Review of Economic Dynamics 3, 365᎐395 Ž2000. doi:10.1006rredy.2000.0098, available online at http:rrwww.idealibrary.com on Optimal Intertemporal Consumption under Uncertainty1 Gary Chamberlain Department of Economics, Har¨ ard Uni¨ ersity, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138 and Charles A. Wilson 2 Department of Economics, New York Uni¨ ersity, 269 Mercer Street, New York, New York 10003 Received November 30, 1999 We analyze the optimal consumption program of an infinitely lived consumer who maximizes the discounted sum of utilities subject to a sequence of budget constraints where both the interest rate and his income are stochastic. We show that if the income and interest rate processes are sufficiently stochastic and the long run average rate of interest is greater than or equal to the discount rate, then consumption eventually grows without bound with probability one. We also establish conditions under which the borrowing constraints must be binding and examine how the income process affects the optimal consumption program. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Number: D91. 䊚 2000 Academic Press Key Words: uncertainty; consumption; permanent income hypothesis. 1. INTRODUCTION We shall consider the following problem. In each period t, a consumer receives income x t . After receiving his income, he must decide how much to consume in that period, c t , and how much to save for future consumption. His savings earn a gross rate of return, rtq1 , so that the value of his 1 Support from the National Science Foundation and the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation is gratefully acknowledged. We have benefitted from discussions with William Brock, Ed Green, Jose ´ Scheinkman, and Itzak Zilcha. 2 To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: Charles.Wilson@nyu.edu. 365 1094-2025r00 $35.00 Copyright 䊚 2000 by Academic Press All rights of reproduction in any form reserved. 366 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON assets at the beginning of period t q 1 Žafter he has received income x tq1 . is given by the relation a tq1 s rtq1Ž a t y c t . q x tq1. The consumer’s problem is to choose a consumption plan to maximize the expectation of Ý⬁ts0 uŽ c t .  t subject to a budget constraint, where u is an increasing, strictly concave function. His only source of uncertainty is that x t and rt follow some stochastic process. The question we address is: What happens to the levels of c t and a t as t goes to infinity? The motivation of the paper lies in the work of several authors who attempt to formalize the permanent income hypothesis of Friedman Ž1957.. The first of these papers, Yaari Ž1976. and Schechtman Ž1976., considers the case where utility is not discounted Ž  s 1., the interest rate is zero Ž rt s 1., and the horizon is finite; i.e., the consumer maximizes ÝTts0 uŽ c t .. Assuming that income x t is identically and independently distributed and imposing only a solvency constraint on lifetime consumption, Yaari shows that as T ª ⬁, the optimal consumption plan requires c Tt , the consumption in period t with horizon T, to converge with probability one to Ew x t x for all t. Schechtman tightens the solvency constraint to forbid borrowing and obtains the weaker result that, as both T and t go to infinity, c Tt converges to Ew x t x with probability one. He also establishes that a t converges to infinity. Bewley Ž1977. retains the restriction on borrowing but considers a more general case where both x t and u t follow a stationary stochastic process. He also allows for discounting Ž  - 1.. He obtains the analogous result that uXt Ž c Tt . converges to a constant as T ª ⬁, t ª ⬁, and  ª 1, so that, asymptotically, the consumer becomes insulated from risk. Some of the implications of this result are developed in Bewley Ž1980a, 1980b.. In this paper we investigate the asymptotic properties of the optimal consumption program for the infinite horizon model when income and interest rates are stochastic and the consumer discounts a bounded utility function. We put no additional restrictions on the form of the stochastic process Žsuch as stationarity ., and we allow for arbitrary restrictions on the permissible level of borrowing in each period. Under these assumptions, we show that if the discount rate is smaller than the long run average rate of interest, then c t will converge to infinity almost surely. When the long run interest rate is equal to the discount rate, the asymptotic properties of c t depend on how stochastic the income stream is. If the income stream is certain, c t is nondecreasing and converges to the supremum of the maximum sustainable consumption level starting from the minimum permissible level of wealth in any given period. However, if the income stream is suitably stochastic, c t must converge to infinity almost surely. This result extends some of the results of Sotomayor Ž1984., who examines the case where income is identically and independently distributed Žbut allows for utility to be unbounded.. CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 367 Our analysis is based on the following observation. For simplicity, suppose that the interest factor is a constant, ␥ . Let ¨ Ž a t , z t . be the expected discounted utility from following the optimal policy, given asset level a t and information state z t at time t. Then the first order conditions for utility maximization require ¨ qŽ a t , z t . G ␥ Ew ¨ qŽ a tq1 , z tq1 .< z t x, where ¨ q denotes the right-hand derivative of ¨ with respect to a t . When ␥ G 1, this implies that ¨ qŽ a t , z t . is a supermartingale. By a theorem of Doob Ž1953., this implies a finite random variable d⬁ such that ¨ qŽ a t , z t . converges to d⬁ with probability 1. If ␥ ) 1, ¨ q Ž a t , z t . G ␥ Ew ¨ qŽ a tq1 , z tq1 .< z t x implies ¨ qŽ a t , z t . ª 0 from which it is easy to show that c t must converge to infinity. If ␥ s 1, this argument can still be used to show that c t converges with probability 1 to some extended random variable c⬁ , but in this case, c⬁ need not equal infinity. In fact, as we show in Theorem 3, if x t is not stochastic, c⬁ is generally not infinite. However, the following argument shows that c⬁ must be infinite if the discounted value of future income is suitably stochastic. Suppose there is positive probability that c⬁ - ⬁. Then we can choose an arbitrarily small interval w b, b q x and a - ⬁ such that there is positive probability that c g w b, b q x, and, with probability greater than 1 y , c t g w b, b q x for all t G whenever c g w b, b q x. But if c ( c for t G , then a t will diverge to "⬁ unless Ž␥rŽ␥ y 1.. c s a q Ý⬁js q1 x j␥ yj. We can show that it is not optimal to have c ( c if a t ª ⬁. So conditional on c ( b, it follows that Ý⬁js q1 x j␥ yj ( Ž␥rŽ␥ y 1.. b y a . But since a is known at time , this implies that the conditional variance of Ý⬁js q1 x j␥ yj can be made arbitrarily small for sufficiently small. Therefore, unless there is perfect foresight, savings must diverge. We conclude that if the income stream is suitably stochastic, then c t converges to infinity with probability 1. In the body of the paper, these arguments are generalized to allow for a stochastic interest rate. In particular, if the discount rate is equal to the long run average rate of interest, then c t grows without bound if there is sufficient uncertainty in the joint distribution of income and interest rates. This case arises in the treatment of the optimum quantity of money by Bewley Ž1980c, 1983.. We see that with discounting and a positive interest rate, the only counterpart to the Yaari᎐Schechtman᎐Bewley result is a zero limit for marginal utility. If ␥ G 1, then consumption does converge, but it converges to bliss, not the expected value of discounted income.3 We should also note that although both Schechtman and Bewley use the convergence theorem for supermartingales, their argument requires either the law of 3 An example of Schechtman and Escudero Ž1977. shows that convergence to bliss with probability 1 can occur when ␥ - 1 and income is independent and identically distributed. They also provide a condition on the utility function that rules this out. 368 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON large numbers or the ergodic theorem, which in turn requires a stationarity assumption. By itself, however, the supermartingale theorem requires no additional assumptions. It is the stochastic generalization of the result that a bounded, monotone sequence converges to a finite limit. Consequently, when we eliminate the need for a law of large numbers by introducing discounting, we are able to considerably weaken our assumptions on the stochastic process and still obtain convergence of c t , even with a positive interest rate. If the underlying process is stationary, there are alternative conditions on the interest rate sequence which ensure that consumption converges to infinity. In Subsection 4.4, we show that if the interest rate sequence is stationary and ergodic, then consumption will grow without bound if Ewlog  rt x ) 0. If Ewlog  rt x s 0 and an additional condition is satisfied which guarantees that the interest rate has sufficient variance and its dependence on the past dies out sufficiently fast, then some subsequence of consumption will grow without bound. In both cases, the result follows from the fact that  t Ł tjs1 r j Žor some subsequence . converges to infinity with probability 1. Section 5 deals with some implications of the budget constraint. Rather than restrict ourselves to a no borrowing constraint at the outset, we allow the lower bound on borrowing in any period to be an arbitrary function of the consumer’s information in that period. We then note that by redefining income and wealth, the original problem is equivalent to a problem where income is nonnegative in each period and no borrowing is permitted. Making this translation explicit emphasizes that these assumptions are not really substantive restrictions on the model, but are merely a simpler representation of a more general model. In particular, they are consistent with the possibility that the only constraint on borrowing is an intertemporal budget constraint. With this interpretation, we establish some conditions under which the borrowing constraint is never binding as well as conditions under which it must be binding in some periods. We also show how the optimal program changes as the borrowing constraints are relaxed. In the final section of the paper, we show how some of our results can be extended to the case where the consumer chooses a portfolio of several risky assets. The main complication introduced by this extension is that the interest rate becomes endogenous. 2. ASSUMPTIONS AND NOTATION n ⺢ is the real line, and ⺢ n is n-dimensional Euclidean space. ⺢q and ⺢q refer to the corresponding subsets of nonnegative elements. Nonnegative integers are denoted by t, , i, j. Other lower-case Roman letters generally CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 369 refer to random variables or their realizations, and lower-case Greek letters Žparticularly, , ␦ , and ␣ . generally refer to real numbers. Let z ' Ž . . . , zy1 , z 0 , z1 , . . . . be a stochastic process with transition probabilities pŽ dz t < z ty1 . used to define conditional expectation, where z t g ⺢ n and z t ' Ž z ty1, z t . ' Ž . . . zy1 , z 0 , z1 , . . . , z t .. Interpret z t as new information the consumer receives at time t and z t as the information state at time t. Let Z t Ž z 0 . s z t : z jt s z j0 , j F 04 be the set of states at time t which are consistent with state z 0 . Except for Section 4.4 where we consider the case where z is stationary, we will take z 0 as fixed. We assume that the income of the consumer at time t G 0 is a continuous function x t : Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢.4 At each time t G 1, the consumer may borrow and lend between time t y 1 and time t at interest factor rt which is assumed to be a positive, continuous function rt : Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢q. For j t G 0, let R t t ' 1. For j ) t G 0, let R t j ' Ł kstq1 r k denote the interest y1 factor between periods t and j, and let R t j denote its inverse. The borrowing constraint of the consumer at time t G 0 is a continuous function, k t : Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢ that satisfies an intertemporal consistency constraint, P Ž rt k ty1 q x t G k t , t G 0 < z 0 . s 1, Ž 1. where r 0 ky1 ' 0. Let x ' Ž x 0 , x 1 , . . . . and k ' Ž k 0 , k 1 , . . . .. Interpret k t as the minimum amount of wealth, measured in terms of period t consumption, that the individual may hold at the end of period t Žafter he receives his period t income and spends his period t consumption.. Equation Ž1. requires that the lower bound on current net wealth be consistent with the borrowing constraint the consumer will face in the next period. It implies that current wealth can never be so low that it may become impossible for the individual to satisfy his borrowing constraint in the next period even if nothing is consumed in the current period. Defining r 0 ky1 ' 0 is simply a convention which implies that the consumer’s initial wealth is derived solely from his period 0 income. Since the consumer’s decision at each information state depends only on what he knows at that state, a consumption program, c ' Ž c 0 , c1 , . . . ., is a sequence of Borel measurable functions, c t : Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢q, t G 0. Let u: ⺢qª ⺢ be an increasing, continuous, strictly concave function with 0 F u F M ' sup c ª⬁ uŽ c . - ⬁. For any consumption program c, uŽ c t . is the undiscounted utility to the consumer from his consumption at time t. We suppose the consumer discounts utility by a factor  Ž0 -  - 1. in each period. Therefore, at state z 0 , the problem of the consumer is to choose a 4 The continuity requirement is without loss of generality since we may always include a variable as one of the coordinates of z t . 370 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON consumption program c to maximize EwÝ⬁js0 uŽ c j .  j < z 0 x subject to P ŽÝtjs0 Ž x j y c j . R jt G k t , t G 0 < z 0 . s 1. Some of our results require some regularity assumptions on the transition probabilities. We assume that for any z 0 the Feller property holds: if f : ⺢ n ª ⺢ is a bounded continuous function, then g Ž z t . s H f Ž w . pŽ dw < z t . is a continuous function from Z t Ž z 0 . to ⺢. This condition combined with the requirement that x t , rt , and k t be continuous functions is shown in Theorem A.1 Žof the Appendix. to guarantee that the consumer’s problem has a solution. Before proceeding with our analysis, it will be useful to redefine our income variable so that the problem may be reduced to a simpler form. As stated, the problem of the consumer is to choose a consumption program that maximizes the discounted sum of utility subject to a Žpossibly random. borrowing constraint. Aside from technical considerations, there are no restrictions on either the income stream or the borrowing constraint other than the requirement that the borrowing constraint satisfy Eq. Ž1.. For instance, if we assume that x t is nonnegative and we wish to prohibit borrowing, we may set k t s 0 for all t. Alternatively, if we wish to impose only an intertemporal solvency constraint, the appropriate constraint is < t. 45 k t Ž z t . ' inf g ⺢: P Ž q Ý⬁jstq1 x j Ry1 t j G 0 z s 1 . However, we also allow for intermediate cases as well as cases where lim t ª⬁ k t Ry1 0 t / 0. Whatever additional assumptions we impose on x t and k t , however, we may always translate the variables so that the problem is equivalent to one in which income is nonnegative and borrowing is not permitted. The key is to redefine income at time t to be the increase in available purchasing power the consumer receives at time t. This is the difference between x t , the income he receives in period t, and k t y rt k ty1 , the change in the minimum allowable wealth from period t y 1 to period t, measured in units of income at time t. Letting ˆ x t ' x t y k t q rt k ty1 and letting ˆ kt ' 0 for all t G 0, Eq. Ž1. may be stated as P Ž ˆ x t G 0, t G 0 < z 0 . s 1, and the < 0. borrowing constraint may be stated as P ŽÝtjs0 Ž ˆ x j y c j . Ry1 0 j G 0, t G 0 z s 1. Note that since x t , k t , and k ty1 are all continuous functions of z t , x̂ t is also a continuous function of z t. Consequently, the technical requirements and information restrictions on ˆ x t and ˆ k t are satisfied. Unless we indicate otherwise, we shall assume for the remainder of the paper that this translation has already been made so that we may restrict attention to the case x t G 0 and k t s 0. However, it is occasionally useful to emphasize the interpretation of our results in the original framework. 5 To ensure the existence of some feasible consumption program consistent with ky1 s 0, < 0 . s 1, and to ensure that yk t - ⬁ so that an optimal we then require P ŽÝ⬁js 0 x j Ry1 0j G 0 z t < t. consumption program exists, we then require P ŽÝ⬁js t x j Ry1 t j - ⬁ z ) 0 for all z . 371 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY To establish the results that follow, it is convenient to work with the value function of future discounted utility defined over the level of accumulated assets. For any state z t and wealth level a G 0, define ¨ Ž a, z t . ' max E c ⬁ Ý u Ž c j .  jyt < z t jst subject to P a y ct q ž < t Ý Ž x j y c j . Ry1 t j G 0, G t z jstq1 / s1 to denote the expected utility of the consumer starting at time t with information z t , given purchasing power a at time t. Following the arguments of Blackwell Ž1965., Strauch Ž1966., and Maitra Ž1968., we establish as Theorem A.1 in the Appendix that ¨ Ž a, z t . s max 0 F c F a uŽ c . q  Ew ¨ ŽŽ a y c . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 .< z t x4.6 With the exception of Subsection 4.4, which uses the stationary assumptions, we shall assume the initial information state z 0 is fixed so that unconditional expectations should be understood to be conditional on z 0 . It is also frequently convenient to suppress explicit reference to the state z t , so that for a given state z t , we sometimes write ¨ Ž a, z t . ' ¨ t Ž a. and regard ¨ t Ž a. as a random variable. Also, to simplify the statement of some of the theorems, we sometimes state properties of the optimal program as if they hold for all z t , although we prove our results on a set of probability 1. 3. PRELIMINARY RESULTS The existence and uniqueness of a solution to the consumer’s maximization problem is established in the Appendix as Theorem A.1. We also establish there that ¨ t is a bounded, strictly concave function. Therefore, right- and left-hand derivatives exist. For any function f : w0, ⬁x ª ⺢, let fqŽ x . denote the right-hand derivative of f Ž x ., let fyŽ x . denote its left-hand derivative when x ) 0, and let fqŽ 0. s lim x x 0 fqŽ x .. Let c* s Ž cU0 , cU1 , . . . . denote the consumption program which solves the consumer’s 6 The result is actually established for the more general model with many assets discussed in Section 6. 372 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON maximization problem, and let a* ' Ž aU0 , aU1 , . . . . denote the corresponding sequence of random variables representing the level of the consumer’s wealth in each period after current income has been received but before consumption has been spent. The wealth sequence a* is defined recurŽ . sively by aU0 ' x 0 and aUt ' rt Ž aUty1 y cUty1 . q x t s x t q Ýty1 js0 x j y c j R jt , for t ) 0. With these definitions, we may state some conditions which an optimal program must satisfy. The proof is quite standard and will be omitted. Ž U. qŽ cUt .,  Ew rtq1¨ q Ž U .< t x4 . Žb. SupLEMMA 1. Ža. ¨ q t a t s max u tq1 a tq1 z U pose a t ) 0. Then U ¨y t Ž at . ¡u y ~ Ž cUt . if aUt y cUt s 0 U y t s  E rtq1¨ tq1 Ž a tq1 . < z ¢min u y U < t Ž cUt . ,  E rtq1¨ y tq1 Ž a tq1 . z if cUt s 0 4 if 0 - aUt y cUt - aUt . For t G 0, let t '  t R 0 t . If the level of consumption in period 0 is equal to the level of consumption in period t, then t measures the rate at which the consumer can transform discounted utility in period t for utility Ž U . is a supermartingale. in period 0. Condition Ža. establishes that t¨ q t at Our first theorem uses the supermartingale convergence theorem to Ž U . must converge to some random variable e⬁ . The establish that t¨ q t at Ž U . must be only problem is that to apply the convergence theorem, ¨ q t at Ž . finite which is not true if x 0 s 0 and ¨ q 0 0 s ⬁. This difficulty can be avoided if we assume that the discounted value of the entire income stream is always positive. In this case, there is a stopping time such that aU ) 0, which allows us to apply the convergence theorem to the sequence Ž ¨qŽ aU ..y1qt¨qqt Ž aUqt .. THEOREM 1. If P Žx s 0. s 0, then there is a Ž real-¨ alued . random Ž U. . ¨ ariable e⬁ such that P Žlim t ª⬁ t¨ q t a t s e⬁ s 1. Proof. P Žx s 0. s 0 implies a stopping time such that x ) 0. ThereŽ U . is finite. Let fore, aU G x ) 0 and the concavity of ¨ imply that ¨ q t at U y1 U q q d t ' Ž ¨ Ž a .. qt¨qt Ž aqt . for t G 0. Since is a stopping time, Lemma 1 implies that Ž d 0 , d1 , . . . . is a nonnegative supermartingale ŽMeyer, 1966, p. 66.. But since d 0 s 1, there is a random variable d⬁ with CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 373 Ew d⬁ F 1x such that P Žlim t ª⬁ d t s d⬁ . s 1 ŽDoob, 1953, p. 324.. Then if . Ž U. we define e⬁ ' ¨qŽ aU . d⬁ , it follows that P Žlim t ª⬁ t¨ q t a t s e⬁ s 1. In the next section, we use Theorem 1 to establish some conditions under which consumption must converge to infinity. To establish these conditions we use the fact that whenever assets grow without bound, consumption also grows without bound. This result is established as Lemma 2. cUt LEMMA 2. G ␣ 1. For any ␣ 1 ) 0, there is an ␣ 2 ) 0 such that aUt G ␣ 2 implies M Proof. From Lemma A.2, 0 F ¨ t Ž aUt . - 1 y  . Therefore, the concavity U q U U M Ž of ¨ t implies a t ¨ t Ž a t . F ¨ t Ž a t . y ¨ t Ž0. F 1 y  . Choose ␣ 2 s Mr 1 y U qŽ Ž . .  . uqŽ ␣ 1 .. Then if aUt G ␣ 2 , Lemma 1 implies uq Ž cUt . F ¨ q a F ¨ t t t ␣2 F MrŽ1 y  . ␣ 2 s uq Ž ␣ 1 .. The concavity of u then implies cUt G ␣ 1. With these results in hand, we are prepared to examine the limiting behavior of the optimal consumption sequence. 4. CONVERGENCE THEOREMS Ž U . must Recall that Theorem 1 establishes that the function t¨ q t at converge to some random variable e⬁ . In this section we demonstrate that the implications of this result for the limiting behavior of the optimal consumption sequence depend primarily on the limiting value of t . Roughly, our results may be summarized as follows. If lim t ª⬁ t s ⬁, the optimal consumption sequence of the consumer must grow without bound, regardless of the properties of the income and interest rate sequences. If the limiting value Žor values. of t is bounded above and away from zero and the income stream is suitably stochastic, then consumption still grows without bound. However, if the income sequence is not stochastic, then the consumption sequence generally converges to a finite limit. These results may also be interpreted in terms of the relationship between the rate at which the consumer discounts future utility and the long run rate of interest. In Section 2, we defined rt to be the one period j interest factor between period t y 1 and period t and R t j ' Ł kstq1 r k to be the accumulated interest factor between periods t and j. Therefore, jyt . R1rŽ represents the a¨ erage interest factor between periods t and j. If tj t lim t ª⬁ R1r 0 t exists, we call it the long run interest factor; otherwise, we say that the long run interest rate fluctuates. Now consider the meaning of t 1r t t '  t R 0 t . Rewriting the expression, we obtain  R1r . Therefore, 0 t s t 374 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON the long run rate of interest is equal to the discount rate if and only if lim t ª⬁ t1r t s 1. Clearly, if the limiting values of t are positive and finite, then the long run interest rate exists and is equal to the discount rate. ŽAlthough this is not a necessary condition, we will sometimes blur this distinction for expositional convenience.. We may translate our conclusions as follows. The limiting behavior of consumption depends primarily on the relation between the long run rate of interest and the rate at which the consumer discounts utility. If the long run rate of interest is greater than the discount rate, then consumption grows without bound as long as the consumer earns a positive income in some period. If the long run rate of interest is equal to the discount factor, then consumption generally converges to infinity only if there is sufficient uncertainty in either the income or interest rate sequences. All of our results are established for the case where both the income and interest rate sequences may be stochastic. In many cases, however, the intuition behind our results and the meaning of the assumptions become more apparent when only the income sequence is stochastic. Throughout this section, therefore, we will frequently focus the discussion on the special case where the interest rate is a constant. We conclude the section with an interpretation of our results in the context of a stationary distribution of interest rates. We turn first to the case where the long run interest rate exceeds the rate at which the consumer discounts utility. 4.1. Lim t s ⬁ Our main result for the case where the long run rate of interest exceeds the discount rate is summarized in the following theorem. THEOREM 2. Suppose P Žx s 0. s 0. Then Ži. P Žlim sup t ª⬁ t s ⬁. s 1 implies P Žlim sup t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1, and Žii. P Žlim t ª⬁ t s ⬁. s 1 implies P Žlim cUt s ⬁. s 1. Proof. Theorem 1 implies that if P Žlim sup t ª⬁ t s ⬁. s 1 and P Žx s Ž U. . 0. s 0, then P Žlim inf t ª⬁¨ q t a t s 0 s 1. Lemma 1 then implies that U q P Žlim inf t ª⬁ u Ž c t . s 0. s 1, and therefore, that P Žlim sup t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1. This proves part Ži.. The proof of part Žii. is similar. Roughly, Theorem 2 says that consumption grows without bound so long as the long run rate of interest always exceeds the discount rate. If the long run interest rate fluctuates, but some subsequence always exceeds the discount rate, then some subsequence of consumption grows without bound. When the interest rate is constant, the theorem may be restated as follows. CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 375 COROLLARY 1. Suppose that rt s ␥ for t G 1. If P Žx s 0. s 0 and ␥ ) 1, then P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1. 4.2. The Case of Certainty: ␥ s 1 For the remainder of this section, we are concerned primarily with the case where the long run interest rate is equal to the rate at which the consumer discounts future utility. To underline the importance of the role of uncertainty in the main results which follow, we first concentrate on the case where the income sequence is nonstochastic and the interest rate in each period is equal to the rate at which the consumer discounts utility. Again denote the constant interest factor by ␥ . When ␥ s 1, the first-order conditions for utility maximization imply that the consumer tries to equalize consumption in each period. As long as such a program does not violate the borrowing constraint, this condition characterizes the solution. If such a program does violate the borrowing constraint, however, the consumer must choose a consumption stream with unequal levels of consumption over time. Nevertheless, consumption never decreases over time. Otherwise, by saving more in an earlier period and consuming more later, lifetime utility can be increased. This observation implies that the consumption level approaches a limit Žpossibly equal to ⬁., which we characterize in the next theorem. Define yt ' ŽŽ␥ y 1.r␥ .Ý⬁jst x j␥ tyj to be the supremum of those consumption levels that can be sustained indefinitely when we consider only the borrowing constraints in the distant future, given that the borrowing constraint is binding in period t y 1. Our next theorem states that cUt converges to the supremum of these maximum sustainable consumption levels. THEOREM 3. sup t yt . If x is not stochastic, then ␥ s 1 implies lim t ª⬁ cUt s Proof. We show first that for t G 1, either Ža. cUty1 s cUt , or Žb. cUty1 U c t and cUty1 s aUty1 Žin which case, aUt s x t .. Suppose cUty1 - aUty1. If cUty1 s 0, then Lemma 1 and the strict concavity of u and ¨ ty1 imply q Ž U . qŽ . Ž . ¨q 0 , which violates Lemma A.3. So suppose 0 ty1 0 ) ¨ ty1 a ty1 G u U U Ž U . c ty1 - a ty1. Then, on one hand, Lemma 1 implies uy Ž cUty1 . G ¨ y ty1 a ty1 U U U U U qŽ qŽ Ž . . G ¨q c t ., and therefore, 0 F c ty1 F c t . On the ty1 a ty1 G ¨ t a t G u y Ž U . Ž U . other hand, Lemma 1 also implies uqŽ cUty1 . F ¨ q ty1 a ty1 F ¨ ty1 a ty1 F yŽ U . Ž U. ¨y c t , and therefore, cUt F cUty1. t at F u Let c ' lim t ª⬁ cUt and let y ' sup t yt . We show first that c F y. Suppose not and let t be the smallest G 0 such that cU ) y. Then, condition Žb. 376 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON above implies aUt s x t . From the definition of aUt , it then follows that ty1 Ý Ž x j y cUj . ␥yj s 0. Ž 2. js0 Conditions Ža. and Žb. also imply that cU is nondecreasing in t. Therefore, cUj ) yt for all j G t, so that ŽŽ␥ y 1.r␥ .Ý⬁jst cUj ␥ tyj G cUt ) yt s ŽŽ␥ y 1.r␥ .Ý⬁jst x j␥ tyj, which implies a sufficiently large such that Ý Ž x j y cUj . ␥ tyj - 0. Ž 3. jst Combining Ž2. and Ž3. then yields Ýjs0 Ž x j y cUj .␥yj - 0, violating the budget constraint of the consumer’s maximization problem. To show that c G y, again assume the contrary. Then there is a yt such that cUj - yt for all j G 0, which implies ⬁ ⬁ jst jst Ý cUj ␥ tyj - Ý x j␥ tyj . Ž 4. But if cUt is feasible, then ty1 Ý Ž x j y cUj . ␥yj G 0. Ž 5. js0 It follows from Ž4. and Ž5. that there is an ) 0 and ˆ G t such that, for all G ˆ , Ýjs0 Ž x j y cUj .␥yj ) . But then ˆ c, defined by ˆ c j s cUj for j / ˆ U and ˆ cˆ s cˆ q , also satisfies the consumer’s budget constraint. But then Ý⬁js0 uŽ ˆ c j .  j ) Ý⬁js0 uŽ cUj .  j implies that c* is not an optimal consumption program. For our purposes the main implication of this theorem is that when the income stream is certain, the consumption sequence generally converges to a finite limit. Consumption grows without bound only if the discounted value of future income is not bounded. However, the theorem also has a noteworthy implication in the context of the original formulation of the model. Suppose that x is an arbitrary income sequence and k is an intertemporally consistent sequence of borrowing constraints from which we derive ˆx t ' x t y k t q ␥ k ty1 G 0. Then, yt ' ŽŽ␥ y 1.r␥ .Ý⬁jst ˆx j␥ tyj s ŽŽ␥ y 1.r␥ .lim ª⬁ŽÝjst x j␥ tyj y ␥ ty k . q Ž␥ y 1. k ty1. Now suppose we start with a sequence of borrowing constraints which generates an optimal consumption program c 1. Then if the k 1 constraint is replaced by a tighter CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 377 constraint, k 2 G k 1 Ži.e., k t2 G k 1t for all t ., but which allows for the same discounted value of consumption Ži.e., lim ª⬁␥y Ž k1 y k2 . s 0., then the tighter constraint k 2 generates a limiting value of consumption at least as large as did the k 1 constraint Ži.e., lim t ª⬁ c t2 G lim t ª⬁ c 1t .. An even stronger result can be established about the behavior of the sequence of accumulated wealth in each period, but this is left to Section 5, where the stochastic case is treated as well. 4.3. The Stochastic Case As noted above, the analysis of the certainty case yields little insight into the limiting behavior of consumption when we introduce uncertainty into either the income sequence or the interest rate sequence. In this subsection, we formulate a general ‘‘uncertainty’’ condition under which we show that consumption grows without bound even when the long run interest rate equals the discount rate. The meaning of our uncertainty condition is most transparent when the interest factor is fixed at ␥ s 1 . In this case, we require: Condition ŽU␥ .. There is an ) 0 such that for any ␣ g ⺢, P ␣F ž ⬁ Ý x j␥ tyj F ␣ q < z t jst / -1y for all z t , t G 0. Condition ŽU␥ . says that starting at any information state, there is a fixed probability that the discounted value of future income lies outside any sufficiently small range. The key implication of this condition is when consumption stays within a sufficiently small range in each period, assets must diverge with some fixed probability from any information state. However, the proof of our main result requires a fixed probability that assets diverge whenever the consumption program keeps the marginal utility of consumption approximately constant. Consequently, when we allow for a stochastic interest rate, the uncertainty condition requires a slight reformulation that uses the utility function to restrict the relation between the income and interest rate sequences. Define the ‘‘inverse’’ of uq by hŽ0. ' ⬁ and, for y ) 0, hŽ y . ' inf c g ⺢q: uqŽ c . F y4 . Condition ŽU.. There is an ) 0 such that for any ␣ g ⺢ and any ) 0, ž P ␣F for all z t , t G 0. ⬁ Ý jst ž ž // xj y h j < t -1y Ry1 tj F ␣ q z / 378 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON Suppose the consumption program were chosen so that, in any information state, an increase in the present value of consumption by one unit generates an increase in discounted utility equal to . Then the consumption level in each information state would be determined by the relation cUt s hŽ r t ., and Condition ŽU. would imply a nontrivial probability that the present value of current assets plus future income is bounded away from the present value of current plus future consumption, starting at any state z t. Roughly speaking, the condition says that the actual income stream is stochastic relative to the hypothetical income stream required to make the marginal discounted utility of a ‘‘present value’’ unit of consumption equal in all information states. When the interest factor is constant, Condition ŽU␥ . implies Condition ŽU.. Our results are based on Lemma 4 below. Roughly, it says that if t is bounded away from zero and infinity Žthe long run interest rate is equal to the discount rate., then Condition ŽU. implies that the marginal utility of Ž U . must converge to 0. The argument goes as follows. Suppose assets ¨ q t at qŽ U . ¨ t a t does not converge to zero. Then we may choose - ⬁ and an arbitrarily small interval w b, b q x with b ) 0 such that Ži. there is positive probability that ¨qŽ aU . g w b, b q x, and Žii. if ¨qŽ aU . g w b, b x Ž U. w q x, then, with probability greater than 1 y , t¨ q t a t g b, b q for all t G . Now consider the Žnonnull. set of paths for which ¨qŽ aU . g w b, b q x for all t G . Since the first-order conditions for utility maxiŽ U .., Condition ŽU. implies that whenever mization imply that cUt s hŽ ¨ q t at qŽ U . t¨ t a t g w b, b q x for all t G , aUt must diverge with probability at least . But if aUt diverges, Lemma 2 implies that cUt must converge to Ž U . converges to infinity, which if t is bounded above, implies that t¨ q t at 0. This contradiction establishes the result. We proceed now with the formal analysis. To use Theorem 1 we must first establish that Condition ŽU. implies a nonzero income stream. LEMMA 3. Condition ŽU. implies P Žx s 0. s 0. Proof. We show first that Condition ŽU. implies that P Žx s 0 < z t . - 1 y for all z t. For this, it is sufficient to show that for any z t we may < t. choose sufficiently large so that P ŽÝ⬁jst hŽ r j . Ry1 t j - z s 1. Since yŽ . u is concave and bounded between 0 and M, we have cu c - M for all c g ⺢qr 04 . By definition, uyŽ hŽ r j .. G r j . Therefore, Ž r j . Ž .ŽŽ r j .  jyt . implies Ý⬁jst hŽ r j . hŽ r j . F M. Then Ry1 t j ' tr ⬁ jyt y1 R t j s Ž tr .Ý jst Ž r j . hŽ r j .  F Ž tr .Ž MrŽ1 y  ... Setting ) t Mr Ž1 y  . establishes the result. All that remains is to show that P Žx s 0 < z t . - 1 y for all z t implies P Žx s 0. s 0. We establish this by contradiction. Suppose P Žx s 0. ) 0. Let A t s x t s 04 and A⬁ s x s 04 . Then P Ž A t . ) 0 for all t G 0, and A j x A⬁ . Then, since P Žx s 0 < z t . - 1 y for all z t and A t is measurable 379 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY z t , we have P Ž A j < A t . ª P Ž A⬁ < A t . - 1 y . Therefore, there is an increasing sequence Ž Ž t .. such that P Ž A Ž tq1. < A Ž t . . - 1 y which implies P Žx s 0. s Ł⬁ts0 P Ž A Ž tq1. < A Ž t . . P Ž A Ž0. . F lim t ª⬁Ž1 y . t P Ž A tŽ0. . s 0. LEMMA 4. Suppose there is an ) 0 for which Condition ŽU. is satisfied Ž U. . and P Ž - t - 1 , t G 0. s 1. Then P Žlim t ª⬁ t¨ q t a t s 0 s 1. Proof. We will suppose the lemma is false and show that this implies a violation of Condition ŽU.. Our first step is to find an interval w , q ␦ x and a time such that w , q ␦ x contains ¨qŽ aU . with positive probability and, in the event that U Ž U. w x ¨qŽ aU . g w , q ␦ x, it is also true that t¨ q t a t g , q ␦ and c t is near hŽ r t . with probability close to 1 for all t G . Theorem 1 and Ž U. . Lemma 3 imply a random variable e⬁ such that P Žlim t ª⬁ t¨ q t a t s e⬁ s 1. If P Ž e⬁ s 0. - 1, then there is a ) 0 such that for any ␦ ) 0, P Ž e⬁ g w , q ␦ x. ) 0. Let ' 3 Ž1 y  .r2. Then, since h is uniformly continuous on any positive interval bounded away from zero, we may choose and ␦ , 0 - - - q ␦ , so that Ži. P Ž e⬁ g w , q ␦ x. ) 0, Žii. P Ž e⬁ s . s P Ž e⬁ s q ␦ . s 0, and Žiii. < hŽ r t . y hŽŽ q ␦ .r t .< - for - t - 1 . Define B ' e⬁ g w , q ␦ x4 , and for G 0, define Ž U. A ' ¨qŽ aU . g w , q ␦ x4 and B ' < cUt y hŽ r t .< - , t¨ q t at g w , q ␦ x, t G 4 . Then lim ª⬁ P Ž A . s P Ž B . ) 0. Also, Lemma 1 imŽ U .. s 0, t G 0. s 1. Therefore, P Ž - t - 1 . s 1 plies P Ž cUt y hŽ ¨ q t at and the continuity of h imply P Žlim t ª⬁Ž cUt y hŽ ⬁ r t .. s 0 < B . s 1. Then, since the monotonicity of h implies P Ž hŽ r t . G hŽ e⬁ r t . G hŽ q ␦ .< B . s 1, we have lim ª⬁ P Ž B . s P Ž B .. Consequently, we may choose - ⬁ such that P Ž B . ) Ž1 y . P Ž A . ) 0. We show next that if the marginal utility of consumption c j is always equated to r j , then the variation in the present value of the limiting level of assets is less than 2 on B . The monotonicity of h and the construction of B imply P Ž cU - hŽ . q , t G < B . s 1. Therefore, letting ␣ 2 ' hŽ . q , Lemma 2 implies an ␣ 1 - ⬁ such that P Ž0 F aUt y cUt F ␣ 1 , t G < B . s 1. Then, since P Ž - t - 1 , t G 0. s 1 implies jy P Ž Ry1 r j F y2 jy , j G . s 1, it follows that P Žlim t ª⬁Ž aUt j '  U y1 y c t . R t s 0 < B . s 1. Therefore, Ž aUt y cUt . Ry1 t s aU y cU q s aU y x q t Ý Ž x j y cUj . Ry1 j js q1 t Ý js ž ž // xj y h j Ry1 j q t Ý js y cUj Ry1 j žž / / h j 380 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON implies P aU y x q ⬁ ž ž // ž Ýž ž / / / ⬁ q h js Ý js j xj y h j Ry1 j Ž 6. y cUj Ry1 j s 0 B s 1. jy But from P Ž Ry1 r j F y2 jy , j G . s 1 and the definition j '  of B it follows that ⬁ P y cUj Ry1 j - ž žž / / Ý js h j Ž1 y  . 2 ' 2 / B s 1. Ž 7. / Ž 8. Combining Ž6. and Ž7. then yields P ž aU y x q ⬁ Ý js ž ž // xj y h j Ry1 j - 2 B s 1. We now use these results to show that Condition ŽU. must be violated. Let ␣ s x y aU y 2 . Since B ; A and P Ž B . ) Ž1 y . P Ž A ., it fol< < . lows from Ž8. that P Ž ␣ - <Ý⬁js Ž x j y hŽ r j .. Ry1 j - ␣ q A ) 1 y . But then A measurable z implies that the set of z such that P Ž ␣ <Ý⬁js Ž x j y hŽ r j .. Ry1 < < . ) 1 y has positive probability, j - ␣ q z which violates Condition ŽU.. We use this lemma again in Section 5. For the moment, however, it serves as the basis for the main result of this paper. THEOREM 4. Suppose there is an ) 0 such that Condition ŽU. is satisfied. If P Ž - t - 1 , t G 0. s 1, then P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1. Proof. If P Ž - t - 1 , t G 0. s 1, then Lemma 4 implies Ž U. . P Žlim t ª⬁¨ q t a t s 0 s 1. The conclusion then follows from Lemma 1. With sufficient uncertainty in the income and interest rate sequences, consumption will grow without bound even if the long run rate of interest is equal to the discount rate. A case in which this equality holds has been considered by Bewley Ž1980c, 1983. in his treatment of the optimum quantity of money. There is an asset with a fixed nominal return factor equal to y1 . The real return is rt s y1 Ž qty1rqt ., where the price Ž qt . of the consumption good in terms of the asset is uniformly bounded away CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 381 from zero and infinity. Consequently, t s q0rqt satisfies the conditions of Theorem 4. We conclude that if the uncertainty condition is satisfied, cU converges to infinity. For the case where the interest rate is constant, Theorem 4 implies the following corollary. COROLLARY 2. Suppose rt s ␥ for all t G 0 and suppose ␥ s 1. If Condition ŽU␥ . is satisfied, then P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1. If income is bounded above, then Condition ŽU␥ . in Corollary 2 can be replaced by the condition that the conditional variance of discounted future income is uniformly bounded away from zero; i.e., there is a ) 0 such that VarŽÝ⬁jst x j␥ tyj < z t . G for all z t , t G 0. However, if the income stream is stochastic, but the conditions of Corollary 2 are not satisfied, there are examples where the limiting level of consumption is finite with some positive probability. When contrasted with the outcome in the case of certainty, Corollary 2 is perhaps a surprisingly strong result. Unfortunately, the line of argument used in the proof does not provide a very convincing economic explanation. Clearly the strict concavity of the utility function must play a role. ŽThe result does not hold if, for instance, u is a linear function over a sufficiently large domain and Ž x t . is bounded.. But to simply attribute the result to risk aversion on the grounds that uncertain future returns will cause risk-averse consumers to save more, given any initial asset level, is not a completely satisfactory explanation either. In fact, it is a bit misleading. First, that argument only explains why expected accumulated assets would tend to be larger in the limit. It does not really explain why consumption should grow without bound. Second, over any finite time horizon, the argument is not even necessarily correct. Suppose, for example, that x t s x ty1 t for t s 1, . . . , T, where the Ž t . are identically and independently distributed with Ew t x s 1 and a compact support in ⺢. Suppose, also, that the consumer’s utility function is quadratic over a sufficiently large domain. Then if the consumer has a T-period planning horizon, it can be shown that his optimal consumption program is to set c t s x t for all t. In particular, mean-preserving spreads of future income leave current consumption unaffected. Moreover, the expected value of consumption in any period t is just equal to period 0 income. So there is no tendency at all for consumption to rise over time. Why then does the result change when we consider the limiting value of consumption in an infinite horizon problem? Although we have developed other arguments to establish our results, any explanation that we have been able to devise ultimately appeals in an essential way to the martingale convergence theorems. 382 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON 4.4. Limit Theorems When Ž rt . Is Stationary In this subsection, we assume that the sequence of information states is generated by a stationary process and establish some restrictions on the distribution of the single period interest rate that imply the conditions of Theorem 2. Since the stationarity restriction will be placed on the entire distribution of histories, we will be explicit about conditioning on z 0 .7 THEOREM 5. Suppose P Žx s 0. s 0. If Ž r 1 , r 2 , . . . . is stationary and ergodic and Ewlog  r 1 x ) 0, then P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁< z 0 . s 1 with probability 1. Proof. Let s Ewlog  r 1 x. The Ergodic Theorem implies that with probability 1, lim t ª⬁ 1t Ýtjs1 log  r j s ŽDoob, 1953, p. 465.. Therefore, for almost all z there is a Žz. such that Ýtjs1 log  r j ) 2t for t ) Žz., or equivalently, t ) e t r2 . Therefore, P Žlim t ª⬁ t s ⬁. s 1, which implies that z 0 : P Žlim t ª⬁ t s ⬁< z 0 . s 14 has probability 1. The desired result then follows from Theorem 2. For the case where EwlogŽ  r 1 .x s 0, we need some additional regularity conditions. For s F t, define Ž r s , . . . , rt . as the -field generated by r s , . . . , rt , and define Ž rt , rtq1 , . . . . as the sigma field generated by rt , rtq1 , . . . . Consider a nonnegative function of the positive integers. The sequence Ž r 1 , r 2 , . . . . is -mixing if for each t, j G 1, A1 g Ž r 1 , . . . , rt . and A 2 g Ž rtqj , rtqjq1 , . . . . together imply that < P Ž A1 l A 2 . y P Ž A1 . P Ž A 2 .< F Ž j . P Ž A1 .. Condition ŽR.. Ži. Ž r 1 , r 2 , . . . . is a stationary, -mixing stochastic process with Ý⬁js1Ž Ž j ..1r2 - ⬁. Žii. EwŽlog  r 1 . 2 x - ⬁ and 2 ' E Ž log  r 1 . 2 q2 ⬁ Ý E Ž log  r1 . Ž log  r j . / 0. js2 The first part of Condition ŽR. ensures that the dependence between rt and rtqj dies out sufficiently fast as j ª ⬁. Suppose part Ži. is satisfied and Ewlog  r 1 x s 0. Then Ý⬁js2 EwŽlog  r 1 .Žlog  r j .x converges absolutely and 2 s lim T ª⬁ Ew T1 ŽÝTjs1 log  r j . 2 x ŽBillingsley, 1968, Lemmata 1 and 3, pp. 170, 172.. In this case, part Žii. may be satisfied as well if there is sufficient variability in  t R 0T . However, if P Ž  r 1 s 1. s 1, part Žii. is not satisfied, and we know from Theorem 4 that the behavior of Ž cUt . may depend upon 7 Theorem A.1 establishes the existence of an optimal program only for a fixed z t. Because we did not restrict z t to be drawn from a compact set, we are able to show that cUt Ž z t . is a measurable function of z t only for a fixed tail Že.g., a given z 0 .. Without additional restrictions we are unable to prove that cUt is a measurable function if all components of z t are allowed to vary. 383 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY whether or not Ž x t . is stochastic. Nevertheless, our next theorem states that if Condition ŽR. is satisfied and Ewlog  r 1 x s 0, then sup t cUt s ⬁, without a requirement that Ž x t . be stochastic. THEOREM 6. Suppose P Žx s 0. s 0 and Ž r 1 , r 2 , . . . . satisfies Condition ŽR.. Then Ewlog  r 1 x s 0 implies P Žsup t G 0 cUt s ⬁< z 0 . s 1 with probability 1. Proof. Define St ' Ýtjs1 log  r j Žs log t . and define Yt Ž ␦ . ' S ? ␦ t @ Ž 2 t .y1 r2 , where 0 F ␦ F 1 and ? ␦ t @ is the greatest integer less than or equal to ␦ t. Then the functional central limit theorem implies that the distribution of the random function Yt converges weakly to Weiner measure ŽBillingsley, 1968, Theorem 20.1., from which it follows that lim P Ž 2 t . tª⬁ ž y1 r2 max S j F ␣ s 2 Ž 2 . jFt / y1r2 ␣ yu 2 r2 H0 e du Ž 9. for ␣ G 0 ŽBillingsley, 1968, p. 138, and Eq. Ž10.18., p. 72.. Define ' P Žsup t G 1 St - ⬁.. We shall assume that ) 0 and obtain a contradiction. Choose ) 0 so that 2Ž2 .y1 r2H0 expŽyu 2r2. du - 2 and, for t G 1, define A t ' Ž 2 t .y1r2 max j F t S j F 4 . Then lim t ª⬁ P Ž A t . - 2 . For t G 1, define Bt ' Ž 2 .y1 r2 max j F S j F for all G t 4 . Then there is a B such that sup t G 1 S t - ⬁4 ; B and Bt ­ B. Therefore, using Eq. Ž9., Bt ; A t implies P Ž A t . G P Ž Bt . ª P Ž B . G , which contradicts lim t ª⬁ P Ž A t . - 2 . We conclude that P Žsup t G 1 St - ⬁. s 0, or equivalently, P Žsup t G 1 t s ⬁. s 1. The desired conclusion then follows from Theorem 1 and Lemma 1. 5. THE BUDGET CONSTRAINT In this section, we address two questions. First, given an arbitrary stochastic income sequence, under what conditions should we expect the borrowing constraint to be binding at some information state? Second, how does a change in the borrowing constraint Žor equivalently, a change in the income sequence. affect the pattern of borrowing? 5.1. When Is Budget Constraint Sometimes Binding? As noted in Section 2, if the discounted value of the income sequence is finite conditional on any information state, we can represent any intertemporal budget constraint as a sequence of one period borrowing constraints. It may well turn out that none of these constraints are actually binding at the optimum, and yet the consumer is still constrained to choose a 384 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON consumption program whose present value does not exceed the present value of the income stream. Our next theorem gives conditions under which this is the case. THEOREM 7. If Ew rtq1 uqŽ x tq1 .< z t x s ⬁ and aUt ) 0, then cUt - aUt . Proof. Suppose cUt s aUt . Then P Ž cUtq1 F x tq1 < z t . s 1. Lemma 1 then implies U U q < t ⬁ ) uy Ž cUt . G ¨ q t Ž a t . G  E r tq1¨ tq1 Ž a tq1 . z G  E rtq1 uq Ž cUtq1 . < z t G  E rtq1 uq Ž x tq1 . < z t s ⬁, a contradiction. Since aUt G x t , the following corollary follows immediately. COROLLARY 3. If Ew rtq1 uqŽ x tq1 .< z t x s ⬁ and x t ) 0, then cUt - aUt . Theorem 7 and its corollary say that whenever the expected increment in disposable income in the following period is sufficiently small so that the expected marginal utility from consuming out of that increment would be infinite, the consumer chooses to consume less than his current wealth in the current period in order to pass some of his wealth to the next period. If we allow the expected marginal utility of future income to be finite, however, the borrowing constraint may well be binding, at least occasionally. This will obviously be the case if income received in each period is growing at a sufficiently high rate over time so that the consumer wants to transfer future income to present consumption. But if the income stream is suitably stochastic, a much weaker set of conditions guarantees that the budget constraint is sometimes binding. Our next theorem may be summarized as follows. Suppose the single period interest rate never exceeds the discount rate and the marginal utility of consuming from current income alone is bounded above. Then if the long run rate of interest is less than the discount rate or if the income sequence is suitably stochastic, there is a positive probability that the borrowing constraint is binding in at least one period. THEOREM 8. Suppose P Ž  rt F 1, t G 1. s 1 and P Ž uqŽ x t . - ␣ , t G 0. s 1 for some ␣ g ⺢. If either Ži. P Žlim t ª⬁ t s 0. s 1 or Žii. there is an ) 0 for which Condition ŽU. is satisfied and P Ž t ) , t G 0. s 1, then P Ž cUt - aUt , t G 0. - 1. Proof. We establish the theorem by contradiction. Suppose P Ž0 F cUt Ž U. - aUt , t G 0. s 1. Then, by induction, Lemma 1 implies ¨ y 0 a0 F U U y y Ew  r 1¨ 1 Ž a1 .x F Ew t¨ t Ž a t .x for all t G 1. We will establish that 385 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY Ž U .x s 0 and therefore, ¨ y Ž U. lim t ª⬁ Ew t¨ y t at 0 a 0 s 0, violating the monotonicity and concavity of ¨ 0 . Ž U .x s 0, we first show P Ž ¨ y Ž U. . To show that lim t ª⬁ Ew t¨ y t at t at - ␣ 1 s 1 U y for some ␣ 1 g ⺢, and then show P Žlim t ª⬁ t¨ t Ž a t . s 0. s 1. Since P Ž  rt F 1, t G 0. s 1 implies P Ž0 F tq1 F t F 1, t G 1. s 1, the desired result then follows from the Dominated Convergence Theorem. Ž U. . Ž qŽ x t . - ␣ , t G 0. To establish P Ž ¨ y t a t - ␣ 1 s 1, note first that P u qŽ . s 1 implies either u 0 - ␣ or P Ž x t ) , t G 0. s 1 for some ) 0. If Ž U. uqŽ 0. - ␣ , then Lemma A.3 and the strict concavity of ¨ imply P Ž ¨ y t at qŽ . qŽ . - ¨ t 0 s u 0 - ␣ . s 1, in which case we let ␣ 1 ' ␣ . If P Ž x t ) , t Ž U. G 0. s 1, then P Ž aUt ) , t G 0. s 1, and so Lemma 1 implies P Ž ¨ y t at y yŽ . F u , t G 0. s 1, in which case we let ␣ 1 ' u Ž .. Ž U. . Ž. To establish P Žlim t ª⬁ t¨ y t a t s 0 s 1, we consider Conditions i and Žii. separately. If Condition Ži. holds, then the desired property follows immediately. If Condition Žii. holds, then Lemmata 1 and 4 imply U U q P lim uq t Ž c t . F lim ¨ t Ž a t . F ž tª⬁ tª⬁ 1 U lim t ª⬁ t¨ q t Ž a t . s 0 s 1, / and so P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1. Another application of Lemma 1 then yields U U U y y P lim t¨ y t Ž a t . F lim t u Ž c t . F lim u Ž c t . s 0 s 1. ž tª⬁ tª⬁ tª⬁ / If the long run rate of interest is less than the discount rate, the conclusion of Theorem 8 is not particularly surprising. In this case, the marginal return to consuming a fixed level of consumption goes to zero with time. Consequently, if the marginal utility to consuming current income is bounded, then the borrowing constraint must eventually be binding. The theorem is less intuitive for the case where the long run rate of interest is equal to the discount rate Ž ␥ s 1 for a fixed interest factor ␥ .. In this case Theorem 4 implies that consumption grows without bound. Evidently, along almost every path, the asset level first falls to its lower bound at least once before converging to infinity. However, Theorem 4 implies that this happens only a finite number of times. 5.2. Comparati¨ e Dynamics Suppose the original sequence of borrowing constraints is replaced with another sequence which allows at least as much borrowing in any information state. The following theorem states that at any information state the optimal accumulated wealth under the new sequence of borrowing con- 386 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON straints is no higher than the optimal accumulated wealth under the original sequence of borrowing constraints. THEOREM 9. Let a 0 and a1 be the sequence of accumulated assets associated with the solutions c 0 and c 1 corresponding to constraints k 0 and k 1, respecti¨ ely. Then P Ž k t0 G k 1t , t G 0. s 1 implies P Ž a0t G a1t , t G 0. s 1. Proof. Let S0 and S1 be the metric spaces defined in the Appendix corresponding to k 0 and k 1, respectively, and let T0 and T1 be the corresponding T operators. Note that S0 ; S1 so that T1 is defined on S0 . Let ¨ 0 and ¨ 1 be the corresponding fixed points of T0 and T1. We shall show that ¨ 0q Ž a, z t . ) ¨ 1y Ž a q , z t . for all Ž a, z t . g S0 and ) 0. Let f 1 represent ¨ 1 restricted to S0 and let f nq 1 ' T0n f 1, where T0n is the operator T0 applied n times. For Ž a, z t . g S0 , define C1 Ž a, z t . ' arg max 0FcFayk 1t Ž z t . uŽ c . q  E ¨ 1 Ž Ž a y c . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t 4, and for n G 2 define Cn Ž a, z t . ' arg max 0FcFayk t0 Ž z t . uŽ c . q  E f ny 1 Ž Ž a y c . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t 4. Fix Ž a, z t . g S0 and ) 0. Let c1 ' C1Ž a q , z t . and c 2 ' C2 Ž a, z t .. Then either c1 ) c2 G 0 or a q y c1 ) a y c 2 . Therefore, using the standard envelope arguments exploited in Lemma 1, the strict concavity of u and ¨ implies that either ¨ 1y Ž a q , z t . F uy Ž c1 . - uq Ž c 2 . F f 2q Ž a, z t . Ž 10 . or ¨ 1y Ž a q , z t . F  E rtq1¨ 1y Ž Ž a q y c1 . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t -  E rtq1¨ 1q Ž Ž a y c 2 . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t F f 2q Ž a, z t . . In either case, we have shown that ¨ 1y Ž a⬘, z t . - f 2q Ž a, z t . for any Ž a, z t ., Ž a⬘, z t . g S0 , a⬘ ) a. Now suppose f nq Ž a, z t . ) f Ž ny1.y Ž a⬘, z t . for any Ž a, z t ., Ž a⬘, z t . g S0 with a⬘ ) a. Fix Ž a, z t . g S0 and ) 0 and define c n ' CnŽ a q , z t . and c nq 1 ' Cnq1Ž a, z t .. Then either c n ) c nq1 G 0 or a q y c n ) a y c nq1. CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 387 Then the envelope argument implies either f ny Ž a q , z t . F uy Ž c n . - uq Ž c nq1 . F f Ž nq1.q Ž a, z t . Ž 11 . or f ny Ž a q , z t . F  E rtq1 f Ž ny1.y Ž Ž a q y c n . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t -  E rtq1 f nq Ž Ž a y c nq1 . rtq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t Ž 12 . F f Ž nq1.q Ž a, z t . . In either case, we have shown that f ny Ž a⬘, z t . - f Ž nq1.q Ž a, z t . for any Ž a, z t ., Ž a⬘, z t . g S0 , a⬘ ) a. Now let Ž n . be a strictly decreasing sequence such that 1 s and lim nª⬁ n s 2 . Then for n G 2, we have just shown that ¨ 1y Ž a q , z t . f 1y Ž a q 2 , z t . - ⭈⭈⭈ - f Ž ny1.y Ž a q n , z t . - f ny Ž a q 2 , z t . for all Ž a, z t . g S0 . Since T0 is a contraction mapping and T0¨ 0 s ¨ 0 , it follows that f n Ž a, z t . ª ¨ 0 Ž a, z t . as n ª ⬁. Therefore, Lemma A.4 implies ¨ 0q Ž a, z t . ) ¨ 0y Ž a q 2 , z t . G lim sup n f ny Ž a q 2 , z t . G ¨ 1y Ž a q , z t . for any Ž a, z t . g S0 and ) 0. To show that a1 F a 0 , we again argue by induction. Fix any realization of z s Ž . . . , zy1 , z 0 , z1 , . . . .. By definition, a00 Ž z 0 . s a10 Ž z 0 .. Suppose a0t Ž z t . y a1t Ž z t . G 0. We will show that a0tq1Ž z tq1 . y a1tq1Ž z tq1 . G 0. Note first, that for any w g ⺢ N, a0tq1 Ž z t , w . y a1tq1 Ž z t , w . s rtq1 Ž z t , w . Ž Ž a0t Ž z t . y a1t Ž z t . . y Ž c t0 Ž z t . y c 1t Ž z t . . . . Ž 13 . Therefore, a0tq1Ž z tq1 . - a1tq1Ž z tq1 . implies c t0 Ž z t . ) c 1t Ž z t . and a0tq1Ž z t , w . - a1tq1Ž z t , w . for all w g ⺢ N . Lemma 1 then implies  E rtq1 Ž z t , w . ¨ 1y Ž a1tq1 Ž z t , w . , Ž z t , w . . < z t G uq Ž c 1t Ž z t . . ) uy Ž c t0 Ž z t . . Ž 14 . G  E rtq1 Ž z t , w . ¨ 0q Ž a0tq1 Ž z t , w . , Ž z t , w . . < z t . But we have just shown above that a0tq1Ž z t , w . - a1tq1Ž z t , w . implies ¨ 0q Ž a0tq1Ž z t , w ., Ž z t , w .. ) ¨ 1y Ž a1tq1Ž z t , w ., Ž z t , w ... This contradiction completes the proof. 388 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON It should be clear from our discussion in Section 2 that for any change in the set of feasible consumption programs in response to a change in the borrowing constraint, there is an equivalent change in the income sequence that generates the same change in the set of feasible consumption programs. Consequently, we may reinterpret Theorem 9 as a statement about how the optimal consumption program changes in response to certain kinds of changes in the income sequence. Our next corollary states that if the income sequence changes so that at any state z t the discounted value of income up to time t has not decreased, then the discounted value of the consumption up to time also does not decrease for any state z . COROLLARY 4. Let c 0 and c 1 be the optimal consumption programs associated with borrowing sequence k and income sequences x 0 and x 1, respecti¨ ely. Then t P ž Ý Ž x 1j y x j0 . Ry1 0 j G 0, js0 / tG0 s1 t implies P ž Ý Ž c1j y c j0 . Ry1 0 j G 0, js0 / t G 0 s 1. 1 Proof. Let k 0 ' k, x ' x 0 , and define k 1 s Ž ky1 , k 0 , k 1 , . . . . by ky1 '0 0 1 0 1 1 t and k t ' Ý js0 Ž x j y x j . R jt q k t for t G 0. By assumption, x and k jointly satisfy Ž1.. Therefore, x t y k 1t q rt k 1ty1 s x t0 y Ýtjs0 Ž x j0 y x 1j . R jt y k t0 q 1. 0 1 1 Ž 0 Ýty1 js0 x j y x j R jt q r t k ty1 s x t y k t q r t k ty1 implies that x and k do as 0 1 well. Furthermore, the definitions of c and c imply that they are also the optimal consumption programs associated with the Žcommon. income sequence, x, and respective borrowing constraints, k 0 and k 1. To see this, note that for any consumption program c, we have Ýtjs0 Ž x 1j y c j . R jt y k t s Ýtjs0 Ž x j y c j . R jt y k 1t . Therefore, a program c is feasible for x 1 and k if and only if it is feasible for x and k 1. By assumption c 1 is optimal for x 1 and k. Therefore, it is also optimal for x and k 1. Now let a 0 and a1 denote the asset sequences associated with consumption programs c 0 and c 1 for income sequence x. Then, for i s 0, 1, a0i s x 0 i. Ž and a it s Ýty1 js0 x j y c j R jt q x t for t G 1. The hypothesis of the corollary and the construction of k 1 imply k 1 F k 0 . Therefore, Theorem 9 implies 0. ty1 Ž 1 0 . y1 Ž 1 0 F a0t y a1t s Ýty1 js0 c j y c j R jt s R 0 t Ý js0 c j y c j R 0 j for all t G 1. 6. MANY ASSETS In this section, we illustrate how the argument behind Theorem 2 can be extended to the case where there are several risky assets. We show that to apply the martingale convergence theorem, it is not necessary to actually 389 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY solve the portfolio problem of the consumer. So long as the consumer is able to choose a sequence of ‘‘marginal’’ interest rates which, in the long run, exceed the discount rate, consumption must converge to infinity. Suppose the consumer must choose a portfolio of J risky assets in each period t G 0. If the investment in period t in the ith asset is bi Žmeasured in terms of period t consumption., then the payoff at t q 1 is bi g i, tq1 , where g i, tq1 is a nonnegative, continuous function from Z tq1 Ž z 0 . to ⺢q for i s 1, . . . , J, and t G 0. If b ' Ž b1 , . . . , bJ . is the portfolio chosen in period t, then the multi-asset analogue of the budget constraint is a constraint on short sales which we represent by the requirement that b g K t Ž z t .. We assume that K t is a continuous correspondence from Z t Ž z 0 . to ⺢ J and that K t Ž z t . is a nonempty, closed, convex subset of ⺢ J which is bounded from below; i.e., there is a function m: Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢ such that K t Ž z t . ; Ž ␣ 1 , . . . , ␣ J . g ⺢ J : ␣ j G mŽ z t .4 . We also assume that yK t Ž z t . is comprehensive; i.e., if 1 g K t Ž z t . and 2 g ⺢qJ , then 1 q 2 g K t Ž z t .. This guarantees that it is always feasible for the consumer to increase his holding of any asset. For any ␣ ,  g ⺢ J, let ␣ ' Ý Jjs1 ␣ j  j . Let denote the J-vector of ones, and define k t Ž z t . ' inf b: b g K t Ž z t .4 . Interpret k t as the minimum amount of wealth measured in terms of period t consumption that the individual may hold at the end of period t Žafter receiving period t income and spending period t consumption.. Let g t ' Ž g 1 t , . . . , g J t .. We require that the current bounds on short sales be consistent with the borrowing constraints the individual will face in the future: P Ž bg tq1 q x tq1 G k tq1 < z t . s 1 for all b g K t Ž z t . and all z t. For any state z 0 , a consumption-portfolio program, Žc, b., is a sequence of a pair of functions, c t : Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢q and bt : Z t Ž z 0 . ª ⺢ J, t G 0. For any z t g Z t Ž z 0 . and any a G k t Ž z t ., let K t Ž a, z t . ' Ž c, b . g ⺢q= K t Ž z t .: 0 F c F a y b4 denote the set of feasible consumption-portfolio pairs for the consumer, and define ¨ Ž a, z t . ' max E c, b ⬁ Ý u Ž c j .  jyt < z t jst subject to P Ž c j , bj . g K j Ž a j , z j . , j G t < z t s 1, ž / where a t ' a and a j ' bjy1 g j q x j for j ) t. Theorem A.1 implies that this problem has a solution and that ¨ Ž a, z t . is strictly concave in a G k t . Therefore, right- and left-hand derivatives are well defined for a ) k t . We let ¨ qŽ k t , z t . ' lim ax k t¨ qŽ a, z t .. As in Section 2, let ¨ t Ž a. ' ¨ Ž a, z t ., and let Žc*, b*. denote the solution to the consumer’s problem starting in state z 0 with wealth a s x 0 . We 390 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON shall simplify the martingale arguments by assuming that x 0 ) k 0 . The following conditions are then implied by an optimal program. They are established by the same standard arguments used to establish Lemma 1. q Ž U .< t x Ž U. w LEMMA 5. Ži. ¨ q for k s 1, . . . , J, and t a t G  E g k, tq1¨ tq1 a tq1 z U U qŽ Žii. ¨ q Ž . c t .. t at G u To obtain the analogues of Theorems 1 and 2 from Lemma 5, we consider an arbitrary marginal portfolio, i.e., a portfolio which can be added to the existing portfolio. Given our assumptions on K t , the only portfolios we might not be able to consider are those involving short sales. For this reason, we restrict attention to those portfolios without short sales. We say that Ž b 0 , b1 , . . . . is a positi¨ e portfolio program if each bt is a measurable function from Z t Ž z 0 . into ⺢qJ y 04 . For any positive portfolio program, we define the sequence of return factors by rtq1Ž z tq1 . ' bt Ž z t . g tq1Ž z tq1 .rbt Ž z t . for t G 0. The next theorem provides a condition that, if satisfied by the return sequence generated by at least one positive portfolio, implies that optimal consumption converges to infinity. Recall that R 0 t ' Ł tjs1 r j and t '  tR0 t . THEOREM 10. Suppose that Ž r 1 , r 2 , . . . . is the return sequence for some positi¨ e portfolio program. Then, Ži. P Žlim t ª ⬁ t s ⬁. s 1 implies P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1, and Žii. P Žsup t G 0 t s ⬁. s 1 implies P Žsup t G 0 cUt s ⬁. s 1. Ž U . qŽ U . Proof. Ži. Define d 0 ' 1 and d t ' t¨ q t a t r¨ 0 a 0 . Lemma 5 imU q t qŽ U . plies that ¨ t a t G  Ew rtq1¨ tq1Ž a tq1 .< z x from which it follows that d t is a nonnegative supermartingale. Therefore, there is a random variable d⬁ with Ew d⬁ x F 1 and P Žlim t ª⬁ d t s d⬁ . s 1 ŽDoob, 1953, p. 324.. So if Ž U. t ª ⬁, it follows that ¨ q t a t ª 0, and therefore, from Lemma 5 that qŽ U . u c t ª 0, from which we conclude that P Žlim t ª⬁ cUt s ⬁. s 1. Žii. If t ª ⬁ along a subsequence, then, along that subsequence, U qŽ U . Ž . ¨q a c t ª 0 and therefore, P Žsup t cUt s ⬁. s 1. t t ª 0 which implies u We emphasize that there need be no relation between the optimal portfolio and the positive portfolio program that generates the sequence of interest rates used in Theorem 10. APPENDIX We establish the existence of an optimal solution for the problem presented in Section 6 where the consumer must choose an optimal portfolio and consumption program in each period. Recall that z t g ⺢ n 391 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY and for any z 0 s Ž . . . , zy1 , z 0 ., Z t Ž z 0 . ' z t : z t s Ž z 0 , z1 , . . . , z t .4 . Fix z 0 . Let Ž S, d . denote the metric space defined by S ' Ž a, z t .: a G k t Ž z t ., z t g Z t Ž z 0 ., t s 0, 1, . . . 4 , and d Ž Ž a, z t . , Ž a⬘, z j . . s ½ 1 if j / t max < a y a⬘ < , Ž z1 , zX1 . , . . . , Ž z t , zXt . 4 if j s t , where is the metric on ⺢ n. For any f : S ª ⺢, let 5 f 5 s sup s g S < f Ž s .<, and let DŽ S . denote the set of continuous functions f : S ª ⺢ such that M t. Ž 0 F f F 1y is nondecreasing and concave in a. Note that  and f a, z DŽ S . is a complete metric space under the metric 5 f y g 5. Recall that K t Ž a, z t . ' Ž c, b . g ⺢q= K t Ž z t .: 0 F c F a y b4 , where is the n-vector of ones, denotes the set of feasible consumption and portfolio choices for wealth level a in state z t. Define the operator T on DŽ S . by Tf Ž a, z t . ' u Ž c . q  E f Ž bg tq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t 4 . sup Ž c, b .gK t Ž a, z t . LEMMA A.1. T is a contraction mapping DŽ S . into DŽ S .. Proof. We show first that f g DŽ S . implies Tf g DŽ S .. Suppose f g M DŽ S .. It is immediate that 0 F Tf F 1 y  and that Tf is monotone nondecreasing. We show next that Tf is continuous. Since dŽ s, s⬘. - 1 implies t s t⬘, we suppress the dependence on t and let z denote z t. For w g ⺢ n, define mŽ b, z, w . ' f Ž bg tq 1Ž z, w . q x tq 1Ž z, w ., Ž z, w .. and let hŽ b, z . ' H mŽ b, z, w . pŽ dw < z .. Then Tf Ž a, z . s supŽ c, b.g K t Ž a, z . uŽ c . q  hŽ b, z .4 . Since u is continuous and K t is continuous and compact-valued, it follows that Tf is continuous if h is continuous ŽHildenbrand, 1974, Corollary, p. 30.. To show that h is continuous, note that < h Ž b, z . y h Ž b⬘, z⬘ . < F Hm Ž b, z, w . Ž p Ž dw < z . y p Ž dw < z⬘. . Ž 15 . q < m Ž b, z, w . y m Ž b⬘, z⬘, w . < p Ž dw < z⬘ . . H Define dŽŽ b, z ., Ž b⬘, z⬘.. ' max 1Ž b, b⬘., 2 Ž z, z⬘.4 , where 1 and 2 are Euclidean metrics. For fixed Ž b, z ., the Feller property implies that for any ) 0, there is a ␦ 1 ) 0 such that < H mŽ b, z, w .Ž pŽ dw < z . y pŽ dw < z⬘..< - for dŽŽ b, z ., Ž b⬘, z⬘.. - ␦ 1. Since Z t Ž z 0 . is a finite-dimensional Euclidean 392 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON space, the Feller property also implies that there is a compact set A ; ⺢ n and ␦ 2 ) 0 such that dŽŽ b, z ., Ž b⬘, z⬘.. - ␦ 2 implies H⺢ nyA pŽ dw < z⬘. Ž1 y  . - M . Since f is uniformly continuous on compact sets, we may choose ␦ 3 ) 0 so that dŽŽ b, z ., Ž b⬘, z⬘.. - ␦ 3 implies < mŽ b, z, w . y mŽ b⬘, z⬘, w .< - for w g A. Therefore, if dŽŽ b, z ., Ž b⬘, z⬘.. - min ␦ 2 , ␦ 34 , we have H< m Ž b, z, w . y m Ž b⬘, z⬘, w . < p Ž dw < z⬘. - ž M 1y 1y M Ž 16 . / q s 2 . Combining these results, we have dŽŽ b, z ., Ž b⬘, z⬘.. - min ␦ 1 , ␦ 2 , ␦ 3 4 implies < hŽ b, z . y hŽ b⬘, z⬘.< - 3 . All that remains is to show that Tf Ž a, z t . is concave in a. But this follows since u is concave and hŽ b, z t . is concave in b. This establishes that Tf g DŽ S .. To establish that T is a contraction mapping, we may use Blackwell’s Theorem 5 to show that given f, g g DŽ S ., 5 Tf y Tg 5 F  5 f y g 5. LEMMA A.2. There is a unique ¨ g DŽ S . such that T¨ s ¨ . Proof. Given that T is a contraction and DŽ S . is a complete metric space, the lemma follows immediately from the contraction mapping fixed point theorem. Define h ¨ Ž b, z t . ' H ¨ Ž bg tq1Ž z t , w . q x tq1Ž z t , w ., Ž z t , w .. pŽ dw < z t .. Since u and h ¨ are continuous functions and K t is a continuous, compact-valued correspondence, it follows that we can select measurable functions, C and B, such that for all z t and all a G k Ž z t ., Ž C Ž a, z t ., B Ž a, z t .. g K t Ž a, z t . and ¨ Ž a, z t . ' u Ž C Ž a, z t . . q  E ¨ Ž B Ž a, z t . g tq1 q x tq1 , z tq1 . < z t for all Ž a, z t . g S. ŽSee Hildenbrand, 1974, Corollary, p. 30, Proposition 1, p. 22, and Lemma 1, p. 55.. Furthermore, C is unique since u is strictly concave, h ¨ is concave in b, and K t is convex-valued. For any z t and any a G k t Ž z t ., define the random variables a* s U Ž a t , aUtq1 , . . . ., c* s Ž cUt , cUtq1 , . . . ., and b* s Ž b*t , bUtq1 , . . . . recursively as follows: aUt ' a, and for j G t, cUj ' C Ž aUj , z j ., bUj ' B Ž aUj , z j ., and aUj ' bUjy1 g j Ž z j . q x j Ž z j .. The next theorem establishes that Žc*, b*. is an optimal consumption-portfolio program for the consumer, and a* is the corresponding sequence of wealth levels when starting with wealth level a and state z t. 393 CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY THEOREM A.1. Ži. Žc*, b*. maximizes EwÝ⬁jst uŽ c j .  jyt < z t x subject to P ŽŽ c j , bj . g K j Ž a j , z j ., j G t < z t . s 1, where a t ' a and a j ' bUjy1 g j Ž z j . q x j Ž z j . for j ) t. Žii. For a G k t Ž z t ., ¨ Ž a, z t . s EwÝ⬁jst uŽ cUj .  jyt < z t x, which is a strictly conca¨ e function of a. Proof. It follows from Lemma A.2 and Strauch Ž1966, Theorem 5.1b. that ¨ Ž a, z t . s EwÝ⬁jst uŽ cUt .  jyt < z t x. Condition Ži. then follows from Blackwell’s Theorem 6. The strict concavity of ¨ follows from the strict concavity of u. The following results are used in Sections 4 and 5. As in those sections, Lemma A.3 is restricted to the case where there is only one asset and income is defined so that x t G 0 and k t s 0 for all t G 0. As in the text, we let ¨ t Ž a. ' ¨ Ž a, z t .. LEMMA A.3. qŽ . Ž . P Ž  rt F 1, t G 1. s 1 implies P Ž ¨ q 0 , t G 0. s t 0 su 1. Ž . Proof. Without loss of generality it is sufficient to prove that ¨ q 0 0 s qŽ . . u 0 . Note first that if u 0 s ⬁, the lemma follows immediately from Lemma 1 of the text. So we may suppose that uqŽ 0. - ⬁. Since Lemma 1 qŽ . qŽ . Ž . Ž . implies ¨ q 0 , we need to show that ¨ q 0 . Let c 0 and c 0 0 Gu 0 0 Fu denote the optimal consumption programs for a0 s 0 and a0 s ) 0, respectively, and let a 0 and a denote the corresponding sequence of wealth levels. We show first that P Ž a0t F a t , t G 0. s 1. Suppose not, and let t be the smallest j such that P Ž a0j ) a j . ) 0. For any z t g ⺢ n, we have qŽ a t Ž z ty1 , z t . y a0t Ž z ty1 , z t . s rt Ž z ty1 , z t . Ž Ž a ty1 Ž z ty1 . y a0ty1 Ž z ty1 . . y Ž c ty1 Ž z ty1 . Ž 17 . 0 yc ty1 Ž z ty1 . . . . 0 Therefore, there is a nonnull set of z ty1 such that a0ty1 F a ty1 , c ty1 0 ty1 0 a ty1 , and P Ž a t ) a t < z . s 1. From this, Lemma 1 and the strict concavity of ¨ t imply 0 y 0 < ty1 ¨y ty1 Ž a ty1 . F  E r t¨ t Ž a t . z < ty1 -  E r t¨ q F ¨q t Ž at . z ty1 Ž a ty1 . , which violates the concavity of ¨ ty1. Ž 18 . 394 CHAMBERLAIN AND WILSON 0. t 0 . y1 Ž Ž By definition, Ž a tq1 y a0tq1 . Ry1 0, tq1 s a 0 y a 0 y Ý js0 c j y c j R 0 j for 0 any t G 0. Therefore, P Ž a t F a t , t G 0. s 1 implies t E Ý Ž c j y c j0 . Ry1 0j Ž 19 . js0 s Ž a0 y a00 . y E y a0tq1 . Ry1 Ž atq1 0, tq1 F . Furthermore, using Lemma 1 and the strict concavity of u and ¨ t , it also follows from P Ž a0t F a t , t G 0. s 1 that P Ž c t0 F c t , t G 0. s 1. Then, t . since P Ž  rt F 1, t G 1. s 1 implies P Ž Ry1 0 t G  , t G 0 s 1, it follows from the concavity of u that ¨ 0 Ž . y ¨ 0 Ž 0. s E ⬁ Ý Ž u Ž c t . y u Ž c t0 . .  t ts0 FE ⬁ Ý uq Ž c t0 . Ž c j y c j0 .  t Ž 20 . ts0 FE ⬁ Ý uq Ž c t0 . Ž c j y c j0 . Ry1 0t F uq Ž 0 . . ts0 Letting go to zero proves the result. The arguments behind Lemma A.3 exploit only the strict concavity of u. As long as ¨ is well defined, the conclusions still follow. LEMMA A.4. Let D be an open, con¨ ex subset of ⺢ and let Ž f j : D ª ⺢, j G 1. be a sequence of conca¨ e functions such that f j Ž x . ª f 0 Ž x . for all qŽ . yŽ . Ž . Ž . x g D. Then fq x and fy 0 x F lim inf jª⬁ f j 0 x G lim sup jª⬁ f j x . Ž x .Ž y y x . for x, y g D. Proof. Since f j is concave, f j Ž y . y f j Ž x . F fq j Then f j ª f 0 implies that f 0 is concave and f 0 Ž y . y f 0 Ž x . F qŽ . Ž x .Ž y y x ., which implies fq Ž . lim inf jª⬁ fq x . The proof of j 0 x F lim inf j f j the second half of the lemma is similar. REFERENCES Bewley, T. Ž1977.. ‘‘The Permanent Income Hypothesis: A Theoretical Formulation,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 16, 252᎐292. Bewley, T. Ž1980a.. ‘‘The Permanent Income Hypothesis and Long-run Economic Stability,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 22, 377᎐394. Bewley, T. Ž1980b.. ‘‘The Permanent Income Hypothesis and Short-run Price Stability,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 23, 323᎐333. CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 395 Bewley, T. Ž1980c.. ‘‘The Optimum Quantity of Money,’’ in Models of Monetary Economics ŽJ. Karenken and N. Wallace, Eds.., Minneapolis: Federal Reserve Bank. Bewley, T. Ž1983.. ‘‘A Difficulty with the Optimum Quantity of Money,’’ Econometrica 51, 1485᎐1504. Billingsley, P. Ž1968.. Con¨ ergence of Probability Measures. New York: Wiley. Blackwell, D. Ž1965.. ‘‘Discounted Dynamic Programming,’’ Annals of Mathematical Statistics 36, 226᎐235. Doob, J. L. Ž1953.. Stochastic Processes. New York: Wiley. Friedman, M. Ž1957.. A Theory of the Consumption Function. New York: National Bureau of Economic Research. Hildenbrand, W. Ž1974.. Core and Equilibria of a Large Economy. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press. Meyer, P. A. Ž1966.. Probability and Potentials. Waltham, MA: Blaisdell. Maitra, A. Ž1968.. ‘‘Discounted Dynamic Programming on Compact Metric Spaces,’’ Sankhya Series A 30, 211᎐216. Schechtman, J. Ž1976.. ‘‘An Income Fluctuation Problem,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 12, 218᎐241. Schechtman, J., and Escudero, V. L. S. Ž1977.. ‘‘Some Results on ‘An Income Fluctuation Problem’,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 16, 151᎐166. Sotomayor, M. Ž1984.. ‘‘On Income Fluctuations and Capital Gains,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 32, 14᎐35. Strauch, R. E. Ž1966.. ‘‘Negative Dynamic Programming,’’ Annals of Mathematical Statistics 37, 871᎐890. Yaari, M. E. Ž1976.. ‘‘A Law of Large Numbers in the Theory of Consumer’s Choice Under Uncertainty,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 12, 202᎐217.