Bohr debates of the 1930’s [Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen 1935; Bohr 1935], through attempts to establish determinism in quantum mechanics by means of introducing “hidden variables” [de Broglie 1960, 1964; Bohm 1952], to lengthy discussions of epistemological versus ontological interpretations of quantum mechanics [Bohm and Hiley 1993]. Throughout most of the twentieth century the Copenhagen interpretation of Bohr and Heisenberg has endured as the orthodox interpretation, replete with contradictions and paradoxes such as duality, the necessity for an observer before a quantum system can attain physical meaning, and the reduction of the wave function upon observation. The reductio ad absurdum of such paradoxes was the example of Schrödinger’s cat [Schrödinger 1936; Gribben 1984,1995], in which a cat inside a closed chamber remained in limbo as a linear superposition of dead cat + live cat until an observer determined whether or not a radioactive nucleus had decayed, releasing a deadly poison. During the last several decades, nonlinear dynamics and chaos theory have become well-enough developed that they can be used to intercede in some of these seeming paradoxes of quantum mechanics. Since chaotic systems are fundamentally deterministic, yet have to be treated statistically, it is worth investigating as to whether chaos can form a bridge between the determinism of classical mechanics and the probabilistic aspects of quantum mechanics. Perhaps both Einstein and Bohr could 2 Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics have been correct in their interpretations: At heart chaos theory provides the determinism so dear to Einstein; yet for most practical purposes it reduces to the probabilities of the Copenhagen interpretation. Interestingly enough, although authors of the earlier (not altogether successful) attempts to impose determinism on quantum mechanics did not have access to modern chaos theory, in many ways they toyed with ideas that we now can see as arising naturally in chaotic systems. More recently, nonlinear extensions to quantum mechanics have been promulgated by a number of authors [Weinberg 1989; Gisin 1989, 1990; Mielnik 2001; Czachor and Doebner 2002]. Again, their efforts have been but partially successful, sometimes introducing superluminal (nonphysical) signals into multi-particle correlations. Mielnik sums up their thinking, “…perhaps, it resists embedding into too narrow a scheme…the nonlinear theory would be in a peculiar situation of an Orwellian ‘thoughtcrime’ confined to a language in which it cannot even be expressed…A way out, perhaps, could be a careful revision of all traditional concepts…” Their efforts centered around corrections and perturbations applied to traditional, linear quantum mechanics — and in such weakly nonlinear systems chaotic behavior cannot develop! From a different perspective, viz., a consideration of the possibility that nonlinearities can arise at the Planck length (10–33 m), has come the recent work of t’Hooft [2003] and Krasnoholovets [2003]. However, this is more concerned with reconciling quantum mechanics with relativity than in dealing with the (more simplistic?) imponderables encountered with the Copenhagen interpretation. Perhaps the time is ripe to inquire into the possibility that chaos and nonlinear dynamics could be an inherent component of quantum mechanics — only heretofore not recognized as such. In a series of papers [McHarris 2001, 2003, 2004] I have cautiously put forth the idea that certain imponderables — or paradoxes — encountered with the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics might have parallel explanations in terms of nonlinear dynamics. This is not to be construed as any sort of proof of the existence of chaos underlying quantum mechanics — indeed, just as quantum mechanics itself cannot be derived, but only postulated, such a proof cannot be forthcoming. And these ideas are still at the “from the bottom up,” even “quasiexperimental” stage: Examples must be collected and analyzed before any broad formulations can even be considered. Nevertheless, the very existence of such parallel examples makes raising the question(s) worthwhile. Even if eventually it becomes accepted that quantum mechanics can contain deterministic, if nonlinear components, for the most part this will have relatively little effect on the day-to-day use of quantum mechanics. This results from the fact that most scientists use it simply as the superb procedure — or computer formulation — that it is and care little about the quandaries associated with its foundations. And they would be trading one set of difficult mathematics for an equally messy set of nonlinear numerologies. The primary exception to this that I foresee lies in the field of quantum information and computing, the very field that has helped so much to reinitiate interest in reexamining the foundations of quantum mechanics. For the possibility of massively parallel quantum computing rests firmly on the principle of linear superposition of states, which can be manipulated simultaneously but independently. In a quantum mechanics containing nonlinear elements, this basis might have to be reexamined. Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics 3 X.2 Quantum Mechanical Imponderables with Nonlinear Parallels At least seven so-called imponderables or paradoxes associated with the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics have analogous nonlinear interpretations that logically are quite compelling. Some of these have been investigated much more thoroughly than others. They are summarized here in decreasing order of effort spent in trying to fathom them. X.2.1 The Exponential Decay Law and the Escape Group from Unimodal Maps Radioactive decay and atomic and molecular transitions — indeed, all first-order processes, including first-order chemical reactions — follow exponential decay laws, exhibiting time-independent half-lives. These are often justified by analogy with actuarial tables, such as those used by the life insurance industry. Although it is difficult, if not impossible, to determine when an individual will die, given a sufficiently large sample, the statistical predictions become quite precise, allowing insurance companies assured profits. By analogy, it is impossible to predict when, say, a given radioactive nucleus will disintegrate; however, given a large enough sample of nuclei, a statistical exponential decay law is followed very precisely. Upon further consideration, such an analogy should not hold up. Actuarial tables are based on complexity: There are large numbers of different people having widely diverse causes of mortality. On the other hand, one of the fundamental premises of quantum mechanics is that identical particles are truly identical and interchangeable; thus, completely different statistics should apply. A nonlinear parallel can be found in the iteration of unimodel maps in their chaotic regimes, where extreme sensitivity to initial conditions applies. Consistent with (but not dependent on) the Uncertainty Principle, an initial, say, radioactive nuclear state, having a finite width, can be likened to a tiny interval in initial input values. Different individual nuclei in this state can then be represented by random initial values selected within this interval. The final nuclear state can similarly be represented by a second interval, corresponding to possible final values. And the decay dynamics — a transition probability is at least quadratic in nature — can be considered analogous to iterating the map. One keeps a record of the number of initial states remaining, i.e., the number that have not escaped into the final state, after each iteration. A plot of this remaining number against the number of iterations yields an exponential decay curve. This analog is treated in considerable detail in [McHarris 2003], where both the quadratic and sine maps are considered. Tens of thousands of randomly-generated initial states within intervals typically having widths of 10 –11 were followed, and this procedure consistently generated exponential decay curves. The process of iteration can be justified physically if one makes a correspondence with a physical process such as the number of oscillations of, say, a nuclear dipole or the number of attempts of an particle at barrier penetration. Unfortunately, because of the “universality” of chaos, it is difficult to make further mechanistic predictions, and any sort of time series analysis is unlikely to retain significant correlations because of the enormous difference between the laboratory and nuclear times scales. (Nevertheless, because of the relative ease with which time-delay experiments could be performed with radioac- 4 Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics tive species, such experiments should be performed on the off chance that some faint remnant of an attractor could be perceived.) X.2.2. Bell’s Theorem and Nonextensive Entropy The EPR paradox [Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen 1935] was designed to demonstrate that quantum mechanics was incomplete ; it involved correlations between separated particles (Einstein’s “spooky action at a distance”), but it was cast in the form of an abstract Gedankenexperiment. Bohm [Bohm 1951] made the EPR more specific and less astract by considering a pair of spin-1/2 fermions, but it was Bell [Bell 1964] who reanalyzed it into something that touched upon physical reality. There have been various refinements and variants on Bell’s inequality, but perhaps the simplest — designed to be experimentally friendly — is the CHSH inequality [Clauser, Horne, Shimony, and Holt 1969], which is used as the illustration here. (Also, cf. [McHarris 2004]). Consider the following correlation experiments on pairs of particles, using the standard information theory cartoon characters, Alice and Bob, who are stationed at an effectively infinite (incommunicado) distance apart. Pairs of particles having binary properties, e.g., spin up vs spin down or perhaps horizontal vs vertical polarization, are prepared, then one particle from each pair is sent to Alice and the other to Bob. Examples of such pairs could be two electrons or two photons. Alice can make measurements Q or R on each of her particles, each measurement having a possible outcome of +1 or –1. For example, Q could be a measurement of spin with respect to a vertical axis, while R would be with respect to an oblique axis. Similarly, Bob can make measurement S or T on each of his particles. Alice and Bob each choose which measurement to make at random, often waiting until the particles are already on their way in flight, thus assuring no communication between them or with the originator of the particles. After making many pairs of measurements in order to attain statistical significance, the two get together to compare notes. The quantity of interest based on their measurements is QS RS RT QT (Q R)S (R Q)T. (1) Note the single minus sign — because Q and R independently can have the values +1 or 1, one of the terms on the right side of the equation must be 0. Either way, QS RS RT QT 2, (2) or in terms of probabilities, where E(QS), for example, is the mean value of the measurements for the combination QS, we come up with the CHSH inequality, E(QS) E(RS) E(RT) E(QT) 2. (3) This so-called “classical” derivation of a specific variant of Bell’s inequality places an upper limit on the statistical correlations for a specific combination of products obtained by presumably independent (and randomly chosen) measurements. 5 Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics The quantum mechanical version is obtained by starting off with the pairs of particles in the entangled Bell singlet state, ( 01 10 ) / 2. (4) The first qubit from each ket is sent to Alice, the second from each ket to Bob. Measurements are carried out as before, but on the following combinations of observables: (Z 2 X 2 ) (Z X 2 ) Q Z1, R X1, S , T 2 2 2 (5) Here X and Z are the “bit flip” and “phase flip” quantum information matrices, corresponding to the Pauli 1 and 3 spin matrices. It can be shown that the expectation values of the pairs QS, RS, and RT are all +1/2, while that of QT is 1/2. This leads to the quantum mechanical analogy to the CHSH inequality, QS RS RT QT 2 2. (6) Thus, quantum mechanics, within the framework of entangled states, predicts a possibly larger statistical correlation than was allowed by the so-called classical inequality. Bell’s theorem predicts that classical systems will obey such inequalities, while quantum systems might violate them under the right circumstances. During the last several decades, several dozen “Bell-type” experiments have been performed [Bertlmann and Zeilinger 2003], and they have consistently violated the inequalities. Quantum mechanics wins, classical mechanics loses! As with most ideas connected with quantum mechanics, interpretations vary — but most interpretations involve the elimination of “local reality.” Two isolated, far-apart but entangled particles have some sort of influence on each other. A down-to-earth experimental example of this might be the following: Two electrons are emitted in a spin-singlet state. Their individual spin directions are unknown (undefined according to the Copenhagen interpretation), but they must be opposite. When Alice arbitrarily measures the direction of her electron, say, with respect to a z axis and gets , this information is instantaneously conveyed to Bob’s electron, whose wave function reduces to with respect to this same axis. Einstein’s “spooky” — and superluminal — action at a distance is real! But wait a minute. Is this really a contest between quantum vs. classical mechnics, or is it between correlated vs. uncorrelated statistics. In the so-called classical derivation, the particles were presumably prepared in correlated pairs, but these correlations were then tacitly ignored, while the quantum mechanical entangled pairs necessarily retained the highest correlations. And correlated statistics are known to exist in nonlinear systems: The codification of correlated statistics was introduced by Tsallis and his coworkers [Tsallis 1988, Curado and Tsallis 1991], when they formulated so-called “nonextensive” (meaning nonadditive) thermodynamics. Correlations in classical systems result in a generalized entropy, Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics 6 W Sq (1 piq ) /(q 1). (7) i1 Here the phase space has been divided into W cells of equal measure, with pi the probability of being in cell i. For the exponent q (termed the “entropic index”) having a value of 1, the generalized entropy reduces to the standard Boltzmann entropy, W S1 pi ln pi . (8) i1 As q varies from 1, the deviation from standard distributions becomes greater, with “long-range” correlations becoming greater. When such correlations are present, the entropy becomes nonextensive, and the entropy of the total system becomes Sq (A B) k Sq (A) k Sq (B) k (1 q) Sq (A)Sq (B) k2 . (9) When q < 1, the entropy of the combined system is greater (superextensive) than the sum of its parts, and when q > 1, it is less (subextensive) than the sum of its parts. This concept has found widespread applications in classical systems, ranging from winds velocity distributions in tornadoes to the energy distributions of cosmic rays [i.a., Gell-Mann and Tsallis 2004]. What is pertinent is that systems “at the edge of quantum chaos” have recently been studied [Weinstein, Tsallis, and Lloyd 2004], and both for the quantum kicked top and for the logistic map [Baldovin and Robledo 2002; Borges et al. 2002] values of q > 1 could be applied. [One has to be careful here with quantitative interpretations because these values were derived within the context of standard (linear) quantum mechanics with “quantum chaos”; however, the crossover into classical chaos is similar, and it seems that both systems exhibit long-range correlations.] For the logistic equation these groups found that a value of q 2 seemed reasonable. From the above it seems rather clear that nonlinear classical systems can indeed exhibit correlations in which “long-range” correlations play an important role. (This does not necessarily mean long-range forces or “action at a distance,” as has been known for a long time from the behavior of cellular automata and self-evolving systems.) Thus, the “classical” derivation of the CHSH inequality — and most if not all of the other guises that Bell’s inequality takes on — is suspect. Classical systems can easily involve correlated statistics, which raises the apparent upper limit of inequalities such as Eqn. (3). With a value of q in the vicinity of 2, one could easily obtain something closer to an exponential rather than a Gaussian distribution. In other words, Bell’s inequality is moot in ruling out the existence of local reality in quantum mechanics. Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics 7 X.2.3 Other Possible Nonlinear Parallels with Quantum Mechanics Other parallels between nonlinear dynamics and quantum mechanics should also be considered. These have been less extensively investigated, so are only listed here as a prod to one’s imagination. •Attractors and innate quantization. Nonlinear systems have preferred modes of oscillation, independent of boundary conditions or external influence. Many deterministic but nonlinear classical systems obey eigenvalue equations, i.e., they are quantized innately without having to invoke such artifices as wave interference. •Spontaneous symmetry breaking — parity nonconservation. Nonlinear systems can spontaneously break both temporal and spatial symmetry. Odd iterators, for example, exhibit this property. And practical applications include chemical reactions and the separation of powders in nonlinear tumblers [cf. McHarris 2004]. Might this have some bearing on the nonconservation of parity in weak interactions? •Decoherence and the destruction of KAM tori. Decoherence and the reduction of wave functions are among the more intriguing paradoxes associated with the Copenhagen interpretation. The nonlinear alternative would be for an observer to perturb, ever so slightly, a knife-edge equilibrium in a Hamiltonian system, perhaps resulting in its orderly breakdown of KAM tori. This would remove the observer from having to be an integral part of the system. Weinberg [Weinberg 1989] touches on ideas similar to this. •Diffraction — the existence of order in chaos. A possible mode of attack on problems such as the double-slit experiment would be to examine the intricate mixing of windows of order with regions of chaos in many chaotic regimes. Windows of order would correspond to “constructive interference,” whereas chaos would correspond to “destructive interference.” It is well known that two first-order differential equations can be combined to produce a single second-order equation. Thus, two identical slits could possibly lead to chaotic behavior, but closing one slit (or doing anything else to remove one of the equations) would do away with the possibility of chaos. •Barrier penetration. Again, many nonlinear systems exhibit a type of barrier penetration, e.g., water waves crossing a barrier. Chap. 7 of [Hey & Walters 2003] gives an intriguing overview of this field, which might have deeper implications for quantum mechanics than they realized. X.3. Conclusion This paper is intended more to be thought provoking than to proclaim definite conclusions. Nevertheless, I hope to have raised serious questions about our current, orthodox thinking about quantum mechanics. Two of the paradoxes of quantum mechanics have been shown to have reasonably quantitative alternative explanations in nonlinear, possibly chaotic dynamics, while five others simply raise reasonable speculations. Chaos applies to almost every other discipline in nature, so why is quantum mechanics exempt from nature’s preferred feedback and nonlinearities? Perhaps, as Mielnik suggested, we have unconsciously been using a scientific linear “newspeak,” which has prevented us from expressing any nonlinear “thoughtcrimes.” The consequences of nonlinearities and determinism underlying quantum mechanics should shock us, 8 Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics but then it should make us think again — and investigate the situation without wearing (linear) blinders. After all, perhaps Einstein and Bohr were both right — but couldn’t realize it at the time. References Baldovin, F., & Robledo, A., 2002, Phys. Rev. E, 66, 045104(R). Bell, J.S., 1964, Physics, 1, 195; reprinted in Bell, J.S., 1993, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, Cambridge Univ. Press (Cambridge). Bertlmann, R.A., & Zeilinger, A., Eds., 2003, Quantum [Un]Speakables, Springer Verlag (Berlin). Bohm, D., 1951, Quantum Theory, Chap. 22, Prentice-Hall (Englewood Cliffs, NJ). —, 1952, Phys. Rev., 85, 166; also discussed in Wheeler, J.A., & Zurek, W.H., Bohm, D., & Hiley, B.J., 1993, The Undivided Universe, Routledge (London). Bohr, N., 1935, Phys. Rev., 48, 696. Borges, E.P., Tsallis, C., Añaños, G.F.J., & de Oliveira, P.M., 2002, Phys. Rev. Lett., 89, 254103. Clauser, J., Horne, M.A., Shimony, A., & Holt, R., 1969, Phys. Rev. Lett., 23, 880. Curado, E.M.F., & Tsallis, C., 1991, J. Phys. A, 24, L69. Czachor, M., & Doebner, H.-D., 2002, Phys. Lett., A301, 139. De Broglie, L., 1960, Non-Linear Wave Mechanics: A Causal Interpretation, Elsevier (Amsterdam). De Broglie, L. 1964, The Current Interpretation of Wave Mechanics: A Critical Study, Elsevier (Amsterdam). Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N., 1935, Phys. Rev., 47, 777. Gell-Mann, M., & Tsallis, C., 2004, Nonextensive Entropy — Interdisciplinary Applications, Oxford Univ. Press (Oxford). Gisin, N., 1989, Helv. Phys. Acta, 62, 363. —, 1990, Phys. Lett., A143, 1. Gribben, J., 1984, In Search of Schrödinger’s Cat, Bantam (New York). —, 1995, Schrödinger’s Kittens and the Search for Reality, Little, Brown (Boston). Hey, T., & Walters, P., 2003, The New Quantum Universe, Cambridge Univ. Press (Cambridge). Krasnoholovets, V., 2003, “Deterministic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics,” www.inerton.kiev.ua. McHarris, Wm.C., 2001, Z. Naturforsch., a56, 208. —, 2003, J. Opt. B. Quantum and Semiclass. Opt., 5, S442. —, 2004, “On the Possibility of Nonlinearities and Chaos Underlying Quantum Mechanics,” in Progress in Quantum Physics Research, edited by V. Krashnoholovets, Nova Science Publ. (New York). Mielnik, B., 2001, Phys. Lett., A289, 1. Schrödinger, E., 1936, Naturwiss., 23, 807, 823, 844. t’Hooft, G., 2000, “Quantum Mechanics and Determinism at the Planck Scale,” www.phys.uu.nl/quantloss/index.html. Tsallis, C., 1988, J. Stat. Phys., 52, 479. Weinberg, S., 1989, Ann. Phys. (NY), 194, 336. Weinstein, Y.S., Tsallis, C., & Lloyd, S., 2004, in Decoherence and Entropy in Complex Systems, edited by H.-T. Elze, Springer Verlag (Berlin). Chaos and Determinism in Quantum Mechanics 9