Overcoming the Prophecy of Rational-Choice: The Innovations of Sustainable Development and the Limitations of Ecological Modernization Theory Tyler Carlson April 10th, 2013 POL 358 – Political Psychology Environmental policy-making has been historically confronted with many economic, political, and social barriers. Yet the logic used to conceptualize these barriers often carries undertones of rational-choice theory. That is to say, problems of resource consumption are often equated to ‘the tragedy of the commons’, while environmental protection is considered undesirable after being reduced to an economic cost-benefit analysis (Weale, 1992; Carter, 2006). What this suggests is that the nature of environmental problems has been, to some degree, predetermined. Consequently, this seems to attract solutions that follow the same questionable logic, wherein environmental policies have to be justified in an instrumentally rational way in order for actors on any level to take collective action. Ecological modernization (EM) was developed as an environmental policy paradigm with this logic – offering rational-choice solutions that reconcile the ‘economy-ecology’ divide. In contrast to this approach is sustainable development (SD), which presents environmental problems and solutions in a more holistic and innovative light. To illustrate this distinction, and the respective implications that each paradigm has for the environment; this paper will compare the EM and SD literature to reveal which of the two provides a better policy framework in the context of three traditional environmental problems: temporal/spatial variability, public goods, and administrative fragmentation. This analysis will ultimately find sustainable development to provide a superior environmental policy model because it not only escapes from the rational-choice assumptions of EM, but also inspires collective action on a global level. To briefly provide context to these paradigms, sustainable development is widely considered to originate from the 1987 Brundtland Commission, which provided the commonly cited definition of SD as “development that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs (Our Common Future, 1987, p. 34). 2 Both the sustainable development and ecological modernization literature draw insights from this seminal work (Weale, 1992; Mol, 1996; Christoff, 1996; Baker et al. 1997). Among SD theorists, Baker (2006) finds the Brundtland model to have ‘authoritative status’ in the SD literature. Elsewhere, critics challenge the principles of EM and SD, such as Redcliffe (1987) and Shiva (1988), while others divide the two concepts into ‘weak’ and ‘strong’ variants (Baker et al. 1997). Inevitably, there is some degree of conceptual overlap in these paradigms, as not many EM theorists explicitly distance themselves from the Brundtland Report’s approach. However, EM is thought to have its origins slightly before this document, as the works of Joseph Huber and Martin Janicke in the mid-1980s are broadly regarded as the foundation of EM theory (Christoff, 1996; Mol and Sonnenfield, 2000; Langhelle, 2000). Both the former and latter are German sociologists, whereas other subsequent literature in EM emerged among policy analysts in the Netherlands (Hajer, 1995; Mol, 1996), and in the U.K (Weale, 1992). Hence, it is worth noting that EM theory first developed in wealthy, northern European countries with limited domestic environmental concerns, whereas the Brundtland Commission consisted of a diverse, international panel that found interconnections between both poverty alleviation and environmental issues (Christoff, 1996). The influence that these distinct perspectives had on the policy principles of SD and EM will remain in the subtext of the following analysis. Exploring these paradigms and applying them to traditional environmental policy-making barriers provides insight into how their respective policy principles act in practice. Although similar analyses have been conducted in the literature (Pepper 1998; Langhelle, 2000; Brand, 2010), few have explored how reductionist conceptions of the environment based off rationalchoice can be challenged by sustainable development in both principle and practice. Therefore, the aforementioned ‘core environmental policy-making problems’ of temporal/spatial variability, 3 public goods, and administrative fragmentation will be utilised for revealing this confrontation. These three problems made subtle appearances 1987 Brundtland Report; however, they were not theorized and categorized until Weale (1992) and Carter (2006), respectively. The latter defines environmental challenges as being both ‘intrinsic’ and ‘institutional’ in character. With consideration of these useful conceptualizations from past literature, this analysis begins with temporal and spatial divisions. Temporal/spatial variability Temporal factors are centred on the general myopia witnessed in environmental policymaking, whereas spatial variables reflect the geographical disconnect between cause and effect in environmental degradation. In other words, the former explores the variability in willingness of present generations (including governments and citizens) to make sacrifices to protect the environment for future generations, whereas the latter involves the unequal distribution of ecological impacts across the world resulting from environmentally destructive actions that come disproportionately from the Global North. Weale (1992) first illustrates this phenomenon through the example of acid rain falling on Scandinavian countries because of air pollution produced in the United Kingdom. More broadly, Carter (2006) discusses how droughts, floods, desertification and the destruction of biodiversity can be endured by populations who are seldom the sole contributors to such outcomes. He also discusses environmental policies of Northern countries in the 1970’s, which were characterized by end-of-pipe solutions and shortsighted objectives for environmental protection. The question for SD and EM, therefore, is how these policy paradigms attempt to overcome the prioritization of short-term policy agendas and geographically proximate concerns. Moreover, how can these policies reconcile the inequity of resource usage and climate impact across time and space? 4 According to the SD literature, the solution to myopic environmental agendas begins with reframing the concept of the ‘future’. Sustainable development does so by posing ‘multiple futures’ with varying global environmental consequences; however, a sustainable future begins with two guiding principles: intra- and inter-generational equity. In essence, these concepts necessitate that environmental policies reflect the needs of generations of both the present and future as well as the disparities of the Global North and South. Michael Redcliffe, a prominent and early critic in the SD literature, finds these two principles to be the ‘foremost objective’ of sustainable development (Baker et al., 1997). Baker (2006) emphasizes the normative role of these principles, equating them to “moral statements that specify what is good or bad, and mould attitudes and guide behaviour” (p. 36). In effect, SD evokes a moral imperative for not forfeiting the needs of future generations, which is based on tangible connections between poverty, the overexploitation of resources, and climate change. What is also pointed out by Baker (2006) is that the Brundtland Report centers on promoting sustainable development, not achieving it. The logic behind focusing on promotion of this concept is that the desirable characteristics of sustainable development will evolve over time and will vary across borders. Arguably, such a flexible and holistic approach has the potential for broad, international appeal. The appeal of sustainability was first witnessed in the summer of 1992 in Rio de Janeiro, where the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development (WCED) was being held. The Brundtland Report and its normative principles had been the core inspiration for Agenda 21, which was adopted by 172 states. Inevitably, this voluntary, non-binding international agreement has both strengths and weaknesses. It brings together the international community for collective action on sustainable development and disseminates norms of global ecological interdependence (Martin, 2004). However, it remains silent on relevant issues such as 5 international debt and population control. Among the many states who signed Agenda 21 were the Vatican and the Philippines, whose presence prevents any discussion of methods to reduce birth rates such as contraceptives (Baker, 2006). Regardless of its flaws, though, this action plan confronts rational-choice narratives that assume that any intergenerational benefits are outweighed by present, individual costs (Weale, 1992). Put simply, the future externalities of decisions take precedence in policy-making for SD, which is encompassed in the precautionary principle. The main way this diverges from ecological modernization is that literature in EM tends to lack prioritization of ecological issues like climate change, nor does it promote equity across generations. Instead, EM theorists like Weale (1992) posit a revamped cost-benefit analysis to encompass future generations: If the ‘costs’ of environmental protection are avoided the effect is frequently to save money for present generations at the price of an increased burden for future generations. In other words, the costs do not disappear, they are merely pushed forward and possibly magnified in the process. Thus, a failure to regulate industrial waste disposal of agricultural pesticide use in one generation will simply have the effect of creating soil clean-up costs for future generations (p. 76). Of course, this remark does not acknowledge the extent to which these spillover effects have also amplified spatial disparities of current ecological problems. The general neglect among EM theorists regarding the distribution of biodiversity, which is overwhelmingly found in the Global South, is a case in point. Christoff (1996) points out that “the entire literature is somewhat 6 Eurocentric, deeply marked by the experience of local debates over the politics of acid rain and other outputs, rather than conflicts over biodiversity preservation” (p. 486). Mol and Spaargaren (2000) explain this prioritization by the fact that EM initially “developed in a limited number of West European countries,” and that its solutions “still partly mirror this geographical focus” (p. 42). This sheds light on why early EM theorists like Huber and Janicke placed the role of technological innovation at the forefront of the environmental policy-making agenda, as it confronted the industrial burdens of pollution faced by the North, while conveniently ignoring the unequal distribution of ecological problems in the South (Langhelle, 2000). Public goods Related to the international character of environmental problems is the next category, public goods. This concept derives from the fact that many aspects of nature are ‘non-rival’ and ‘non-excludable’. Meaning that one’s consumption of a particular natural resource does not limit another’s ability to do the same (Our Common Future, 1987). In the context of the global commons, it implies that efforts to reduce carbon emissions by one country will benefit other nations, regardless of whether or not they follow suit (Carter, 2006). Therefore, preventing climate change is faced with the quintessential rational-choice problem of ‘free riding’, as there is thought to be no incentive for actors to engage in these activities if they perceive others to be already acting on their behalf. This problem directly relates to ‘the tragedy of the commons,’ in which rationally self-interested actors end up exhausting the carrying capacity of an ecosystem in attempt to maximize individual gains (Weale, 1992). Evidently, this assumes a predetermined cost-benefit analysis that favours the myopic thinking addressed in the previous section. 7 However, the issues of greater pertinence here are the rational-choice assumptions made about consumers and producers who provoke this hypothetical ‘tragedy’ in the first place. There is generally a consensus in the literature that reductions to resource consumption are at the heart of SD. Some go further to say it profoundly confronts the capitalist system (Christoff, 1996). As per Lafferty (2007), “of the numerous issues covered by sustainable development, one of the far most crucial is the nature and level of consumption in the overdeveloped North,” wherein “each American birth represents a level of consumption that is hundreds of times that of each birth in Nepal, Vietnam, or Madagascar ” (p. 47). On the other hand, EM theory, albeit vocal on the problem of consumption, places more emphasis on the type of consumption rather than the level. This rests on the belief that, with the use of more efficient, innovative technologies, the goal of ‘producing more with less’ becomes ecologically feasible (Carter, 2006). That is to say, the consumption of Green products can reduce negative environmental impacts. When contrasted to SD, EM appears reductionist in the fact that ecology is “reduced to concern about resource inputs, waste and pollutant emissions” (Baker, 2006, p. 139). Al Gore, perhaps unknowingly a proponent of EM, uses a similar line of argument in his Global Marshall Plan. Despite offering an ambitious plan for international cooperation on sustainable initiatives, his emphasis on “the stabilizing of world population” and “the rapid creation and development of environmentally appropriate technologies” has apparent shortcomings (Dryzek, 1998, p. 325). In effect, these strategic objectives, albeit important, do not challenge the structure that permits capitalism to disguise itself in an eco-friendly facade, nor are they inclusive of the Global South. It is worth noting that Gore’s plan seems to align closely with the rational-choice perspective of Garrett Hardin, who maintained after writing The Tragedy of the Commons that 8 “pre-emptive, even coercive, action is needed to control population and conserve resources” (Redcliffe, 1987, p. 9). Although Gore’s vision is not necessarily ‘coercive’, he does concede that his Marshall Plan relies on nations that follow the ‘philosophical direction’ of democracy, free markets, and global co-operation. Yet the global ‘inclusiveness’ of this plan falters after he admits that “the responsibility for taking the initiative, for innovating, catalyzing, and leading such an effort, falls disproportionately on the United States” (Dryzek, 1998, p. 324). Hence the reasonable suspicions by Dryzek (1998) that Gore, along with other EM theorists, bolster Green consumerism without identifying the underlying structure that provokes ecological disasters. It is also a legitimate concern that the Global South may face ‘mal-development’ because of EM theory’s disregard for the ever-increasing consumption levels produced by capitalist society (Shiva, 1988). Moving past these claims, where SD fundamentally differs from EM is the ability to reframe consumption through cause and effect and the emergent structures of inequality induced by disproportionate global consumption (Baker, 2006). To some extent, the approach of SD takes the form of an appeal to mutual understanding and education of the social, economic, and ecological interdependence of this planet. This emphasis, which places global interconnections and the centrality of maintaining a sustainable carrying capacity, seems to lie outside of the realm of rational choice. Conversely, Weale (1992)’s EM approach to the public good returns to reductionist terms: The task of politics is to supply the public good of environmental protection. A similar logic can be applied to relations between states. On this account, international regimes of pollution control exist to solve the prisoners’ dilemma that nations face when they 9 confront one another over the use of common resources like the global atmosphere or the open seas (p. 42). Weale’s application of rational-choice theory has considerable implications for this next core problem as well, which turns to the institutional barriers of environmental policy-making. Administrative fragmentation In essence, administrative fragmentation refers to the division of administrative tasks into policy sectors with conflicting environmental objectives. This is best described in Carter (2006)’s own words: A core group of economic ministries – typically finance, industry, employment, energy, agriculture and transport – make policy decisions affecting production, consumption, mobility and lifestyles that will frequently have negative consequences for the environment. A transport ministry might implement a massive road-building programme, or the agriculture ministry might encourage intensive farming methods, while responsibility for protecting the environment is typically given to a separate ministry (p. 180). Beyond this summation, Carter (2006) goes on to note that this institutional rigidity is incompatible with ecological problems, which require a holistic approach from all administrative sectors. Issues such as climate change are marginalized when fragmentation exists; therefore, it is relevant to see how EM and SD propose to resolve this division of interests and overcome the status quo of environmental negligence that it maintains. Evidently, this implies structural change to environmental regimes so that they encompass the entire bureaucracy, not just one section of it. It is important to note that SD and 10 EM emerged during a structural change from the Fordist to post-Fordist system of production. It demanded increased specialization and efficiency, rather than mass production for mass consumption. The post-Fordist system calls for resource efficiency and pollution control, which are evidently the principles in which EM is grounded. Arguably, EM is merely a rational-choice narrative for a systemic transformation that it did not entirely understand. Christoff (1996) explained this as the ecological aspect of modernity. SD, on the other hand, was directly influenced by the series of environmental disasters that occurred during the four years that the Brundtland Commision was meeting, such as the Chernobyl incident and severe droughts of subSaharan Africa (Baker, 2006). The Brundtland Report subsequently stressed the need to enact environmental policies that are preventative, not curative (Mol, 1996). Hence the position of much of the SD literature during and after the publishing of Our Common Future that structural change is vital to ecological protection (Dryzek, 1998; Langhelle, 2000). The necessities to reform these institutional gaps, which result from fragmented sectors of the bureaucracy, are even recognized by recent work in ecological modernization. Martin Janicke identified four complexes that place considerable burdens on environmental policy – construction, transportation, energy, and agro-industrial. All of these, he finds, require restructuring (Langhelle, 2000). One principle that arguably challenges his four complexes is the “bottom-up” involvement of individual citizens in SD. This is articulated by Baker et al. (1997) as follows: The failure of the state adequately to address the problem of environmentally damaging activities affecting public welfare, and thereby securing social harmony, often generates opposition at the grassroots level. In such case, legitimation concerns of the polity can act 11 as political opportunity structures for grassroots activists to pressure the state and gain concessions (p. 22). Grassroots participation is one of the principle goals encompassed in the 1992 Rio Earth Summit through the establishment of Local Agenda 21 (LA21) (Baker et al., 1997). LA21 is based on the message presented in the Brundtland Report that SD must rely on political will on the local level just as much as the international level. This rejects claims by EM theorists that key actors in the policy process will not account for the ‘spill-over effects’ of other sectors. As the Brundtland Commission advocates, “All governments should develop a 'foreign policy for the environment' as one major way of improving the international coordination of national environmental policies.” This works in tandem with notion that the local and grassroots levels must actively participate in the same manner. This idea is crucial because the consequences of destructive environmental actions, such as acid rain or pollution, are often endured on the local level. Therefore, it is a vital for this level to be engaged in finding collective solutions, as they understand the real-life implications of environmental policy (Langhelle, 2000). Perhaps the most prominent success story of Agenda 21 in the context of the Global South is Costa Rica, a nation that is now seen as a global leader in sustainable development. This country’s environmental policy makes the necessary link between development and the environment by promoting forest conservation and renewable energy initiatives in tandem with the promotion of local political participation among municipalities throughout the country (Carter, 2006; Porras, 2012). In a sense, this dismantles the early EM proposition that the Global North will be the principal source of global environmental change. In Baker (2006)’s analysis of LA21, there have been tangible results for public participation and good governance in several regions of the world. Her work suggest that the next challenge to overcome is ‘capacity building’ 12 for communities to solve ecological problems on the local level. This observation, of course, returns to SD’s emphasis on intra-generational equity, which attempts to alleviate economic disparities (Baker et al., 1998. Conclusion In the end, rational-choice suggests that individual actors will assume their influence in the political agenda is marginal, which consequently results in a self-fulfilling, self-defeating prophecy (Weale, 1992). Sustainable development provides a framework to confront this defeatist rationale. In consideration of the three sections discussed above, it appears that SD and EM take considerably different approaches to environmental policy. The former utilizes normative principles and implements them on all scales to provide a resonant, global ecological discourse. Meanwhile, the latter concedes with many of the status-quo assumptions that resulted in domestic end-of-pipe solutions during the 1970s (Carter, 2006). SD is perhaps strongest through its emphasis of intra- and inter-generational equity, as well as its call for reduced consumption in the Global North. These positions make the necessary point of global ecological interdependence that the modern world faces. Where rational-choice ultimately falters is its generalized cost-benefit analysis of environmental problems: it neglects the emergent structures of inequality and the international norms that allure collective action. While ecological modernization offers reductionist solutions to predetermined problems in the global commons, sustainable development ultimately seeks to overcome them by reframing the discourse and reconceptualising individual agency in a holistic and innovative manner. 13 References Baker, S. (2006). Sustainable development. London: Routledge. Baker S, Kousis M, Richardson, D, & Young, S. (1997). The Politics of Sustainable Development: Theory, Policy and Practice within the European Union. Routledge: London. Carter, N. (2006). The politics of the environment: ideas, activism, policy. Cambridge: University Press Christoff, P. (1996). Ecological modernisation, ecological modernities. Environmental Politics 5: 476–500. Dryzek, J. (1998). The Politics of the Earth: Environmental Discourses. Oxford University Press: Oxford. Hajer, M. A. (1995). The politics of environmental discourse: ecological modernization and the policy process. Oxford: Clarendon Press Lafferty, W. (1996). The politics of sustainable development: global norms for national implementation. Environmental Politics 5: 185–208. Langhelle, O. (2000). Why ecological modernization and sustainable development should not be conflated. Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning, Special Issue 2: 303-322. Mol, A. (1996). Ecological modernisation and institutional reflexivity: environmental reform in the late modern age. Environmental Politics 5: 302–323. Mol, A., & Sonnenfeld, D (2000). Ecological modernisation around the world: perspectives and critical debates. London: Frank Cass. Mol, A., & Spaargaren, G. (2000). Ecological modernization theory in debate: A review. In A. P. Our Common Future (1987), Brundtland Commission, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 14 Pepper, D. (1998). Sustainable development and ecological modernization: A radical homocentric perspective. Sustainable Development 6(1):1-7. Porras, I, Miranda, M., & Barton, D.N. (2012). Payments of environmental services in Costa Rica: from Rio to Rio and beyond. International Institute for Environment and Development. Retrieved from http://www.pubs.iied.org/17126IIED.html Redcliffe, M. R. (1987). Sustainable development: exploring the contradictions. Routledge: London. Shiva, V. (1988). Staying alive: women, ecology, and development. London: Zed Books. Ulrich Brand (2010): Sustainable development and ecological modernization – the limits to a hegemonic policy knowledge, Innovation: The European Journal of Social Science Research, 23:2, 135-152 Weale, A. (1992), The New Politics of Pollution, Manchester: Manchester University Press. 15