UCLWPL 2011.01 81 Interpreting IDensification Harris Constantinou Abstract We put forward a new theory aiming to account for the interpretation of the English intensifier (i.e. himself as in John himself met Mary). We show that its interpretation is regulated by the interplay between information structure, semantics and surrounding context. More concretely, we propose (a) that the intensifier can assume any role of the component of information structure, which we assume to consist of the autonomous notions of [contrast], [topic] and [focus] (Neeleman and van de Koot 2008, Neeleman and Vermeulen 2010); (b) that the intensifier always denotes an identity function (ID) which takes a nominal constituent x as its argument and maps it onto itself (Eckardt 2001, Hole 2002, Gast 2006). and (c) that specific contextual (both sentential and pragmatic) factors can influence its interpretation. The theory assumes only one lexical entry for the intensifier and derives its properties through independently motivated assumptions, thus claiming superiority at least over polysemous analyses (i.e. Edmondson and Plank 1978, König 1991, Siemund 2000, Eckardt 2001). This proposal also undermines accounts that assume one lexical entry but derive each use of the intensifier from its structural position (i.e. Gast 2006). Keywords: intensifier, contrast, topic, focus 1. Introduction Examples (1) - (3) constitute a minimal triplet differing only with regard to the position of the intensifier. In (1) himself is found immediately next to a nominal constituent and this sentence is roughly understood as the king (in person), and not someone else, performs the action described by the predicate. We will be referring to this instance of the intensifier as the in person reading. In (2) himself is found immediately after the auxiliary verb and the example can be paraphrased with also or too (König and Siemund 1999) (henceforth called the also reading). In (3) himself is found in a sentence final position, giving rise to a paraphrase containing alone or without help (König and Siemund 1999) (henceforth called the alone reading). Note that these approximate paraphrases are merely used throughout most of this paper for the purposes of exposition and avoidance of any confusion between the many readings of the intensifier. They have no theoretical significance. (1) (2) (3) The king himself has come to the meeting (and not his secretary). (Apart from the king‘s secretary,) The king has himself come to the meeting. The king has come to the meeting himself (without anyone accompanying him). As shown in the examples above, the intensifier is never found in an A-position and hence does not receive a θ-role. Therefore, syntactically it is a modifier (or adjunct). Furthermore, it is always understood to interact with a nominal constituent, even if they are not found next to each other. In the case of (1) - (3), this nominal constituent is the subject with which the intensifier I gratefully acknowledge the Leventis foundation and AHRC (UK) for their valuable financial support. I would also like to thank my supervisor, Dr. Hans van de Koot for his advice and numerous comments on earlier drafts of this paper. UCLWPL 2011.01 82 agrees in person, number and gender1. Despite the apparent interpretational dissimilarity of the examples above, which has led to analyses based on diametrically opposed assumptions, most researchers agree on one point: an intensifier evokes alternatives to the referent of the nominal constituent it interacts with and compares this referent with these alternatives. Combined with the fact that the intensifier is universally stressed and carries some sort of accentual prominence within the sentence, many analyses (Eckardt 2001, Hole 2002, Gast 2006, among others) suggest that the inducing of alternatives arises from its interaction with the focus structure of the sentence (Rooth 1985, 1992). We think that the above view is on the right track. However, we believe that it has not been explored in sufficient detail, precisely because previous researchers have underestimated the role of information structure in their attempts to explain the phenomenon under discussion. This paper advocates that the properties of the intensifier can be further elucidated if we accord a more central role to information structure. The main thesis to be defended is that the intensifier is effectively an information structural device, in the sense that its interpretation is governed by the interpretative contribution of contrast, topic or focus, or a possible combination of them2. These notions comprise a particular component of information structure as described by Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010)3. This hypothesis is flexible enough to derive all the readings that have been observed. For example, we propose that the alone use of the intensifier is an instance of contrastive focus whereas the so-called as for use (see example (15) is an instance of contrastive topic. Their interpretational difference is primarily a result of the semantics associated with these two information structural notions. 1 This type of φ-feature specification is by no means universal. For instance, the Dutch intensifier is not specified with any φ-features. Thus the sentence in (a) is ambiguous between the two readings in (b-c). a. Jan heeft Marie zelf een kado gegeven. John has Mary x-self a present given. b. John himself has given Mary a present. c. John has given Mary herself a present. 2 This generalization becomes clearer later in this paper, when we discuss how the intensifier is semantically specified. In a nutshell, we argue that its lexical entry is specified with ID, a truth-conditionally meaningless function that maps its satisfier onto itself. Naturally, this exceptionally basic semantic specification leaves room for an information-structure oriented approach. 3 We are not the first to follow this line of reasoning. In the same spirit, Féry (2010) proposes that the German intensifier selbst can be an instance of a free focus. However, her account remains largely inconclusive with regard to the relatively free interpretation of the intensifier. Also, her account diverges from ours with respect to the reasons found behind the uses of intensifiers. She claims that the different interpretations are a result of the different domains of the free focus intensifier. These domains are determined by the structural position of the intensifier. By contrast, we argue that the intensifier’s interpretation is not determined by its structural position and that its different uses are primarily a result of their characterisation as a contrastive topic, contrastive focus, topic or focus. Bergeton (2004) also pursues a line of research similar to Féry’s by suggesting a focus-based analysis. He distinguishes four readings of the intensifier, namely the three shown in (1) - (3) plus a reading paraphrasable to even. Apart from the fact that he does not account for all the readings that the intensifier can exhibit, he assumes a different approach to derive the readings, one that is too strict, we believe, to account for all available interpretations. Due to lack of space, we do not outline Bergeton’s approach. UCLWPL 2011.01 83 Section 2 surveys some previous analyses and paves the way for our proposal. Our purpose is not to offer a full review of these accounts, or by any means of the abundant literature around the topic, but simply to expose some of the fundamental problems of certain assumptions that persist throughout the literature and introduce some of the notions that will be required for our analysis. Section 3 develops the core proposal of this paper, and derives the various interpretations of the intensifier. Section 4 concludes the discussion. 2. Some remarks on previous accounts 2.1. Previous accounts On the face of it, examples such as (1) - (3) suggest that one could try to link the interpretation of an intensifier to its position in the sentence. According to prior literature on the topic there are two ways in which one could go about doing this. One possibility is to assume that every interpretation of the intensifier is listed separately in the lexicon and that each lexical realisation is compatible with only a certain position within the sentence. Alternatively, one could assume that there is only a single lexical entry with a fixed base-generated position. Its various surface positions would then be derived through movement. On this second approach, the difference in interpretation associated with each position is attributed to a variety of contextual (syntactic, semantic, or pragmatic) reasons4. Edmondson and Plank (1978) follow the former line of reasoning and distinguish intensifiers in terms of their position. In their terminology, himself1 is always attached to the nominal phrase it modifies (as in (1)). The function of himself1 is to place the referent of the nominal it modifies in the highest position on a scale of remarkability. In other words, this instance of the intensifier marks the referent it interacts with as the least expected person/thing in the situation described by the sentence. On the other hand, himself2 is never found attached to the nominal it interacts with but still orders its referent with regard to a scale. In this case, however, the scale is defined in terms of direct involvement by characterising the referent of the intensified DP as the value most directly involved in the situation. As Cohen (1999) points out, even though the notions of remarkability and direct involvement are suggested to constitute a central component of the meaning of himself1 and himself2 respectively, they do not shed any light on the intensifier‘s function. Examples (4) - (5), taken from Cohen (1999), show that these notions are irrelevant to the semantic contribution of the intensifier. (4) The staircase wound round the lift shaft and went the whole way to the roof, though the lift itself went no further than the top floor. (Sayers 1986: p.51) My grandmother knows these things. She is a witch herself. (5) 4 As mentioned in the introduction, we do not intend to offer a complete literature review of previous proposals, but simply to briefly consider a few representatives of each line of reasoning. This is both for reasons of space and because the arguments presented here apply to all proposals which assume an absolute correlation between the position and interpretation of the intensifier, whether through a polysemous analysis (Moravcsik 1972, Dirven 1973, Edmondson and Plank 1978, König 1991, König and Siemund 1999, Siemund 2000,) or a monosemous one (see Gast 2006 for a movement approach, Primus 1992 for an analysis attributing the various interpretations to the nature of the constituent the intensifier attaches to). For an extensive literature review and criticism of the proposals outlined here see Cohen (1999), Eckardt (2001), Siemund (2000), Gast (2006), Tavano (2006). UCLWPL 2011.01 84 In (4), the lift, despite being modified by himself1, is not understood as being ordered in a scale of remarkability or even as being remarkable at all. A similar problem is raised by (5), an instance of himself2, in which my grandmother is not understood as being more directly involved in being characterised as a witch compared to the rest of the people who are witches. König (1991, 2001), König and Siemund (1999) and Siemund (2000)5 also follow the first line of reasoning and (at least) draw a clear link between focus particles such as also, only, and too and the intensifier. They distinguish three different intensifiers, namely the adnominal (in person reading), the adverbial inclusive (also reading), and the adverbial exclusive (alone reading). What seems to be the underlying connection between these three lexical entries is the notion of centrality (see Baker 1995 for a similar notion, namely of discourse prominence). According to König and Siemund, all intensifiers characterise the referent of the DP they interact with as ‗central‘, and oppose it to a set of alternative values which are ‗peripheral‘ to the head DP. For example, the king in (1) - (3) is not compared with just any alternative but only with ones that are peripheral to the king, such as the king‘s family or the king‘s staff. Apart from their interpretational variation (as described in the first paragraph of the present paper), what distinguishes the adverbial types from the adnominal is their distribution. As its name indicates, the adnominal intensifier is assumed to be a nominal modifier, hence is usually found next to an NP, whereas the adverbial intensifiers are assumed to be verbal modifiers, hence occurring somewhere in the VP domain. The main argument, however, in favour of the view that the three uses of the intensifier are a clear case of polysemy is the ability to build grammatical (laboratory) sentences exhibiting all the uses simultaneously, as the example below of Siemund (2000) shows. (6) Bill himself has himself not found the answer himself. However, Gast (2006) shows that the above example does not necessarily illustrate the polysemous nature of the intensifier. He follows König and Siemund with regard to the possible interpretations that the intensifier can have (i.e. exclusive adverbial, inclusive adverbial, adnominal), assuming though a single lexical entry, whose denotation is the identity function ID that takes a nominal constituent x as its argument and maps it onto itself. This minimal semantics combined with the assumption that the intensifier always interacts with the focus structure of the sentence derives some of its interpretational properties (such as the evoking of alternatives). In particular, he assumes that the intensifier is always base-generated in a position attached to the DP it modifies. Its various positions are accounted for by assuming that the complex of DP and associated intensifier undergoes several steps of movement and may strand the intensifier at any point in the course of the derivation. This is illustrated in (7) for the exclusive interpretation. (7) I1 always [TP t1 [do my homework]2 [vP [DP t1 myself] t2 ]]. In this example the following operations are assumed to take place: i) do is moved to T0, ii) the complement my homework is pied-piped to satisfy the phonological constraint FINALFOCUS (see Larson 1988 for an analysis of pied-piping that fits this proposal and Büring 2001 for discussion of FINALFOCUS) iii) the subject DP associated with the intensifier, I, initially moves 5 For an extended criticism of this approach see the works themselves in which the authors recognise that their analysis faces some serious problems mostly related to the parallelism with focus particles (König 1991, König and Siemund 1999, Siemund 2000, König 2001) or Eckardt (2001), Bergeton (2004), Gast (2006). UCLWPL 2011.01 85 to [Spec,TP] and then to [Spec,FinP]6. As is evident from the derivation, the movement of material across the intensifier is licensed by the FINALFOCUS constraint (the subsequent movement operation is assumed to result from [Spec,FinP] attracting the subject). However, when it comes to the inclusive intensifier, which, according to Gast, can occur either in postauxiliary position or sentence-finally, the same phonological constraint is suspiciously less stringent7. Regarding the interpretational differences between the adnominal and the two adverbial instances of the intensifier, Gast suggests that they result from their structural position, which in turn forces them to interact with different types of constituents. Whereas the adnominal only interacts with a DP, the two adverbials interact with the entire predication. The interpretational difference between the two adverbial instances is the outcome of the assumption that the inclusive use is structurally located outside the VP, whereas the exclusive use is located within the VP. This assumption is based on the argument that the exclusive use is invariably within the scope of negation, whereas the inclusive one is always outside the scope of negation (but see Eckardt 2001 for problems with this generalisation)8. From a purely conceptual point of view, we find it implausible that the well-known crosslinguistic freedom in the distribution of intensifiers should follow from a conspiracy of movement operations. In Gast‘s proposal, trying to do so comes at the price of associating each positional variant of the intensifier with quite ad hoc assumptions about the movement triggers in the sentences that contain them. What matters most here, however, is the fact that Gast ties every meaning of the intensifier to a particular structural position, and as illustrated later in this paper, such an approach accounts only for a fraction of the data. 2.2. One lexical entry, many structural positions (round 1) The common characteristic of the accounts outlined so far is the fact that they assume a correlation between the structural position of the intensifier and its interpretation. In other words, they predict that an intensifier found attached to the nominal DP it interacts with cannot have the same interpretation as one that is not adnominal. This prediction is immediately falsified by the following examples, where the continuation and not his secretary ensures that the interpretation of the intensifier remains stable across the board. (8) a. The director himself has appeared, and not his secretary. b. The director has himself appeared, and not his secretary. c. The director has appeared himself, and not his secretary. Note that our informants have explicitly stated that the above examples do not differ in the slightest either with regard to grammaticality or interpretation. Their interpretation is consistent 6 Note that these are not the only movement operations that Gast assumes. In order to derive the sentence final inclusive intensifier in Swedish, he further assumes that the whole verb phrase moves across the intensifier to some position above TP. This type of movement is widely known as “heavy shift”. The Swedish example below shows this process (taken from Gast (2006: p. 91)) a) ...för att jag3 [t2 har levt i Oslo]1 [t3 själv]2 t1 . . because I have lived in Oslo myself 7 The same point is valid for the adnominal intensifier found next to the subject of the sentence, or for any instance of the intensifier which is not sentence final (remember that intensifiers are always stressed). 8 Due to lack of space we do not offer a full review of Gast’s analysis. UCLWPL 2011.01 86 with the widely adopted view that the intensifier evokes alternatives to the referent of the intensified DP, whilst at the same time excluding them (what König 1991, Siemund 2000 and Gast 2006, among others, call the adnominal meaning). In the case of (8a-c) the contrasting alternative is the director’s secretary. What becomes apparent from (8a-c) is that the context, and not the structural position of the intensifier, is the decisive factor for its interpretation. Note that if it was the case that this intensifier meaning was intrinsically tied to the adnominal structural position, the sentences (8b-c) should at least be rendered infelicitous due to the strong effect of the surrounding context. Indeed, the linguistic context supplied in these examples should be incompatible with the meaning of the intensifier. The examples below apply the same test to the remaining two readings of the intensifier that we have encountered up to now (paraphrased as also and alone/by x-self). (9) Context: Speaker A: Being poor is tough. a. Speaker B: Yes, I know, I myself have been poor and I remember it wasn‘t easy. b. Speaker B: Yes, I know, I have myself been poor and I remember it wasn‘t easy. c. Speaker B: Yes, I know, I have been poor myself and I remember it wasn‘t easy. (10) Context: Speaker A: John found the way to the station with his brother. a. Speaker B: ? No, no John himself has found the way to the station. b. Speaker B: ? No, no John has himself found the way to the station. c. Speaker B: No, no John has found the way to the station himself. The examples in (9a-c) illustrate the same point as before but with the also reading of the intensifier. This reading exhibits the same distributional flexibility found with the in person one. The relative infelicity of (10a-b), however, is unexpected, given what we concluded with regard to the other two readings of the intensifier. As evident from (10a-c), the alone reading of the intensifier seems to prefer a post-verbal position. It cannot be the case that this position is tied to this reading because we have already seen examples where a post-verbal intensifier does not have the alone reading. Another idiosyncrasy of this reading is that it imposes restrictions on the event-type of the predication it is found in. As König (1991) points out, this reading is present only in sentences describing non-repeatable activities. Siemund (2000) elaborates on this idea and suggests that the alone/by x-self reading is only compatible with verbs denoting accomplishments or achievements (the examples in (10) all have interpretations compatible with this claim). This is illustrated in the example provided by Gast (2006) in (11), which becomes infelicitous if we attempt to interpret myself in this way (alone). This is due to the stative nature of the verb to be. (11) # I am a gardener myself. In section 3 we argue that both the incompatibility of this reading with stative verbs and its restriction to post-verbal positions is a consequence of the nature of the evoked alternatives. For the time being, note that the wider context is a crucial factor in defining the interpretation of the intensifier. The example below, which repeats (10c) but with a different context, is intended to show that intra-sentential factors (i.e. type of predicate) do not have anything to do with the choice of the reading. Hence, this time the preferred reading is the also one. (12) Speaker A: Bill managed to find the way to the station the other day, surprisingly! UCLWPL 2011.01 87 Speaker B: Well, he is not the only one! John found the way to the station himself! The overall discussion up to this point leads us to the conclusion that approaches which correlate a particular interpretation of the intensifier with a syntactic position are far too restrictive. Evaluating these accounts from a purely interpretational perspective illustrates the same point; assuming two or three fixed readings for the intensifier is again far too restrictive. There is an abundance of interpretations of the intensifier; Cohen (1999) provides us with the example in (13), in which the intensifier has a reading closely paraphrasable to even (henceforth called the even reading); a reading akin to the focus particle only is shown in (14) (henceforth called the only reading), even though it is not perfectly felicitous (see section 3 for an explanation); finally, a reading similar to the phrase as far as x is concerned (or as for x) (henceforth called the as for reading) is illustrated in (15)9. (13) Clinton himself will vote for the Republicans. (paraphrase: Even Clinton will ...) (14) Speaker A: Mary gave Jane her syntax course-book and all the notes before leaving the university. At least that what she told me! Speaker B: ?Well, you must have misheard! Mary gave the syntax course-book itself, and threw away the notes. (paraphrase: ... Mary gave John only the syntax ...) (15) Speaker A: How was your first flight to the US? (Speaker B is afraid of flying) Speaker B: Well, the flight itself was ok, but seriously... you don‘t want to know about the landing! (paraphrase: Well, as for the flight, it was ok, ...) Up to this point we have pin-pointed six readings of the intensifier, and there may well be others. Our intention though is not simply to spell out a full list of the interpretations of the intensifier. Instead, we attempt (in section 3) to provide a uniform treatment of intensifiers that assumes a single lexical entry, while being flexible enough to accommodate and predict all the possible readings of the intensifier. 2.3. One lexical entry, many structural positions (round 2) Contrary to the empirical character of the arguments presented above, we now attempt to argue for a common lexical entry for all the uses of the intensifier based on arguments of a more conceptual basis, which in turn are based on empirical observations found in the literature. The first argument is based on the (obvious) observation that the various readings of the intensifier (i.e. himself) do not affect its morphological make-up. For researchers who assume a different lexical entry for each of these readings, this amounts to the claim that a single word can have at least six different lexical entries (these are the readings we detected up to this point). On top of this, the same word serves the purpose of being a reflexive in English, thus adding one more entry, leaving us with at least seven entries. Clearly, this is theoretically unattractive. Moreover, to our knowledge, there is no other word in the language with so many lexical entries. Note that 9 The reading is most easily accessible with a B-accent, characteristic of contrastive topics (Jackendoff 1972), maximally realised as L+H* and followed by a default low tone and a high boundary tone (L H%) on the intensifier. Contrastive topic is indicated with double underlining throughout the rest of the paper. UCLWPL 2011.01 88 the situation in English is not unique. Cross-linguistically, numerous languages10 encode all the different readings of the intensifier with one word (i.e. Dutch: zelf, German: selbst, Greek: o idios). Moravcsik (1972), Siemund (2000), and Gast (2006), among others, argue that the different uses of the intensifier impose dissimilar selectional restrictions on the nominal constituent it interacts with. No consensus has been reached with regard to this issue. For example, Siemund (2000) argues that the in person reading does not impose any restrictions on its head-DP, thus it can denote anything (i.e. [±human])11, whereas the alone reading cannot interact with DPs denoting anything other than humans and higher animals. The same author suggests that the also reading can only interact with humans. On the other hand, Gast (2006) counter-argues the above claims on the basis of examples such as (16) and (17). (16) Any business that stores sufficiently large amounts of hazardous waste can be a storage facility even if it is merely storing the waste that it produced itself on the site where it was produced. (17) We are works of art, belonging to a world that is itself an aesthetic phenomenon. Examples (16) and (17) illustrate that no selectional restrictions on the associate DP in terms of an animacy hierarchy are imposed by the alone and also readings, respectively. The example below illustrates that the even reading does not impose any animacy-related selectional restrictions on its associate DP either. (18) Context: Two geologists are discussing the fact that Japan’s earthquake was so strong that it was supposedly felt all over the world. It is shared knowledge between them that France is the most distant country from Japan. Japan‘s earthquake was massive! The whole world felt the shake. France itself felt the hit. Examples (14) – (18) force us to conclude that the different readings of the intensifier do not impose any restrictions with regard to the animacy status of their head-DP12. This common property of all readings of the intensifier provides more support for an account assuming a single lexical entry. 10 We have not been able to find a study that checks this parameter. We suspect from König and Siemund’s cross-linguistic morphological comparison between intensifiers and reflexives (WALS, 27.3.2011) that most languages encode the various readings of the intensifier in one word. 11 There is consensus for the in person reading’s absence of animacy-related restrictions. Irrespectively of this point, we take it for granted that everyone agrees that all the readings can interact with human referents, and therefore do not provide any examples of such uses. 12 Of course it is not expected that the intensifier will exhibit the same behavior with regard to animacy restrictions on its associated DP universally. Gast (2009) discusses this issue and illustrates that in Japanese there is one intensifier that can interact only with animate DPs, namely jishin, and one intensifier that can interact only with inanimate DPs, namely jitai. As he explains, the reason for this discrepancy is associated with the historical origin of each word. For example, jishin is lexically derived from the word body, hence its use is restricted to animate DPs (things which have bodies). What we do expect however, is for one and the same morphological word not to have different selectional restrictions across different readings. UCLWPL 2011.01 89 Aside from the animacy restrictions just discussed, there has been no consensus in relation to whether the intensifier can interact with indefinite DPs, and if so, on which readings. Moravcsik (1972) provides the minimal pair example below aiming to illustrate that an in person reading is not able to interact with indefinites, while an alone reading is. (19) a. An engineer should know this himself. b. ?An engineer himself should know this. We believe that examples such as the above have misled various researchers towards accounting for the wrong facts. Eckardt (2001), for example, takes this picture for granted and assumes a different semantics for each variant (head-adjacent vs head-distant), particularly tailored to express that the head-distant (or adverbial) occurrences can interact with indefinites whereas the head-adjacent ones cannot. Following Siemund (2000), we would like to argue that, despite appearances, all the readings are equally incapable of interacting with true indefinites. The word true is meant to exclude indefinite DPs which have a generic or specific interpretation. As pointed out by Siemund, the apparent ability of the alone reading to interact with indefinites is owed to the fact that these DPs are invariably interpreted as generic or specific13. Indeed, (19a) has a generic reading. (20) illustrates that despite its indefinite nature, a general must be interpreted as specific in the sense that a particular general is under discussion (Siemund, 2000). (20) A general has commanded the army himself. This conclusion is in agreement with the fact that regardless of the reading of the intensifier, it cannot interact with the indefinite pronoun someone as long as it is not read specifically. This is exemplified below for the alone reading ((21) is provided by Siemund (2000)). (21) ? Someone wrote me a letter himself. Note that the example in (19b) can be rendered felicitous when a suitable context is provided that forces the indefinite‘s interpretation to become generic, as shown in (22). (22) Context: Discussion about what responsibilities engineers and their assistants are supposed to have Speaker A: I think that an engineer‘s assistant is responsible for knowing what new research is being developed. Speaker B: No, I disagree, I think an engineer himself should know this. The examples below illustrate the same point for the also (23), even (23), and as for (24) readings. The only way for (23) - (24) to be felicitous is if the DP in question is interpreted as a generic or specific indefinite. Note that in (23) the intensifier can be an instance of either the also or the even reading. (23) a. Context: The whole country was surprised by the recent political scandals. 13 We remain agnostic as to why this reading is less contextually dependent compared to the rest of the readings in terms of its ability to achieve a generic/specific interpretation on the indefinite. UCLWPL 2011.01 90 A politician was surprised himself. (generic/specific reading) b. #A politician was surprised himself. (true indefinite reading) (24) a. Context: Discussing about which animals can be pets. Speaker A: Even though the dog is a species that comes from the wolf, it can easily be a pet. Speaker B: Well, I don‘t know whether this is the case for every dog breed, but a wolf itself can certainly not be someone‘s pet. (generic reading). b. # A wolf itself can certainly live less than a hundred years. (true indefinite reading) Again, we reach the same conclusion as with the animacy parameter. There is no variation between the intensifier readings as far as the definiteness nature of the head-DP is concerned. None of them can interact with a true indefinite DP; a commonality that on the one hand again points towards one lexical entry and on the other indicates a fundamental property of the intensifier (the centrality effect). This is discussed in the next section, the core proposal of the paper14. 3. Deriving the various readings of the intensifier (the proposal) We propose that an intensifier and its associate DP always fulfil the information-structural role of a topic or a focus. Furthermore, it may or may not be interpreted contrastively, just like topics or foci that lack an intensifier. The presence of the intensifier gives rise to an additional interpretive effect though: the characterisation of the value denoted by the associate DP as central. In section 3.1. we discuss, and adopt, Eckardt‘s (2001) insight that the intensifier denotes a truth-conditionally meaningless function ID (x). The exact predictions of our proposal depend on one‘s view of information structure and particularly the interpretations of topics, foci and contrast. Hence in section 3.2. we outline Neeleman and Vermeulen‘s (2010) approach towards these notions, which is (slightly modified but essentially) adopted in this paper. In sections 3.3. 3.10. we discuss how the various readings of the intensifier-associate DP constructions fit with the information structural typology of Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) and reach the conclusion that there is only one lexical entry for the intensifier. The intensifier‘s various readings boil down to the nature of its information-structural role (mainly), which in turn is determined by the context. Section 3.11. attempts to provide an explanation of why the intensifier is incompatible with true indefinites. 3.1. The meaning of the intensifier 14 Note that, contrary to the rest of the readings of the intensifier we discovered up to this point, the only reading is not felicitous with any type of indefinite DP . This is shown below. a) Speaker A: I want to buy a pencil and a pen. Speaker B: #I think you should buy a pen itself. (specific/generic reading) This, however, does not create any problems for our attempt to unify all the readings of the intensifier under one lexical entry because, as will be discussed in detail later in the paper, what we call the only reading is not an intensifier reading to begin with. UCLWPL 2011.01 91 In an attempt to explain why the intensifier consistently evokes a set of alternatives to the associate DP that it is intuitively linked to, Eckardt (2001) proposes that it is the intensifier‘s interaction with focus, and not a property of the intensifier itself, that is responsible for it. In particular, Eckardt, who follows Moravcsik (1972), suggests that the core meaning contribution of the intensifier is the identity function ID on the domain of objects De. (25) ID: De De ID (α) = α for all α ∈ De According to this analysis, the intensifier is merely lexically specified with ID, which takes as its input value a nominal constituent x, the associate DP, and maps it onto the same output value. (26) exemplifies this operation for the DP John himself. (26) 〚[John] himself〛 = ID (〚John〛) = 〚John〛 Adopting the assumption that the intensifier denotes ID is equivalent to saying that its core meaning contribution to the sentence amounts to nil. We agree with this view mainly for two reasons. One, it makes perfect sense from an interpretive perspective; the DP John himself does not have a different denotation from John. Two, it predicts obligatory stress on the intensifier. Eckardt proposes that the obligatory stress indicates that the constituent is in focus, and like every other focused constituent, it evokes alternatives, contributing in this way to the meaning of the sentence; hence, the invariable presence of alternatives in intensifier constructions15. However, this picture is overly simplistic. Eckardt takes it for granted that the stress on the intensifier is usually associated with emphatic focus (hence the surprise inference), whilst we have seen examples in which an intensifier and its associate fulfil another information-structural role, namely that of contrastive topic (see example (15)). Even though she notes that such a reading (with a hat contour accent) is indeed possible, she only states that this use of the intensifier, along with some other uses (i.e. in contexts of question-answer focus and of use of the focus particle only), does not express surprise. What would be more interesting though is to find out what this reading does express and how it is achieved, as well as to figure out a way of unifying all the no-surprise cases (as Eckardt calls them) with the surprise ones. The stand we take in this paper suggests that the notion of surprise is simply redundant in accounting for the full range of uses of the intensifier. Instead, we need the notions of contrast, topic and focus, as described by Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010), in order to capture the underlying mechanisms that govern the possible readings of the intensifier. We propose that the intensifier and its associate DP can potentially take the form of any notion, or a possible combination of the notions, of the component of information structure,16 15 It has to be noted that Eckardt makes the crucial assumption that the intensifier is in focus and the associate DP in its propositional background and it is this kind of relationship that eventually gives us alternatives to the associated DP and not alternatives to the intensifier itself. The technical details of this process are discussed later in this paper. 16 As Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) point out, these notions can be of a discourse nature targeted by mapping rules operating between different components of grammar (i.e. information structure and syntax). As far as we can see, this does not create any issues for our approach here. UCLWPL 2011.01 92 which comprises [contrast], [topic] and [focus]. These notions are organised systematically as shown in the table below, (first presented by Neeleman and Van de Koot 2008)). (27) Contrast Topic Focus Aboutness topic [Topic] New information focus [Focus] Contrastive Topic [Topic, Contrast] Contrastive Focus [Focus, Contrast] The table expresses that topic and focus are basic notions of information structure that can be enriched to yield a contrastive interpretation. This results in the following four way typology of information structural categories; focus, topic, contrastive focus, contrastive topic. The independent existence of these categories and their linguistic relevance have been extensively argued in various works (Reinhart 1981; Rizzi, 1997; Kiss 1998; Vallduvi and Vilkuna, 1998; Molnar, 2002; Neeleman and van De Koot, 2008; Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010); among others). As will be illustrated, the interpretive characteristics of these categories constitute the basic interpretive aspects of the various readings of the intensifier. 3.2. The interpretation of [contrast], [topic] and [focus] The Selfish Gene in (28B) is commonly assumed to be in focus because it corresponds to the whexpression found in (28A). (28) Speaker A: What did John read? Speaker B: He read [The Selfish Gene]F. As pointed out by Selkirk (1984, 1996) and others, the focused constituent receives the main stress of the sentence. Following Rooth (1985, 1992), Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) suggest that the focused constituent evokes a set of alternative propositions that differ only in the focused position and share all the rest of the material, the focus value of the sentence. The ordinary value of the sentence is the proposition expressed by the sentence. Below are the ordinary and focus values of (28B). (29) Ordinary value: [John read The Selfish Gene] Focus value: {[John read The Selfish Gene], [John read The Blind Watchmaker], [John read The Ancestor‘s Tale], [John read The Extended Phenotype],...} The information in (29) can be represented in the somewhat different notational variant of (30) provided by Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010), which we adopt in this paper for reasons of simplicity. (30) <λx [John read x], The Selfish Gene, {The Selfish Gene, The Blind Watchmaker, The Ancestor‘s Tale, The Extended Phenotype,...}> UCLWPL 2011.01 93 When (28B) is compared to (31B) below, there is an interpretive difference17. Whereas in the latter example the focused constituent stands in opposition to an alternative explicitly mentioned in the discourse, in the former there is no explicit alternative and no sense of contrast (Neeleman and Vermeulen, 2010). (31) Speaker A: John read The Extended Phenotype. Speaker B: (No, you‘re wrong) THE SELFISH GENE he read. (31B) is an instance of a proposition containing a constituent which is interpretatively a combination of the notions of focus and contrast, a contrastive focus. Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) propose that contrast corresponds to a quantifier which gives information about the relation between two sets, similarly to every other quantifier (i.e. every, some). On this view, contrast in (31B) expresses to what extent the set α of contextually relevant books is contained in the set β of things that John read. Two assertions are made: a) one member of α is also a member of β, and b) there is at least one other member of α that is not contained in β (The Extended Phenotype). The presence of alternatives and the positive statement in (a) are a result of the semantics of focus, whereas the negative statement in (b) is a result of the semantics of contrast. Therefore, contrastive focus and regular focus differ in that only the former encodes a negative statement. The interpretation of (31B) is shown below in (32). (32) a. <λx [John read x], The Selfish Gene, {The Selfish Gene, The Blind Watchmaker, The Ancestor‘s Tale, The Extended Phenotype,...}> b. x [x ∈ {The Selfish Gene, The Blind Watchmaker, The Ancestor‘s Tale, The Extended Phenotype,...} & [John read x]] Contrary to what is the case with the notion of focus, researchers have not reached a consensus with respect to the content and linguistic relevance of the notion of topic (compare Chafe 1976, Reinhart 1981, Vallduvi 1992, Lambrecht 1994). We follow Neeleman and Van de Koot (2008) and Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010), who in turn follow Reinhart (1981), in characterizing topics in terms of ―aboutness‖. Note that Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) draw a clear distinction between ‗discourse topics‘ and ‗sentence topics‘. Discourse topics refer to entities that a unit of discourse is about, whereas sentence topics refer to the syntactic constituents used to introduce a referent that the sentence is about. Since the notion of discourse topic is not directly relevant to this paper, henceforth we refer to the notion of topic as to mean sentence topic. The subject in (33B) is an instance of topic. (33) Speaker A: Tell me about one of your friends. Speaker B: Well, [Maxine]T was invited to a party by Claire on her first trip to New York. Similarly to foci, topics are associated with a set of alternatives. However, contrary to the propositional nature of the focus alternatives, the lambda operator generates utterances. The representation of topic differs from that of focus in that the function contains an assertion operator, which means that its application derives utterances rather than propositions. The 17 Instances of contrastive focus are represented with SMALL CAPS throughout the rest of the paper. According to Jackendoff (1972), contrastive focus requires an A-accent in English, a plain high tone (H*) often followed by a default low tone. Regular focus on objects is usually marked with nuclear stress. UCLWPL 2011.01 94 representation of the ordinary value and topic value (in parallel to the focus value) of (33B) is shown below as (34). Note that the representation below is in accordance to the intuition that the speaker performs the following speech acts when uttering (33B): a) Consider Maxine (out of a set of possible topics); b) I assert that Maxine was invited by Claire to a party in New York. (34) <λx ASSERT [x was invited by Claire to a party in New York], Maxine, {Maxine, Susan, Bill,...}> Similarly to the notion of focus, the notion of topic can also be interpreted contrastively. In (35), Maxine stands in opposition to an alternative explicitly mentioned in the discourse, Bill. (35) Speaker A: Tell me about Bill. Was he invited to a party when he went to New York? Speaker B: Well, I don‘t know about Bill, but Maxine was invited to a party on her first trip to New York by Claire. Since the alternatives evoked by topics (and contrastive topics) are utterances, and not propositions as is the case for focus, the interpretational effect associated with contrast is that the speaker is unwilling to make (at least) one alternative assertion. As Vermeulen (2010) points out, since contrastive topic is an utterance level notion, the reason for not committing to an alternative utterance must be pragmatic (i.e. the speaker does not want to be held responsible for the information conveyed by the relevant alternative). In a nutshell, Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) suggest that contrastive foci deny at least an alternative proposition, whereas contrastive topics indicate that the speaker is unwilling (for a pragmatic reason) to make an alternative utterance. (36) constitutes the interpretation of (35B). (36) a. <λx ASSERT [x was invited by Claire to a party in New York], Maxine, {Maxine, Susan, Bill,...}> b. y [y ∈ {Maxine, Bill, Susan,...} & (y λx ASSERT [x was invited by Claire to a party in New York])]. Equipped with the interpretation of the notions of contrast, topic and focus, and their possible combinations, we are now able to derive all the readings of the intensifier. As previously suggested, we hypothesize that the intensifier and its associate can carry these information-structural interpretations (i.e. focus, topic), or a combination of them (i.e. contrastive focus, contrastive topic). We will argue that each reading of the intensifier can be explicated in terms of the interpretive characteristics of one of these notions. The analysis that follows concentrates on the English intensifier, and as we will see the approach advocated here not only captures the readings already discussed, but makes predictions regarding the possible readings of an intensifier. Importantly, these predictions are borne out by the discovery of readings that, to our knowledge, have gone unnoticed (i.e. the reading marked as topic). 3.3. The in person reading The reading of the intensifier that has undoubtedly attracted most interest in the prior literature is the in person one. Suppose the intensifier is associated with an argument a and that P is the predicate resulting from performing lambda abstraction on a. Then the meaning contribution of the in person reading can be summarized as follows; a) it evokes a set of alternative referents that includes a, b) it structures this set into a central element a and peripheral elements {b, …} UCLWPL 2011.01 95 (König and Siemund 1999, Siemund 2000, Eckardt 2001, Hole 2002, Gast 2006, among others), and c) (P(a) is true, while application of λx.P(x) yields a false proposition for (at least) one of the evoked alternatives. These characteristics are now discussed in more detail. (37) contains an instance of the intensifier with the in person reading. The intensified value is the direct object. (37) Yesterday, I saw [DP John himself]. An important property of the intensifier construction in (37) is the evoking of a set of alternative sentences, which are formed by replacing John himself with alternative DPs. Even though it seems tempting to assume that the DP John himself is just like every other constituent that is focused, such an analysis runs into problems when considering (28) repeated below as (38). (38) Speaker A: What did John read? Speaker B: He read [The Selfish Gene]F. There are two main differences between the sets of alternatives of (37) and (38B), as first pointed out by Gast (2006). The first one has to do with the saliency of these alternatives. The intensifier in (37) invariably makes reference to contextually given alternatives, which are evoked if not present (i.e. Yesterday, I saw [DP the brother of John]). This is not the case for (38B), which does not evoke any specific alternatives (i.e. He read [The Extended Phenotype] F). Thus, unlike what is the case for (37), the person uttering (38B) does not need to have any particular alternatives in mind. The second difference has to do with the nature of the evoked alternatives, namely the fact that in the case of (37), the alternatives must have something to do with the associate DP. Moreover, the associate‘s referent must be central with respect to the referents denoted by the alternative values, the entourage. This requirement is exemplified in (39). Assuming that there is not some sort of relation holding between Mary and John, the option of identifying the referent of the alternative value (Mary) as peripheral to the referent of the intensified DP is ruled out; hence Speaker B‘s reply in (39b) is infelicitous. On the other hand, the use of the intensifier in (39a) is felicitous because the referent of the alternative value (the brother of John) is identified through the intensified referent, John, by the use of the relational noun brother of18, hence the understanding of John as being central. (39) a. Speaker A: Bill told me that you saw the brother of John yesterday. Speaker B: No, no, yesterday I saw John himself. b. Speaker A: Bill told me that you saw Mary yesterday. Speaker B: #No, no, yesterday I saw John himself. As Gast (2006) points out, the centrality effect imposed by the intensifier on its associate DP is not found in focus constructions. Focused constituents allow reference to alternatives that are only restricted in terms of their semantic type. The contrast between a constituent which is intensified and one which is focused is also visible in the example provided by Gast (2006) in (40), once we assume that there is no historical or contextual relationship between the two islands, in which Hawaii is central and Tahiti peripheral (i.e. Tahiti is financially dependent on Hawaii). 18 Note that the use of relational nouns, such as bother of, sister of etc is not a prerequisite for the felicitous use of the intensifier. See Siemund (2000) for a list of contexts that fulfil the requirements of the felicitous use of the in person reading. UCLWPL 2011.01 96 (40) a. #I have never been to Hawaii itself, but I‘ve been to Tahiti. b. I have never been to [Hawaii]F, but I‘ve been to [Tahiti]F. What can be concluded from the examples above is that the intensifier can only associate with values that have been previously rendered as central in discourse, in some way. In (39a) for instance, the alternative value brother of John is a possessive construction consisting of two entities, namely the brother and John. As Nikolaeva and Spencer (2010) point out, the relationship between the possessor and the possessee is largely asymmetric. Following various authors, they further point out that the possessors function as pragmatic anchors (J. A. Hawkins 1978; R. Hawkins 1981; Fraurud 1990; Koptjevskaja-Tamm 2000, 2004) or reference points for identifying the possessee (Langacker 1993, 1995). For (40a) we pointed out that the intensifier can be used felicitously only if a similar asymmetric relationship (i.e. Tahiti is dependent in some way on Hawaii) holds, a priori, between the intensified value and its alternative. Apart from structuring a set of salient alternatives into a centre and periphery, the in person reading exhibits one last significant function. It opposes the referent of the intensified DP to the referents of the evoked alternative values, and, importantly, excludes at least19 one of the corresponding alternative propositions. (41) means that the president, and not someone else related to him (i.e. the president‘s secretary, the vice-president), will perform the action described by the predicate. (41) The president himself will announce the decision of the cabinet (and not his secretary). Again, the exclusion of alternatives is not necessarily found in focus constructions. Speaker B‘s reply in (28), repeated below as (42), is not interpreted as excluding an alternative (i.e. John read [The Extended Phenotype]F). (42) Speaker A: What did John read? Speaker B: He read the [The Selfish Gene]F. Taking into account the interpretation associated with the information structural categories predicted by the typological table in (27) and the various aspects of the meaning contribution of the in person reading, we may hypothesize the following: (43) Hypothesis 1 (first draft): The in person reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of contrastive focus. 19 We stress the point that the in person reading is not understood exhaustively (in the sense of Kiss 1998, i.e. negates all alternatives), but only contrastively. After all, if it were the case that this reading is characterized with exhaustivity the example below should be, but is not, infelicitous. As can be seen, someone peripheral to Mary, her brother, is not excluded from the action denoted by the predicate. The fronting of the intensifier-DP construction ensures that it is interpreted contrastively (see Neeleman and Van de Koot 2008). This is in accord to our hypothesis below that the in person reading and its associate DP are interpreted as contrastive focus. a) Context: John intends to marry Mary. However, it is tradition that he has to meet her whole family in order to be approved by them. John’s mother: John met Mary yesterday! John’s father: Yes, Mary HERSELF he met, her BROTHER he also met, but he didn’t meet the rest of her family. UCLWPL 2011.01 97 Given that the intensifier i) denotes the function ID (x) (that maps its input to the same output), ii) is satisfied by a nominal constituent, namely the associate DP that it is intuitively understood to interact with, iii) is (contrastively) focused and iv) that the effect of such focusing is the inducing of alternatives of the same semantic type as the asserted value (Rooth, 1985, 1992), the alternative values that are induced should also be functions from De to De. In the case of the in person reading, we assume that ID (x) contrasts with the function DEP (x), which is paraphrased as an entity dependent on (x) (see Eckardt 2001, Hole 2002, Gast 2006 for similar approaches). Let us call this function the dependent function. This function, by definition, restricts the alternative values to x (x = the value denoted by the nominal constituent interacting with the intensifier) to only those that are peripheral to x, because it encompasses the asymmetrical relationship holding between the entity x and some other entity in the alternative value. Contrary to ID (x) though, DEP (x) does not map its input onto the same output, when applied to x (in the same fashion as ID (x)). Assuming that one of the evoked alternatives to the DP Hawaii itself is Tahiti, DEP takes Hawaii as its input and maps it onto an entity dependent on Hawaii, which in this case is Tahiti. This process is exemplified below. (44) 〚Tahiti〛 = DEP (〚Hawaii〛) = 〚an entity dependent on Hawaii〛 = 〚Tahiti〛 Note that our approach is significantly different from authors (Eckardt 2001, Hole 2002 among others) who assume that the centrality effect is a result of the fact that the alternative values are structured around the intensified value. To make things more transparent, these authors assume that the centrality effect simply results from the presence of the intensified value in the alternative values. It is true that the alternative values invariably consist of the intensified entity (and some other entity). This can be seen in (44), in which the alternative value of Hawaii, Tahiti, is indeed defined in terms of Hawaii, through the application of DEP. However, despite the attractiveness of this approach, it falls short in expressing the fact that the intensified value needs a specific type of alternatives (the entities found in the alternative values must be a priori structured in a centre-periphery fashion). The mere presence of the intensified entity within all of its alternative values is not enough. In fact, this assumption makes the wrong predictions. As we will see in section 3.6 an explanation of centrality along these lines over-generates, in the sense that it predicts impossible alternative values for the intensified value, and hence readings of the intensifier that do not exist. On the other hand, our approach suggests that the alternative values are structured around a central element x beforehand (intensification) with various means such as the use of the possessive construction or historical events that make a country dependent on some other one (see example (40a) and surrounding discussion). This asymmetric relation between the entity that eventually becomes the intensified value and another entity, both forming part of the alternative value, is precisely what DEP expresses. Of course, for this asymmetric relation (or for any relation) to exist, both entities need to be present in what we call the alternative value. Therefore, the consistent presence of the intensified value in the alternative values is merely an epiphenomenon. Notice that the assumption that ID (x) contrasts only with DEP (x) predicts that the intensifier will only associate with DPs whose denotations are central, hence the in person reading‘s observed centrality effect is explained. For the sake of completeness we would like to point out that, on a par of the possessive construction, there are other ways of expressing an asymmetric relation between two entities that constitute part of one syntactic constituent, and hence are felicitous alternatives to the in person reading and its UCLWPL 2011.01 98 associate DP. The example below illustrates this. The subject is a complex DP consisting of the head DP and its modifier. The modifier, near the table, functions as a reference point for the identification of the head DP, the chair. This is reminiscent (see above) of the role played by (and hence the asymmetric relation between) the entities in a possessive construction. However, contrary to the asymmetric relation expressed by possession, the relation holding between the entities in the subject constituent of the example below is a relation of distance, as expressed by the preposition near. The fact that we are able to define, with no particular difficulty, the nature of the relation expressed by near will become particularly important later on, when we will discuss the exact nature of the entities comprising the alternative referents of the intensified DP. (45) Speaker A: The chair near the table looks nice. Speaker B: Well, I think that the table ITSELF looks nice. The chair is awful. We have not yet explained though the requirement of this reading to interact with salient alternatives and the effect of excluding them (as will become more explicit in the representations given in (47) and (48), this reading does not interact with, and exclude, the salient alternative values themselves but alternative propositions involving these alternative values). This is where the notion of contrast comes into play. As pointed out above, contrast has two main functions. One, it refers to alternatives explicitly mentioned in discourse or evokes them if not present; in other words it requires salient alternatives. Two, when combined with the notion of focus, it excludes (at least one of) these alternatives, which have the form of propositions. Based on these parallel interpretational effects, it seems reasonable to analyse the DP that interacts with an intensifier with the in person reading along the lines of a contrastively focused constituent. A note is in order here with respect to (43). (43) states that it is the intensifier itself, and not the DP it interacts with, that is contrastively focused marked. This means that, contrary to a regularly contrastively focused marked constituent, the intensified nominal constituent is not marked as such. The interpretation of this constituent as a contrastive focus occurs indirectly through its interaction with the intensifier (and as we have seen it is this indirect route that also gives rise to the centrality effect). The representation of (37), repeated below as (46) without yesterday for the sake of simplicity, is shown in (47)20. (46) I saw John HIMSELF. (47) a. <λx [I saw x], John, {John, DEP_1_(John), DEP_2_(John), ..., DEP_n_(John)}> b. x [x ∈ {John, DEP_1_ (John), DEP_2_(John), ..., DEP_n_(John)} & [I saw x]] In order to see more clearly the effect of context with regard to restricting the set of alternatives, the representation of speaker B‘s utterance in (39a) is provided below in (48). This time the set of referents is closed and consists only of two entities as specified by the context. As the semantics illustrate below, the brother of John is represented as DEP (John). 20 We will follow this type of representations throughout the rest of the paper. However, we are aware that this representation disregards issues having to do with the position of the intensifier. This representation and every one that follows essentially take it for granted that the intensifier always takes scope over the entire proposition/utterance (as there are never variables that are closed off through existential closure), something which cannot always be right. Further research is needed in order to determine whether the intensifier is able to take different scope from the one determined by its position in surface syntax, and if this is possible, whether there are any restrictions in this process. UCLWPL 2011.01 99 (48) a. <λx [I saw x], John, {John, DEP (John)}> b. x [x ∈ {John, DEP (John)} & [I saw x]] (48) expresses to what extent the set of contextually relevant entities (i.e. John, the brother of John, etc) is contained in the things that I saw. It is asserted that one member of this set of entities is also a member of the set of things that I saw. It is also asserted that there is at least one other member of this set that is not contained in the set of things I saw (i.e. the brother of John). Similarly to a constituent marked with contrastive focus, the presence of alternatives and the positive statement are a result of the semantics of focus, whereas the negative statement is a result of the semantics of contrast. Contrary to just any other contrastively focused constituent however, the presence of the in person reading in (39a) and (46) constrains the members of the set of alternatives in such a way that only certain variants of the proposition I saw John can be included. The position held by John in these variants can only be filled by constituents denoting referents peripheral to John (i.e. the brother of John), and nothing else. All things considered, the meaning contribution of an intensifier carrying the in person reading is crucially a result of the interpretational effects of contrastive focus interacting with ID (x). This interaction evokes a particular type of alternatives, which are assumed to be the dependent function(s). We may therefore replace (43) with the more articulated hypothesis in (49). (49) Hypothesis 1 (second and final draft): The in person reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of contrastive focus and always makes reference to dependent function(s). It is now predicted that the felicity conditions of the in person reading should show parallel behaviour to the conditions of a contrastively focused constituent. A comparison between (50) and (51) illustrates that this prediction is borne out. (50) Speaker A: What did John read? Speaker B: #THE SELFISH GENE he read. (51) Speaker A: Who did you see yesterday? Speaker B: #I saw John HIMSELF, yesterday. As Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) point out, speaker B‘s answer in (50) is infelicitous in that context because the contrast implied by The Selfish Gene and some other reading material cannot easily be accommodated by speaker A. This is because the alternative reading material is not made accessible to him/her in the discourse. As a result, speaker B‘s answer is likely to trigger a request for clarification, such as What do you mean? What did he not read? It has to be noted here that the requirement for availability of salient alternatives is intrinsically connected to the main function of contrast, which is to negate alternatives. In order to successfully negate alternatives, the speaker/hearer must have them under consideration. Therefore, the requirement for salient alternatives in contrastive contexts can be seen as a by-product of the function of contrast to negate them. The situation in (51) is similar to that of (50). Speaker B‘s reply is infelicitous because the contrast implied by the DP John himself and someone else related to John cannot easily be accommodated by speaker A. This is due to the unavailability of salient alternatives that the contrastively focused intensifier and its associate DP need to make reference UCLWPL 2011.01 100 to. However, as pointed out above, if these alternatives are not salient, the intensifier evokes them. Thus, speaker B‘s reply will trigger a request for clarification along the lines of What do you mean? Who didn’t you see (related to John)? The analysis proposed for the in person reading also accounts for another reading of the intensifier, the delegative. Its use is understood as ―the intensified referent‖ has done the action denoted by the predication instead of having it done by someone else. In the example below for instance, Mary is understood to have done the action of dying her hair instead of having someone else (i.e. the hairdresser) performing the action for her. (52) Speaker A: The hairdresser dyed Mary‘s hair. Speaker B: No, Mary has dyed her hair HERSELF (and not the hairdresser). Similarly to the in person reading, the proposition in (52B) can have a continuation of the sort and not x. This is because it is understood as negating an alternative proposition that differs with the one asserted only with respect to the position occupied by the intensified referent (and the absence of the intensifier). Hence, the proposition in (52B) contrasts with a proposition of the sort in (52A). The question that arises then is how do we get the extra inference in the case of the delegative reading, namely that the alternative referent contained in the excluded alternative proposition performs an action on behalf of the intensified referent. We think that this is clearly a result of pragmatics. The delegative reading comes across only when the intensified referent has a direct interest in the action described by the predicate. In the case of (52B), Mary has a direct interest in the action of dying her hair. Note that the delegative reading is always accompanied in the predication by a possessive DP of the type her hair (where her refers to the intensified referent). The presence of such DPs is what expresses the direct interest of the intensified referent in the denoted action. Once we attempt to change the referent of her in (52), as in (53) below, the delegative inference becomes unavailable. Instead, as expected, the in person reading arises. (53) Mary has dyed Jane‘s hair HERSELF, and not the hairdresser. Another contextual factor that decides among the two readings is the type of the verb that is present in the predication. According to Eckardt (2001), the use of the delegative reading is restricted to combination with agentive verbs (or verbs denoting an action). As shown in (54), the intensifier can only be an instance of the in person reading (again as expected when the delegative inference is removed). This is because of the stative nature of the verb. (54) John is a gardener HIMSELF (not his brother). This restriction is expected once we consider the interpretative contribution of the delegative reading (see above). It is inconceivable for someone Y to be a gardener for someone X. We can think of the delegative reading as a way of transferring whatever is denoted by the predication, from Y (the alternative referent) to X (the intensified referent). The only conceivable things that can be transferred and simultaneously be denoted by verbs are actions, hence it is restricted to occur only with agentive verbs. In the same way that the in person reading requires that the intensified referent is central, the delegative reading requires Mary in (52) to be central and the hairdresser as the entourage. UCLWPL 2011.01 101 This kind of asymmetric relation is defined against the denotation of the rest of the predication, which is about dying Mary‘s hair. Therefore, we suggest the same analysis for the delegative reading as for the in person one. ID (x) is contrastively focused and evokes the dependent function (DEP (x)), whose application on the intensified referent will deliver the hairdresser in the alternative (and excluded) proposition of (52B), in (52A). This process is shown below21. (55) 〚the hairdresser〛 = DEP (〚Mary〛) = 〚an entity dependent on Mary〛 = 〚the hairdresser〛 The example in (56) further substantiates that the delegative reading and its associate DP are interpreted as contrastive focus, as its infelicity in a context of question-answer focus illustrates (for those who find this example felicitous, it is because there is evocation of alternative values that include something like the hairdresser. This further shows that this reading must be interpreted contrastively in order to be felicitous). (56) Speaker A: Who has dyed Mary‘s hair? Speaker B: #Mary has dyed her hair HERSELF. 3.4. The alone reading Example (57) contains an intensifier with the alone reading. Its use gives rise to the inference that the subject referent performs the action described by the predicate alone or without help (hence widely called the assistive reading in the literature), hence the felicitous (albeit slightly redundant) continuation of the sentence without Bill. (57) John found the way to the station himself (without Bill). In contrast to what happens with a simple new information focus (see the discussion surrounding (42), the intensifier in (57) forces us to consider someone that did not participate together with John in the action of finding the way to the station (i.e. someone who usually gives directions to John). To put it otherwise, the main contribution of this reading is to state that the intensified referent has acted without the external input of some other agent. This fact points towards a constituent whose function is to evoke alternative referents (to its associate DP) and at the same time to exclude them from the action described by the predicate. In fact, we can be more specific than that, and say that the sentence containing the alone reading contrasts with, and negates, a salient alternative proposition stating that the action denoted by the proposition containing the intensifier is carried out by the intensified referent together with some other entity. This means that (57) contrasts with, and negates, something like (58 below. (58) John found the way to the station with Bill. Following this reasoning, we conclude that the alone reading along with its associate DP is an instance of contrastive focus. 21 To save space and to avoid repetition, we do not provide a formalised analysis of this reading. The reader should assume that it is the same as with the in person reading. UCLWPL 2011.01 102 However, at first sight the centrality status required by this reading on its associate DP differs from the one required by the in person one. As pointed out above, the in person reading requires the entity that is subsequently intensified to be related in some asymmetrical way (i.e. through kinship relations, financial dependence, distance) with another entity in the alternative value. This, we argued, led the way for the intensified value to be understood as central within the alternative value. On the other hand, the alone reading does not seem to impose this kind of requirement on the entities being present in discourse. Even if we consider the most extreme situation in which John and Bill do not know each other, the example in (57) remains felicitous. In order to understand why this is the case, we need to take a closer look at what the alternative values of the intensified value in (57) look like. Once we agree that (57) contrasts with something like (58), the alternative value of the intensifier and its associate DP John in (57) must be John with Bill and not simply Bill. If it were just Bill, then we should be able to have a continuation of the sort and not Bill. However, this continuation does not give rise to the targeted reading but the in person one. The only felicitous continuation of propositions containing the alone reading of the intensifier must consist of something that means, or is semantically equivalent to, without y (i.e. not in the company of y). Two things can be concluded from the above discussion. One, the alternative value of the alone reading and its associate DP x is x with y. Crucially, it is not just y. Two, the alternative propositions evoked with the use of the alone reading are invariably an instance of a concomitant construction. Concomitant constructions are the linguistic means of expressing a relation between the entities/participants of the event denoted by a proposition. According to Lehmann and Shin (2005), the concomitant, or comitative, construction (i.e. with y) can be characterised as a relator joining x and y, where y is a participant (henceforth called concomitant participant) that accompanies or associates with x, which is another participant, usually the actor. The same authors further point out that the general meaning of a comitative construction consists of the following features (C = concomitant participant); (59) a. b. c. d. e. There is a situation S with its set of central participants. There is an additional participant C whose nature may vary. C is peripheral to S. C‘s participation in S is in some way oriented towards some central participant. The relation of C to S may be captured by an additional predicate; ultimately, C may be in a situation that is ‗co-present‘. The features that are of direct interest here are (a-d). According to (a-d) the proposition in (58), which is the alternative of (57), is analysed as follows. John is the central participant in the situation S of finding the way to the station. Bill is the participant C; he is peripheral to the situation S and his participation is oriented towards John (i.e. by helping John). This largely asymmetric relation holding between the two participants of the alternative value of the alone reading is in direct parallel to the relation holding between the entities constituting the alternative value of the in person reading. We conclude that the alone reading requires its associate DP to be central in discourse, on a par with the in person reading. Their only difference lies in the way that their associate DPs are rendered as central in prior discourse. Whereas the in person reading‘s associate DP can be central through historical events, kinship relations, distance etc, UCLWPL 2011.01 103 the alone reading‘s associate DP becomes central with respect to the situation denoted by its alternative proposition (see Siemund 2000 for a similar conclusion). Taking into consideration the overall discussion regarding the in person and alone readings, we may safely conclude that the different interpretation between them is due to the nature of the interacting alternative values, which in turn define the intensified entity as central in a different way. Whereas the in person reading‘s associate DP interacts with an alternative with the type of the brother of x (i.e. John‘s brother) (the possessive construction here is used as a representative of the kind of alternatives that contain an entity which is defined in terms of the entity that is intensified), the alone reading‘s associate DP interacts with one of the type x with y (i.e. John with Bill). However, we should not confuse the effect of context on the nature of the alternative values with their initial state in the semantics. As pointed out in the case of the in person reading, when DEP is applied onto x, the only thing that we get is an entity dependent on x, which becomes the brother of x, or the chair near x, or Tahiti only after its interaction with context. We do not see any reason why we could not suggest the exact same thing for the alone reading. This would render the x with y type of alternatives to also become contextual instantiations of the an entity dependent on x general form of alternatives. After all, this is consistent with the stand we take in this paper that it is the context surrounding the intensifier that decides its interpretation. When the context provides an alternative of the type the brother of x, then we will get the in person reading. When an alternative of the type x with y is provided, then we will get the alone reading. More concretely, we propose that the alone reading also denotes ID (x), which invariably contrasts with DEP (x), on a par with the in person reading. This means that at the level of semantics, the alternatives of both readings look the same. In order to show this whole process for the alone reading, let us assume that the alternative value of the intensified referent in (57), John, is John with Bill. This alternative value comes about when DEP takes John as its input and eventually (after the effect of context) maps it onto John with Bill22, the alternative value. This process is exemplified below in (60). (60) 〚[John] with Bill〛 = DEP (〚John〛) = 〚an entity dependent on John〛 = 〚John with Bill〛 Following this discussion, we assume the following. (61) Hypothesis 2: The alone reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of contrastive focus and always makes reference to dependent function(s).23 22 This way of presenting the alternative value of the alone reading and its associate DP may lead the reader to the understanding that the concomitant participant forms a constituent with the subject of the sentence. Of course this cannot be the case, as all of our examples show. We consider that the prepositional phrase containing the concomitant participant (i.e. with y) is introduced in a VP modifying position. We will continue to refer to this alternative value in this way, disregarding the fact that it consists of a subject and a VP modifier. 23 Similarly to hypothesis 1, hypothesis 2 states that it is the intensifier itself and not the constituent it interacts with that is contrastively focused. The intensified constituent is interpreted as if it is contrastively focused itself through its interaction with the intensifier. The reader should assume that this clarification applies to all the hypotheses that follow. UCLWPL 2011.01 104 Once we assume (61), everything falls into place with regard to the meaning contribution of the alone reading. The notion of contrastive focus will give us the requirement of this reading to interact with contextually given alternative propositions, or evoke them if not present, and at the same time to exclude one of them. The reference to the dependent function will deliver the intuitively right type of alternatives. The example below illustrates that the alone reading is felicitous in a corrective context, characteristically suitable for contrastively focused constituents. (62) Speaker A: John wrote this book with Bill. Speaker B: No, you are wrong, John wrote this book HIMSELF. In contrast to (62), which provides the suitable alternative value (John with Bill) for the intensified referent to contrast with, the discourse in (63) fails to do so, at least in the absence of any accommodation on the part of the hearer, hence the infelicitous use of the intensifier. (63) Speaker A: Who wrote this poem? Speaker B: #William Wordsworth wrote this poem HIMSELF. (63B) is infelicitous as an answer to (63A) because there are no contextually given alternatives for the intensifier and its associate DP to make reference to. In actual discourse, speaker B‘s reply would trigger a request for clarification, similarly to the case of the in person reading, along the lines of What do you mean? Who didn’t take part in the writing?. This fact further substantiates the claim that the alone reading requires some other referent(s) available in discourse for the intensified referent to oppose with. (64) provides the representation of the relevant part of (62B)24. (64) a. <λx [x wrote this book], John, {John, DEP (John)}> b. x [x ∈ {John, DEP (John)} & [x wrote this book]] (For a natural language paraphrase of the type of expressions in (64), see the discussion surrounding (48)). What (64) essentially expresses is that the proposition in (62B) is true and the contrasting alternative one in (62A) is false. It also expresses that the presence of the alone reading in (62B) constrains the members of the set of alternatives in such a way that only certain variants of the proposition John wrote this book can be included. The position held by John in these variants can only be filled by constituents denoting referents peripheral to John, of the type John with y, and nothing else. The analysis presented here also explains a phenomenon only related to the alone reading, touched upon in section 2, namely its exceptional dependence on the denotation of the verb. As pointed out, this reading is compatible with verbs denoting some sort of accomplishment, achievement or activity, and incompatible with stative verbs, as shown in (11), repeated below as (65). 24 As pointed out in the previous section, this representation disregards the position of the intensifier. It is taken for granted that the intensifier takes scope over the entire proposition, something which is not reflected in the surfaced syntactic position of the intensifier in the case of the alone reading. As pointed out in a previous footnote, further research is needed to determine whether the scope of the intensifier deviates in certain situations from its surfaced position (which is essentially what is assumed here), and if this is indeed the case, under which circumstances this process is disrupted. UCLWPL 2011.01 105 (65) #I am a gardener MYSELF. (intended intensifier reading: alone) As pointed out above, the denotation of the alone reading, ID (x), contrasts with DEP (x) which, after the interaction with the context, delivers a set of alternative values of the type x with y. These alternative values replace the intensified referent x in the respective alternative propositions. What matters here is the fact that the evoked alternative values consist of the comitative construction, the prepositional phrase with y. Similarly to (57), in which the presence of the alone reading evokes alternative propositions of the sort John found the way to the station with Bill, (65) also evokes alternative propositions of the sort in (66) (the referent Bill is just an instantiation of y). However, such a proposition is ungrammatical. (66) *I am a gardener with Bill. Stative verbs are intrinsically incompatible with the meaning of the comitative PP with y. This PP is only compatible with verbs denoting some sort of action, similarly to the alone reading that it contrasts with. Therefore, we propose that the incompatibility of the alone reading with stative verbs is a consequence of the nature of alternative propositions that it interacts with (which also partly determine its interpretation). Since there are no grammatical alternative propositions consisting of both a stative verb and the PP with y (that is consistently evoked with this reading), there cannot exist alternative propositions at all, hence the incompatibility of the alone reading with stative verbs. The assumption that the alternative values of the referent intensified with the alone reading are structured as x with y, sheds light on one other fact, again touched upon in section 2, namely the intensifier‘s requirement to occur post-verbally. Again, the nature of the evoked alternative propositions seems to be a decisive factor with respect to the intra-propositional distribution of the alone reading. Consider the examples below. (67) *John, with Bill, found the way to the station. (68) John found the way to the station with Bill. According to our analysis, both (67) and (68) can, in principle, be alternative propositions to the sentence in (57). However, only (68) is grammatical due to the requirement that part of the alternative value of John, the comitative PP with Bill, must occur post-verbally. This is because this PP acts like a VP modifier, and in English VP modifiers must occur after the verb. Now, it is well known that there is a general constraint governing the structure of contrasting propositions and utterances. That is, the contrasting elements must have the same number and type of major constituents. Let us call this constraint the parallel (major) constituency constraint (PCC). According to Hankamer (1973: 18), ―A "major constituent" of a given sentence S0 is a constituent either immediately dominated by S0 or immediately dominated by VP, which is immediately dominated by S0.‖ In other words, complete subjects, objects and adverbials qualify as major constituents, but not fragments of any of them (Ning Zhang 2007). In order to illustrate how the PCC works, take the sentence below, in which the secondary predicate drunk (another major constituent) is marked as contrastive focus. (69) John entered the room DRUNK. UCLWPL 2011.01 106 The proposition in (69) is understood to contrast with something like (70) (the choice of the secondary predicate sober is accidental). (70) John entered the room sober. It cannot be the case that (69) contrasts with something like John entered the room, in which there is no secondary predicate, despite the fact that it is perfectly grammatical, because the contrasting propositions must consist of the same number and type of major constituents. This point may seem too simple, or obvious to state, but it is enough to explain the post-verbal character of the intensifier on the alone reading, as well as its free distribution on the in person reading. Consider the structure of (68). This example can be analyzed as consisting of three major constituents (various constituency tests can confirm this, i.e. do so substitution) namely the DP John (subject), the VP found the way to the station, and the VP modifier with Bill. According to the PCC, the contrasting proposition of (68) must consist of the same number and type of major constituents. Assuming that (57) is this contrasting proposition, the only constituent found in this proposition that has the general ability to merge in various positions is the intensifier (see section 2). However, if it merges anywhere except in a VP-modifying position, which is a major constituent position, the PCC is violated (because one of them will have a VP-modifier and one will not). Therefore, the intensifier must serve the role of a VP-modifier (apart from its intensifying role). Since VP-modifiers are always post-verbal in English, the alone reading is consistently found in that position. This conclusion is corroborated by the cross-linguistic data. There are languages in which the comitative PP with y is not found post-verbally. In Dutch for example, such phrases can merge pre-verbally. In fact, they can merge in various positions, as shown in the example below in which the with y phrase can merge either to the left or to the right of the direct object depending on whether the direct object is old (first bracket from the left) or new (second bracket from the left) information. (71) Jan heeft (het huis) met Marie (een huis) John has (the house)with Mary (a house) John has built a/the house with Mary. gebouwd. built. According to our analysis, this predicts that the alone reading of the Dutch intensifier should have a similar distribution. The example below shows that zelf follows a similar distribution to the with y phrase. Note that we put in brackets all the possible positions that zelf can merge. (72) Jan (*zelf) heeft (zelf) Jan (*zelf) heeft (*zelf) John has built a/the house HIMSELF. een huis het huis (*zelf) (zelf) gebouwd. gebouwd. Being a VP modifier, the alone reading is predicted to pass all the tests that show its containment in the VP. Indeed, Gast (2006, ch.4) shows that (only) this reading can form part of deverbal nouns and adjectives, can be left-dislocated together with a VP (see also Browning 1993) and is always c-commanded by, and in the scope of, VP-external adverbials. The freer distribution of the in person reading (see section 2) now falls out naturally. Remember that the alternative propositions of the proposition containing the in person reading look different from the ones contrasting with a proposition containing the alone one. According to the analysis provided in section 3.3. for the in person reading, (73a-b) below can be two UCLWPL 2011.01 107 contrasting propositions (the intensifier in brackets shows all the possible positions that it can occur). They have the exact same major constituency structure, namely a DP acting like the subject (the director/the director‘s secretary), and a VP consisting of the verb (has appeared) and a PP acting like the direct object (to the meeting). What this means is that the PCC is satisfied without the presence of the intensifier. Therefore, there is nothing blocking the intensifier from merging in any of the positions shown in (73a). Note that this argument goes through only if we adopt the widely accepted view that the in person reading is a DP modifier (see Siemund 2000, Bergeton 2004 among others), thus not a major constituent, which may merge in various positions in the sentence (something like a floating quantifier). Thus, according to the PCC the two propositions below are still parallel, despite the presence of the intensifier in (73a). (73) a. The director (HIMSELF) has (HIMSELF) appeared to the meeting (HIMSELF). b. The director‘s secretary has appeared to the meeting. This analysis predicts that the presence of himself when it carries the in person reading is not obligatory, whereas it is on the alone reading. The examples below show that this prediction is borne out. As illustrated in (74), the DP interacting with the intensifier in (73a) can be marked as contrastive focus, and not be intensified, without loss of felicity. Conversely, marking the DP interacting with the alone reading in (57) (only) as contrastive focus sounds odd, as it leaves us with the impression that something is missing, as illustrated in (75). (74) Speaker A: The director‘s secretary has appeared to the meeting Speaker B: No, THE DIRECTOR has appeared to the meeting (75) Speaker A: John found the way to the station with Bill. Speaker B: ??No, JOHN found the way to the station. Note that (75B) is not completely infelicitous due to pragmatic accommodation on behalf of the hearer. This accommodation runs along the following lines of general Gricean reasoning; a) speaker B negates the proposition in which both John and Bill participate in the action denoted by the predicate, b) speaker B simultaneously asserts that John participates in that same action, c) speaker B is assumed to be maximally informative, therefore it must be the case that Bill did not participate in the action denoted by the predicate because otherwise the speaker would have said so. This conclusion equals to the negation of the version of the event of finding the station in which both John and Bill participate. In other words, there is negation of the proposition uttered by speaker A through pragmatics, something which leads to a similar interpretation of (75B) and (57). We now move on to discuss the exhaustive interpretation of the alone reading. As noted in footnote 19, the in person reading behaves as predicted by the semantics of contrast, which expresses that not all alternative propositions are excluded by its use. As the example below shows however, the alone reading behaves somewhat differently, in the sense that it excludes all alternative propositions in discourse. This poses an obvious problem for our semantic analysis in (64), which consists of the semantics of contrast. Remember that the semantics of contrast expresses through the use of the existential operator, which is in the scope of the negative operator, that at least one (and not all) alternative proposition is negated. Until now we got away with the use of the existential operator because we would always have examples with one alternative proposition. What would do the job then, is the replacement of the existential with a UCLWPL 2011.01 108 universal operator. In this way, all alternatives within its scope would be negated. Despite the attractive simplicity of this proposal, it raises an important conceptual issue. This change at the level of semantics is ad-hoc. It is not predicted by the theory of contrast, as outlined in section 3.2. This extension is made up and stipulated specifically for the sake of the exhaustive interpretation of this reading. As it becomes apparent, assuming different semantics for the alone reading would be an undesirable outcome for our attempt to account for all the readings of the intensifier using the system of notions depicted in (27). Fortunately, for our theory, there is no need to make such extra assumptions. As explained below, independent reasons and the assumptions made up to now suffice to explain the (apparent) exhaustive character of the alone reading. (76) Speaker A: John found the way to the station with Bill. Speaker B: No, John found the way to the station WITH MARY. (*Furthermore, he found it with George) Speaker C: No, John found the way to the station WITH PETER. (*Furthermore, he found it with Bill) Speaker D: No, John found the way to the station HIMSELF. . (*Furthermore, he found it with Mary) As shown in (76D), the use of the alone reading is indeed exhaustive. Speaker D negates all of the alternative propositions being salient in discourse, as it cannot be licitly continued by one of its alternative propositions. However, it can be seen that this reading shares this characteristic with the rest of the constituents marked as contrastive focus in (76). None of the propositions in (76) can be continued with an alternative proposition found in discourse, or, as shown in (76B), with a proposition which is not salient in discourse. As can be concluded from (77), this cannot be due to the presence of the negation. (77), which is an out of the blue proposition, also shows that the marking of the VP modifiers as contrastive focus is irrelevant to the phenomenon shown in (76)25. (77) John found the way to the station with Bill. *Furthermore, he found it with Andrew. It is important to keep in mind that the intended interpretation of the sentences in (76) and (77) is not of the type John found the way to the station with Bill and Andrew. Instead, the intended interpretation is that there is an event of finding the way to the station. Depending on the referent denoted by the comitative PP, the version of that same event changes (to be explained below). It follows that one and the same speaker cannot state more than one truthful version of the same event. It would be a contradiction. Why would this happen when himself is used on the alone reading (or with the rest of the VP modifiers) and not when it is used on the in person reading? We believe that this follows from the fact that the intensifier on its alone reading, but not on its in person reading, is a VP modifier. As indicated by their name, VP modifiers modify the VP. Since the VP is the constituent denoting the type of event denoted by the whole proposition, VP modifiers take that event and change (or modify) it accordingly at the level of interpretation. Therefore, one cannot utter more than one sentence with a comitative VP modifier (which is 25 At this point, the reader may be left wondering as to what is the empirical basis for assuming that the alone reading of the intensifier is marked contrastively. The main empirical argument for this assumption is given in section 3.8. UCLWPL 2011.01 109 what the intensifier on the alone reading is26 and contrasts with) because that would amount to stating more than one version of the same event. A similar restriction is not found with the intensifier on its in person reading, as it only interacts with a DP. Since a speaker can modify a DP more than one time in one or more utterances denoting the same event, without resulting in a contradiction (i.e. John‘s brother and John‘s sister found the way to the station. John‘s mother helped them to find the way to the station, too.), the in person reading has no problem in exhibiting its contrastive (and not exhaustive) character. This is because DP modifications simply result in different referents taking part in the same event. This means that the in person reading has the choice of excluding, as well as including, some of them (see footnote 19 for an example). On the other hand, a sentence containing the intensifier on the alone reading is incompatible with the truth of some of the alternatives, because a true alternative proposition would contradict the proposition containing the alone reading itself. We conclude that the exhaustive character of the alone reading is only apparent and falls out from independent reasons, namely its syntactic position (VP modifier) within the sentence. It follows that there is no need to change the semantics of this reading in (64). It has been shown that the (apparent) exhaustive interpretation of the alone reading is due to its syntactic status, and not its semantics. This claim is based on the fact that every VP modifier of the comitative type (including the alone reading) exhibits the same behaviour. However, the example below shows that the alone reading exhibits something unique when compared to the rest of the VP modifiers of the comitative type. (78) Speaker A: John found the way to the station with Bill and (with) Sue. Speaker B: No, John found the way to the station HIMSELF (*AND (WITH) MARY). As illustrated in (78), a comitative type VP modifier can consist of more than one referent. Since the alone reading is assumed to be a VP modifier of the same type, we would expect it to be able to behave in the same way. This is not the case however, as shown in (78B). We think that the answer to this problem lies in one of the core functions of the intensifier. As noted above, the alone reading requires a value that is central to interact with. Let us see whether this requirement is fulfilled in (78). The alternative proposition of (78B), in (78A), consists of the alternative value John with Bill and Sue. This alternative value comes about when DEP (= with Bill and Sue when contextualised) is applied onto John. Now, the function denoted by himself, ID, is applied onto John, in (78B), and delivers John. However, this time the outcome of this process is coordinated with Mary to deliver John and Mary. As can be seen from a comparison of the two alternative values, John and Mary is not central against John with Bill and Sue. This is because Mary is not even present in the alternative value to be able to be defined as central. Hence, the impossibility of combining himself and and Mary in a context like (78). The example below illustrates however that even if Mary is present in the alternative value, it is not sufficient to be rendered as central. (79) Speaker A: John found the way to the station with Bill and (with) Mary. Speaker B: No, John found the way to the station HIMSELF (*AND (WITH) MARY). 26 As a side note, the assumption that the alone reading is a VP modifier that behaves, at least syntactically, in the same way as the comitative PP with y also explains its subject orientation, as it is well known that the comitative with y PP only interacts with subjects, and never objects. This is shown below. a) John1 met Mary2 [PP with Jim1/*2]. UCLWPL 2011.01 110 The resulting contrasting values of the example above are John with Bill and Mary and John and Mary. Both referents of the latter value are present in the former one, thereby no issue arises with regard to the entities being present in the alternative value. However another issue arises. Consider the way the intensified value is being formed in (78) and (79). ID is applied to John to give us John. Only after this process we get John and Mary. However, the only referent of the two that has previously satisfied ID is John. Therefore, the resulting value, John and Mary, is odd in the sense that half of it requires to have been defined as central (because it has satisfied ID) in the alternative value, and half of it does not. This is impossible of course. The only way for John and Mary to satisfy ID as a whole is when both referents form one DP (for syntactic reasons, see Constantinou 2011), as shown below. Thereby the possibility of the second conjunct, and Mary, to be found in any other position in the sentence is ruled out. (80) Speaker A: John and Mary found the way to the station with Bill. Speaker B: No, John and Mary found the way to the station themselves. As noted at the beginning of this subsection, the use of the alone reading can give rise to the paraphrase without x’s help. In fact, for the example in (62B), repeated below as (81), such a paraphrase would perhaps be more appropriate than one using alone. (81) John wrote this book HIMSELF. Abstracting away from the paraphrase possibilities of the above example (which can be misleading), what (81) certainly does is to imply that John wrote the book without someone’s help. The identity of the helper is specified through contextual or world knowledge clues, similarly to any other reading of the intensifier we have seen so far. Even though this reading has led various researchers to assume a separate lexical entry (see, for example, Eckardt 2001), we believe that it is merely another instance of the intensifier being interpreted as a contrastive focus whose evoked alternatives result from the application of the dependent function, which in turn yields (after the effect of context) the type of alternative x with y (comitative) . The refinement to ‗without someone‘s help‘ is a pragmatic effect resulting from the kind of context the intensifier occurs in. Similarly, the alone paraphrase can also be viewed as a pragmatic enrichment of the basic opposition between x and x with y. The type of event denoted by the proposition under discussion is one factor determining the nature of context. In (81) for instance, the proposition denotes an agent (John) participating in the action of writing a certain book. At the same time (81) asserts that this agent did not perform this action together with some contextually given person. The negation of this alternative proposition implies that the referent y did not participate in the action of writing this book. Due to the nature of the event, this lack of involvement or contribution of y is (usually) paraphrased with without y’s help. It cannot imply (thus be paraphrased with) something of the sort not accompanied by y, as in the case of (82) below, because it does not make sense in that particular context. (82) John went to the station HIMSELF. UCLWPL 2011.01 111 It is inconceivable for someone to be accompanied, in the literal sense of the word, in the writing of a book. What can be concluded here is that the alone and without someone’s help27 readings are all instances of the same occurrence of the intensifier. These paraphrases are a result of pragmatic enrichment of the basic meaning of the intensifier, which we have expressed in terms of the function that generates alternatives, which are in turn realised in the specific comitative type x with y. 3.5. Interim summary We began this section with the assumption that the intensifier denotes the identity function ID (x), which takes as its input a nominal constituent x and delivers the (same) output x (Eckardt 2001). Then we reviewed Neeleman and Van de Koot‘s (2008) typology of information structural categories and hypothesised that the intensifier‘s various readings partly depend on the nature of its information structural marking. We have demonstrated that the in person and alone readings, along with their associate DPs, are interpreted as such because of their marking as contrastive focus and the contextual realisation of the alternative to ID, the dependent function (DEP). Whereas the in person reading contrasts with alternatives of the type brother of x or the chair near x or simply Tahiti, the alone reading contrasts with alternatives of the (comitative) type x with y. Both types are instantiations of an asymmetric relation (expressed by DEP (x)) holding between two entities. Unless these instantiations are ruled out for independent reasons, we expect them to interact with the intensifier, and influence its interpretation, in instances in which the intensifier is marked with the rest of the information structural categories of (27). On the other hand, we do not expect to find contextual instantiations of DEP (x) which do not exhibit an asymmetric relation between the entities constituting the alternative values. This last prediction is discussed below, in section 3.6. 3.6. The (alleged) only reading and the idiosyncrasies of each instantiation of DEP (x) Before discussing in detail the only reading, we clarify (once again) that the labeling of each reading is just one way of stating what type of alternative value each reading interacts with and how it is information-structurally marked28. Therefore, the labeling only is our terminological way of saying that the alternatives of a contrastively focused intensifier are of a coordination type. As will become clear, the point of the first half of this section is to show that the intensifier cannot interact with alternatives whose constituent entities do not relate asymmetrically. The second half provides an argument in favour of the view that it is the asymmetric relation holding between the constituent entities of the alternative that is saliently evoked when the intensifier is contrastively marked and not alternative referents per se. In section 2, we presented example (14), repeated below as (83), and claimed that the intensifier could potentially be interpreted similarly to the focus particle only. (83) Speaker A: Mary gave Jane her syntax course-book and all the notes before leaving the university. At least that what she told me! 27 For both reasons of space and to avoid repetition, we do not provide a fully fledged analysis of this reading along the lines of the alone one. The reader should assume that the analysis presented above for the alone reading also applies to the without someone’s help one. 28 As we will see later in this paper, this is not entirely true for the case of the also reading as there is an additional factor determining its interpretation. UCLWPL 2011.01 112 Speaker B: ?Well, you must have misheard! Mary gave the syntax course-book ITSELF, and threw away the notes. (paraphrase: ... Mary gave John only the syntax ...) The reason for being led to such a conclusion is the interpretation of the sentence in (83B) by English native speakers as excluding the notes from the event of giving. However, English speakers also point out that the sentence is not completely felicitous. Note that the relevant interpretation is possible only when the intensifier is marked with an A-accent, characteristic of contrastive focus. In view of the above, it could be argued that the only reading is just another instance of the alone reading. Both readings and their associate DPs are interpreted as contrasting with a type of alternative whose constituent entities denote a separate referent in the proposition (compare John’s brother with John and Bill/John with Bill). Moreover, both instances exclude the referent of the alternative which is not subsequently intensified. However, the analogy ends here. The only reading‘s alternative is a conjunct whereas the alone reading‘s is a VP modifier. More importantly, the felicity judgements do not allow us to pursue an analysis along the lines of the alone reading. The judgements suggest that there must be something else going on here. In fact our analysis predicts that the intensifier should not be able to interact with types of alternatives which are formed by coordination. This is because ID (x) requires that there is an asymmetric relation between the entities constituting the alternative value. Coordination does precisely the opposite. It imposes a symmetric relation between the coordinated entities. Hence, the only reading should not exist in the first place. We think that this is correct and the mild infelicity of (83B) is an indication of this. The reason that (83B) is not completely infelicitous is because of the entities that comprise the alternative value. The notes are interpreted as being peripheral to the syntax course-book. This asymmetric relation between the two entities mitigates the symmetric relation that the coordination imposes on them. Once the coordinate entities in the alternative value become of equal status, the felicity judgements become much worse compared to (83B), as shown below in (84). (84) Speaker A: John and Bill have become incredible students lately. Speaker B: #No, John HIMSELF has become an incredible student lately. Since the intensifier is not responsible for the only inference in (83), the question arises as to where this inference comes from. We think that the only inference is a result of general Gricean reasoning which runs along the following lines; a) speaker B negates the proposition in which both John and Bill participate in the event denoted by the predicate, by marking the intensifier as contrastive focus b) speaker B simultaneously asserts that John participates in that event, c) speaker B is assumed to be maximally informative, therefore it must be the case that Bill did not participate in the event denoted by the predicate because otherwise the speaker would have said so. This conclusion amounts to the only inference. Hence, factors independent from the presence of the intensifier are held responsible for it. The example below provides further support to this conclusion. As can be seen, the only inference is still present without the use of the intensifier. Our explanation for the existence of this inference when the intensifier is present (as in (83B)) applies to the example below too. UCLWPL 2011.01 113 (85) Speaker A: John and Bill have become incredible students. Speaker B: No, JOHN has become an incredible student. The purpose of the discussion of this section up to this point is two-fold. One, to illustrate that the only reading does not exist (and hence neither a coordination type of alternatives). This has provided further support to our assumption that the alternative value of the denotation of the intensifier, ID (x), is DEP (x). Two, to argue against the view that the centrality effect found in intensifier constructions is a result of the presence of the intensified value in the alternative values (see Eckardt 2001, Hole 2002). If this were the case, then the non-existence of the coordination type of alternatives (and hence the only reading) remains unexplained, unless further assumptions are made (see Gast 2006 for an account which restricts the alternatives using focus suppositions (a weak type of presuppositions prior to the moment of the utterance)). In the remainder of this section, we provide one other argument in favour of the existence of the DEP (x) function, and its interaction with ID (x). In doing so, we also further support the distinction between contrastively and non-contrastively marked readings of the intensifier. Finally, we discover how the linguistic constructions instantiating DEP (x) differ with regards to their specification of (un)ambiguous relations between the entities comprising them and by extension how this affects the alternatives of each reading of the intensifier. The following asymmetry between the alternatives of the alone reading on the one hand and the alternatives of the in person reading on the other appears to hold. (86) Speaker A: John found the way to the station with someone. Speaker B: No, John has found the way to the station HIMSELF . (87) Speaker A:*John‘s someone looks angry. Speaker B: #No, John HIMSELF looks angry. (intended reading: in person) As illustrated in (86), the comitative construction has no problem in partly consisting of the indefinite pronoun someone, which is however read specifically. More importantly, the alone reading and its associate DP are perfectly able to interact with such alternative. On the other hand, it can be seen in (87) that the in person reading and its associate DP cannot interact with such alternatives. At first sight this asymmetry is unexpected. One could argue that the infelicity of (87B) is a direct result of the possessive construction‘s inability in (87A) to accommodate an indefinite pronoun, such as someone. However, an explanation along these lines is unattainable once we consider the example below, which is a variation of (40). (88) Speaker A: #I have never been to Hawaii ITSELF, but I‘ve been to some (other) place. (intended reading: in person) In (88), Hawaii is intended to contrast with some place (see example (40) in which Hawaii contrasts with Tahiti). Contrary to the case of (87), the contrasting alternative referent of the in person reading and its associate DP is a perfectly grammatical construction. Despite this, the use of the in person reading of the intensifier remains infelicitous. Things become even more complicated when considering the example below, in which the in person reading and its associate DP felicitously contrast with an alternative that consists of the indefinite pronoun something. This is shown in the example below, which is a variation of (45). UCLWPL 2011.01 114 (89) Speaker A: Something near the table must smell really awful. Speaker B: Well, I think that the table ITSELF smells awful. It‘s been a week to clean it. In order to put things into perspective, we outline the problem presented by a comparison of the examples (86) – (89). The alone reading has no problem with interacting with alternatives which are partly comprised of entities denoted by indefinite pronouns (ie. x with someone). Similarly, the in person reading can interact with such alternatives when it comes to the DP modification instantiation of DEP (x) (see (89)). But not when it comes to the possession instantiation (see (87)) (in fact possession cannot accommodate indefinite pronouns) or the one entity instantiation, such as Tahiti in (40), (see (88)) of DEP (x). In a nutshell, what seems to be relevant here is the particular instantiation of DEP (x). Up to this point we have explicitly distinguished two types of alternatives (instantiations of DEP (x)), namely the comitative type and all the rest (i.e. possession, DP modification, Tahiti). This distinction was based on the different readings we get when the intensifier is contrastively focused. In addition, there is an obvious difference with respect to the nature of the (asymmetric) relation these two kinds of alternatives express. The comitative type expresses a participatory relation between two entities. The choice of this terminology is based on the features of concomitance as stated in (59). With regards to the other type of alternatives, we can generalize and state that they express some kind of defining relation between the entities that comprise them. This characterization is based on the intuition that the one entity in these constructions is invariably defined in terms of the other. For instance, in John’s book, the book is defined in terms of John; in the chair near the table the chair is defined in terms of the table; and in Tahiti, as in example (40), Tahiti is defined in terms of Hawaii. However, this distinction seems to be of no use to our attempt to understand what is going on in (86) – (89) as the in person reading seems to be exhibiting an irregular behavior. To solve this puzzle, we need to take a closer look at each of the contextual instantiations of DEP (x), irrespectively of which reading of the intensifier they deliver. Before doing this, let us see what our approach predicts. Remember that the in person and alone readings are contrastively focused. This means that ID (x) evokes a salient alternative, which is DEP (x). DEP (x) is the expression of an asymmetrical relation, which takes various contextual instantiations. As a result, we predict that the expression of this asymmetrical relation will be salient. Having this in mind, we first attempt a comparison between the relations expressed by the chair near the table and John’s book. The relation holding between the the chair and the table is clearly a relation of distance, as expressed by the preposition near (this is pretty clear-cut). On the other hand, it seems rather difficult to define the relation between John and the book. As Nikolaeva and Spencer (2010) point out the list of possible interpretations of the relation between the possessor and the possessee can be extended indefinitely, subject to contextual factors. In our example for instance, the relation between John and the book can be that of ownership, authorship or even the fact that John is holding the book. In a nutshell, possession is essentially a linguistic construction that is able to realize more than one relations. Since the precise definition of the relation between the possessor and the possessee is subject to context, it follows that this cannot be achieved without identifying the entities being at the two ends of this relation. A direct result of this is the fact that it will never be able to accommodate an indefinite pronoun, even if it is read specifically, thus we explain the ungrammaticality of (87A). Crucially, this way of thinking also explains the infelicity of (87B). (87B) is infelicitous because DEP (x) in (87A) had not even been defined for it to be salient, as required by the contrastively focused ID (x). UCLWPL 2011.01 115 However, one could still argue that the infelicity of (87B) is due to the ungrammaticality of its alternative. (88) provides the means to maintain our last conclusion. The alternative referent of the in person reading and its associate DP, Hawaii, is some place. This last expression is grammatical; nevertheless the use of the in person reading is infelicitous. The reason for this is precisely the same as it is for the case of the possession construction. Remember that in order for Hawaii to be able to be intensified with the in person reading and contrast with Tahiti in example (40), there must be a contextual relation holding between the two entities (i.e. financial dependence of Tahiti). Since we replaced Tahiti with an indefinite pronoun, some place, this relation cannot even be defined for it to be salient, hence the infelicity of (88). It follows that in order for the last two constructions we have discussed to be felicitous alternatives to a contrastively marked intensifier, only identifiable entities can comprise them. In light of the discussion of the last paragraph, we can now explain why the construction something near the table in (89A) is grammatical as well as why the in person reading of the intensifier in (89B) is used felicitously. As pointed out above, the preposition near, which is used to introduce the modifying expression of the subject DP of (89A), expresses a relation of distance. Contrary to the case of the possession construction, in the subject DP of (89A) there is a one to one mapping between a linguistic expression and a relation. That is to say, the preposition near invariably denotes a relation of distance (but not the other way around). A result of this is primarily the fact that an indefinite pronoun can enter such a construction. This is because the possibility of accommodating (on behalf of the hearer) the identity of the entity denoted by the indefinite pronoun now arises. Once the identity of one of the entities of the near construction and the relation holding between the constituent entities is known, the search space of identifying the indefinite pronoun denotation is sharply reduced. In our example for instance, the hearer knows, through the unambiguous relation denoted by near and the unambiguous entity denoted by that the table, that the denotation of something must be a thing which lies in close proximity to the table, hence the possibility of accommodating the thing‘s identity. On the other hand, in the case of possession, the search space of identifying the indefinite pronoun‘s denotation is in principle infinite (because we do not know the relation). This is an impossible task to do, hence the disallowance of an indefinite pronoun to form part of a possession construction. It is important to keep in mind that the indefinite pronoun, whose default interpretation is that of a true indefinite, is forced to be read specifically because it participates in a relation. This is because a true indefinite denotes a group of properties and a specific indefinite denotes an individual, and only individuals can participate in a relation29. The possibility of using the in person reading in (89B) now falls out naturally. ID (x) is contrastively marked, hence saliently evokes DEP (x). DEP (x) is successfully realized by the asymmetrical relation holding between something and the table, as it is clearly defined in the salient alternative proposition through the use of the preposition near. Hence, the felicity of (89B). The exact same reasoning applies to (86), which we summarize below. The possibility of a comitative construction to accommodate an indefinite pronoun (86A) results from the fact that this linguistic expression always denotes a participatory relation (as defined in (59)). There is no ambiguity, hence it can accommodate an indefinite pronoun, which is read specifically for the 29 We clarify that the possession construction can force an indefinite pronoun to be read specifically, as intuitively understood. This is because there is a relation (albeit undefined) holding between the entities, as expressed by ‘s in John’s something. As explained above, the problem lies in the fact that neither the (specifically read) indefinite pronoun denotes an identifiable entity nor the relation denoted by possession is unambiguous. UCLWPL 2011.01 116 reasons outlined in the previous paragraph. A direct result of its non-ambiguous status is the fact that the saliently evoked DEP (x) is successfully realized in context, and thus the felicitous use of the alone reading of the intensifier in (86B). The second half of this section has provided further support to the assumption that the alternative of the intensifier is a relation, as denoted by DEP. The presence of individuals in the alternatives is a result of the inducing of this relation30. In addition, we have explained why certain linguistic constructions allow for an indefinite pronoun to form part of them. Even though we have not given counter-examples, we advocated that the reason behind the (in)ability of the in person and alone readings of the intensifier to interact with certain constructions partly consisting of indefinite pronouns is the notion of contrast. The prediction is that a noncontrastively marked intensifier will be able to interact with such alternatives, once these alternatives themselves allow for such configuration (see for instance (88)). As we will see later on, this expectation is borne out. 3.7. The as for reading This reading has largely remained unexplored throughout the literature. Eckardt (2001) and Féry (2010) are the only researchers, to our knowledge, mentioning this potential use of the intensifier without, however, going into great detail with regard to its meaning contribution to the sentence. (90) exemplifies its use (remember that double underlining indicates a B-accent; in English, switch topics are invariably marked with this accent). (90) Speaker A: Tell me about John‘s brother. How is he taking the whole moving to Paris issue? Speaker B: Well, I don‘t know about John‘s brother, but John himself is fine with it. When using the as for reading in (90B), the speaker is understood to be performing the following speech acts: a) Consider John out of the set of possible alternatives John and John’s brother; b) I assert that John is fine with the moving to Paris issue. To put it differently, the utterance in (90B) asserts something about the subject referent, suggesting that the subject is a topic. In terms of its discourse function, the question in (90A) with the general form ―Tell me about X‖ invites speaker B to make X (John‘s brother) the topic of his/her utterance and say something about this X. Speaker B‘s answer however, switches the topic from X to Y (John), something which is achieved with the use of the intensifier. Notice that the intensified referent is understood to interact with another referent explicitly mentioned in discourse, namely John’s brother. This is reminiscent of the interpretation of the previous readings of the intensifier we have seen, which invariably (force the intensified referent to) make reference to alternatives present in discourse. We argued that this is a consequence of those readings being specified with contrast. The question then is whether this instance of the intensifier also makes reference to such alternatives obligatorily, or whether the reference to a specified set of alternatives, as in (90B), is merely a consequence of the context in (90). (91) gives us a first indication regarding this. 30 a) Note that it is possible for non-intensified indefinite DPs to contrast, as shown below. Speaker A: This is a dog. Speaker B: No, A WOLF this is. Importantly, the two indefinites are not read specifically, but are true indefinites. This further substantiates our claim that ID (x) interacts with DEP (x). UCLWPL 2011.01 117 (91) John himself gave the presentation he was supposed to. (91) forces us to consider someone that could potentially take the place of John in performing the action described by the sentence. In fact, (91) is infelicitous if uttered out of the blue (and there is no accommodation on behalf of the hearer). This is because the shared world knowledge between the interlocutors does not specify anyone apart from John about whom an assertion that he did or did not give the presentation he was supposed to could in principle be made. In such a situation, uttering (91) would most likely trigger a request for clarification, such as What do you mean?, in an attempt on the part of the hearer to understand who else should be under consideration. The fact that this reading makes reference to explicit alternatives in discourse obligatorily is confirmed through a comparison of (92) and (93). (92) Speaker A: Tell me about your friend Maxine. Speaker B: Well, [Maxine]T was invited to a party by Claire on her first trip to New York. (93) Speaker A: Tell me about your friend Maxine. Speaker B: #Well, Maxine herself was invited to a party by Claire on her first trip to New York. The use of a topical constituent in (92B) is appropriate in response to the request from speaker. A. Marking Maxine as a topic serves the function of introducing her as the topic of discourse, following speaker A‘s instruction to do so. This topic is selected out of an undefined set of possible topics, which in principle can be infinite. It is this undefined nature of the set of alternative topics that makes (92B) felicitous. In discourse terms, the use of such a topic does not require the interlocutors to have alternative topics under consideration. The use of the as for reading in (93B) also introduces Maxine as the topic of discourse. Crucially though, the B-accent on the intensifier expresses a discourse move constituting a switch of the topic31 that speaker B is previously invited to say something about, something which does not happen, and a simultaneous contrast between this ‗new‘ topic and the one speaker B is invited to comment on. The ‗new‘ topic must be selected out of a contextually specified set of explicit alternatives that could potentially replace Maxine. This set is not provided in the context of (93) (the set consists of only one member, hence there cannot be contrast), hence the infelicitous status of the utterance (in the absence of an appropriate accommodation on the part of the hearer). A similar case is illustrated below in (94), in which – in the absence of accommodation on the part of A – the use of a contrastive topic constituent is infelicitous because the context does not make available any appropriate alternatives for the female popstars to contrast with. 31 Note that contrastive topics are not restricted only to switch topics. A narrow down topic is also an instance of contrastive topic as illustrated in the by now classic example below. a) Speaker A: What did the popstars wear? Speaker B: Well, the female popstars wore red caftans. In the example above the female popstars is understood to contrast with the male popstars. Both values constitute part of the set of popstars. As expected, the as for reading of the intensifier has no problem in performing the function of a narrow down topic, as shown below. b) Speaker A: How did the employees find the excursion to the mountain? Speaker B: Well, the director himself hated it. UCLWPL 2011.01 118 (94) Speaker A: Tell me about the female popstars. Speaker B: #Well, the female popstars, gave an incredible performance. The shared characteristics between contrastive topics and the kind of intensified DP found in (90B) extend to their interpretative contribution in the sentence (at least to some extent). Remember that the interpretational effect associated with contrastive topics is that the speaker is unwilling or unable to make (at least) one alternative assertion. In the same vein, the use of the as for reading in (90B) is understood as the speaker being unwilling to utter an alternative of the sort John’s brother is fine with the moving to Paris issue because, as stated, he/she does not possess that knowledge. However, what differentiates the meaning contribution of a contrastive topic from that of an intensified constituent with the as for reading is the position held by the referents of these constituents in the constructed set. On a par with the previous intensifier readings, the as for reading requires the referent of the intensified head-DP to be central. As discussed in sections 3.3 - 3.6, the understanding of the intensified entity as central is a result of the nature of the entities found in the alternative value. In particular, the as for reading requires the alternative referents replacing the intensified referent in the alternatives to be defined in terms of the referent of the intensified DP, in the same fashion as with the in person reading (a defining relation must hold between the two entities). Due to this requirement, (95B) is an infelicitous answer to (95A) (compare with (90)), assuming that there is no contextual relation between the two referents that places Bill in the entourage of John. (95) Speaker A: Tell me about Bill. How is he? Speaker B: #Well, I don‘t know about Bill, but John himself is fine. As evident in (96), a contrastive topic constituent (in (96B)) does not impose such restrictions on the referents of the constructed set. (96) Speaker A: Tell me about Bill. How is he? Speaker B: Well, I don‘t know about Bill, but John is fine. In line with the above observations, we suggest that this instance of the intensifier is interpreted as a contrastive topic. The centrality effect it imposes on the referent of its associate DP is the result of the function it denotes, ID (x), being contrasted with the dependent function (DEP (x)). As discussed for the in person reading, the application of this type of function onto an entity x renders x central with respect to another entity y. The hypothesis in (97) captures the underlying mechanisms held responsible for the meaning contribution of this reading. (97) Hypothesis 3: The as for reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of a contrastive topic and always makes reference to dependent function(s). We may now formalize the interpretation of (90B) as in (98), where the contribution of the intensifier is restricted to the functor that generates alternatives to John. (98) a. <λx ASSERT [x is fine with it], John, {John, DEP (John)}> b. y [y ∈ {John, DEP (John)} & (y λx ASSERT [x is fine with it])]. UCLWPL 2011.01 119 Remember that the lambda operator generates utterances and not propositions as it did in the case of focus. Therefore, the representation in (98) expresses that the speaker asserts John is fine with it and is not in a position to assert the brother of John is fine with it. Note that the assertion regarding John does not imply that the brother of John is not fine with it (see Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010)) for a similar conclusion for contrastive topics), as is evident from the felicity of the continuations of the example in (99). Speaker A: Tell me about John‘s brother. How is he feeling lately? Speaker B: Well, John himself is fine... a. ...I haven‘t heard from his brother lately. He is probably fine, too. b. ...His brother, got married recently. (99) The interpretation in (98) further expresses that the use of the as for reading in (90B) constrains the members of the set of alternatives in such a way that only certain variants of the proposition John is fine with it can be included. The position held by John in these variants can only be filled by constituents denoting referents peripheral to John (i.e. the brother of John), as with the in person reading. The analysis provided here for the as for reading is in line with the hypothesis that the intensifier should be able to be marked as contrastive topic and interact with one of the types of alternatives we have discovered in the previous sections, namely the type that expresses, what we called, a defining relation (on a par with the in person reading)32. All else being equal, we expect to find another reading, which is also marked as contrastive topic but interacts with the type of alternatives expressing a participatory relation (on a par with the alone reading). As shown in the example below, not only do we not find a reading with such alternatives but the use of the intensifier in a context with such alternatives is in fact impossible. (100) John is going to Spain with Bill. #John (himself) is (himself) going to Spain (himself). Note that the as for reading, as analysed above, has no problem with the context given in (100), as shown below. (101) The brother of John is going to Spain. John himself is going to Spain, too, but I don‘t 32 Note that our previous conclusion, in section 3.6, regarding the contrastively marked intensifier’s ability to interact with an indefinite pronoun alternative referent is confirmed by the narrow down topic example below. a) Context: Speaker B lives with John. Speaker A: What did some (of the people) wear at the party? Speaker B: #Well, I didn’t go to the party after all. However, John himself wore jeans. I saw him before he left home. It is true that the above example can be easily accommodated by the hearer. However, the reader should note that the judgment is according to the interpretation that John contrasts with some of the people (and of course John has no special status against the rest of the party people). Indeed, under that interpretation the utterance in B is infelicitous. This is confirmed by the felicity of the variation of the example above in (b), in which we do not have intensification. Context: Speaker B lives with John. b) Speaker A: What did some (of the people) wear at the party? Speaker B: Well, I didn’t go to the party after all. However, John wore jeans. I saw him before he left home. UCLWPL 2011.01 120 know about the rest of the family. On further reflection, the non-existence of a reading marked as contrastive topic, which interacts with the x with y type of alternatives should not surprise us. This is because the notion of (contrastive) topic is intrinsically incompatible with such alternatives to begin with, as shown in the example below. It follows that the use of the intensifier marked as contrastive topic in a context with the comitative construction is impossible. (102) John is going to Spain with Bill. ??As for John, he is going to France. We think that the reason behind the incompatibility of contrastive topics, or the intensifier marked as such, and the comitative construction type of alternative lies in the fact that comitatives are VP modifiers. This means that the topic in the first sentence in (102) is not John with Bill but only John. The unacceptability of the following sentence is then a result of the fact that the topic does not change, despite the B-accent indicating that it does. 3.8. The also reading This is one of the rarest readings found cross-linguistically. According to Gast (2009) it represents a peculiarity of some of the European languages, including English. As can be understood from the example in (103B), its use relates to an additive inference of the sort someone else has also been poor, hence its frequent paraphrase with focus particles such as also or too. (103) Speaker A: Many people are poor, and every single one of them says it is tough. Speaker B: Yes, I know, I have been poor myself and I can tell you it‘s not a joke. At first sight, the use of the intensifier in (103B) does not seem to differ much from previous uses in terms of its ability to make reference to alternatives, and more specifically to the clause in (103A) Many people are poor. It does seem to differ from previous readings however in terms of the fact that there is no negation33 of this alternative. Based on what was said before regarding the function of contrast, this last feature excludes the possibility of treating this reading as an instance of contrastive topic or contrastive focus. Assuming that the inducing of alternatives for a given constituent indicates it being marked as a topic or focus (see discussion above), the former feature leads us in the direction of analysing this reading along the lines of one of these two notions. The following argument gives some direction regarding the choice among these two. One of the most prominent features of any instance of the intensifier is its consistent interaction with a DP. As pointed out for the uses we were concerned with thus far, the result of this interaction leads to the interpretation of this DP itself as a constituent which is marked as a contrastive topic or contrastive focus. Therefore, if there is some kind of DP which can be marked only as a topic or only as a focus, and at the same time can interact with the reading we are investigating, then we can safely conclude which of the two candidate interpretations the intensifier carries. As Neeleman and Van de Koot (2008) point out, negative quantifiers can 33 With negation here we mean the effect of contrast. So, when contrast combines with focus it gives us negation of an alternative proposition and when it combines with topic it gives us unwillingness to utter an alternative. UCLWPL 2011.01 121 function as foci but not as topics (because someone cannot say something about nothing or no one). This is shown in examples (104) and (105) respectively. Note that in example (104), the as for construction ensures that the constituent it introduces is marked as a topic. (104) Speaker A: Who went to the cinema? Speaker B: [Nobody]F went to the cinema. (105) #As for [no boy]T, I like him. As illustrated in (106), the also reading can in fact interact with the negative quantifier nobody34, hence it must be the case that it is an instance of focus. (106) Speaker A: Being poor is tough. Can any of you give me some advice on how to get by? Speaker B: I‘m sorry but nobody in this room has [himself]F been poor, so we cannot advise you on that. Being an instance of focus which is not specified with contrast, the also reading is expected not to necessarily interact with explicit alternative propositions. But (103B) (along with every instance of this reading, see Siemund 2000, Gast 2006) does not seem to adhere to this rule. As pointed out above, it seems that it makes reference to Many people are poor. We think that this is not the case, at least for the purpose of expressing its validity (truth/falsity). Instead, the understood interaction between these two propositions is related to the additive inference of this reading, as explained later in this subsection. One last aspect of an intensifier with the also reading is the fact that it can only associate with a DP whose referent is central, similarly to all the previous readings. In the case of all the previous readings, we suggested that the intensifier can only interact with referents that have been previously rendered as central (through an asymmetrical relation holding between the intensified entity and some other entity). However, in this case, the context does not provide us with identifiable alternative referents. Many people is understood as a specific indefinite DP, and there is no way of identifying which people speaker A is referring to. Despite this, there is nothing prohibiting the intensified referent entering into an asymmetrical relation with some other, albeit almost (see footnote 35) unknown, referent. Since the alternative referent is not identifiable, the also reading resorts to other ways of rendering the intensified DP as central. In (103) for example, the intensified DP can be understood to be central through two ways (there may be more). One, by virtue of the fact that the proposition is about the speaker himself. It is well known (especially in the literature of logophoricity) that A is central in discourse from A‘s point of view. Two, through the denotation of the rest of the sentence (Siemund 2000). For example, the intensified referent may have had some experience with respect to being poor, something which renders him/her as a central representative of this state. Therefore, the intensified DP must still be rendered as central prior to the utterance in (103B) in order to be felicitously intensified. However, the central status of the intensified referent in (103B) is admittedly much less prominent when compared to a referent intensified with, for example, the in person reading. This is confirmed by the fact that we can substitute the intensifier in (103B) with the focus particle too or also, without any loss of felicity (note however that the native 34 This goes against Gast (2006), who suggests that this reading interacts with topical constituents. UCLWPL 2011.01 122 speakers still interpret the presence of the intensifier as centralising the associate DP, but not when these focus particles are present). The weak specification of centrality follows from the fact that the also reading is not contrastively marked. Or, to put it in different terms, centrality is understood to be weak because DEP (x), which is the expression of the asymmetrical relation (or centrality), is not saliently evoked. This is in turn a consequence of ID (x) not being understood contrastively. As already pointed out in section 3.6 though, this weak evoking of DEP (x) is predicted to allow for the non-contrastively marked intensifier to interact with specific indefinite pronouns. Indeed, this prediction is borne out by the felicity of example (103), as many people is understood similarly to specific indefinite pronouns, as already pointed out. Following this discussion, we propose that this reading denotes ID (x). On a par with the rest of the readings, ID (x) interacts with the dependent function, DEP (x). The hypothesis below summarises our analysis regarding the interpretation of this reading (note that this hypothesis indicates only the necessary conditions for the occurrence of this reading). (107) Hypothesis 4: The also reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of focus and always makes reference to dependent function(s). In line with the representations given above for a focused constituent, a sentence such as (103B) is analysed as follows. (108) <λx [x has been poor], I, {I, DEP_1_ (I), DEP_2_(I), ..., DEP_n_(I)}> The representation above expresses that the proposition I have been poor is true. It also expresses that this proposition‘s subject referent is contained in the set of people possessing the property of being poor. Hence, the alternative propositions of the sort an entity dependent on me has been poor can also be true. It is also expressed that the intensified referent I is asymmetrically related to the entities contained in the alternatives (in the alternative propositions). It could be argued that the non-exclusion of the alternative propositions is the reason behind the additive inference of this reading. This cannot be the whole story however. Not negating a proposition does not necessarily mean that you are adding it. It may be the case that this proposition is not even considered for the purpose of expressing its truth validity, as suggested above for the also reading. Even though the non-negation of alternatives is a necessary prerequisite for the additive inference of the also reading, the example below illustrates that it is not sufficient. (109B) illustrates that the intensifier can interact with the constituent answering the wh-expression of the question in (109A), hence it must be in focus (let us call this reading the pure focus reading). (109) Speaker A: Who did you see yesterday? Speaker B: The King [himself]F, (walking down the road). Since it is an instance of focus, the intensifier in (109B) does not evoke explicit alternative propositions (in the absence of any accommodation on the part of the hearer), and consequently cannot imply any exclusion. Note that the non-contrastive nature of the intensifier in (109B) is further suggested by the fact that there is no need for a clarification of the sort What do you mean? Who else did you see?, as it was the case for the contrastively marked constituents we have seen before. This is because the notion of focus, by itself, does not force the speakers to UCLWPL 2011.01 123 have any alternative propositions under consideration. In other words, the notion of focus does not provide access to alternative propositions, contrary to the notion of contrast. (110B) ensures that the intensifier with the same reading as in (109B) cannot be interpreted contrastively (for those who find (110B) felicitous, it is because there is evoking of alternatives to the King (contrast); this is not the reading we are aiming for) as it cannot be pre-posed felicitously in that context (note that usually only contrastively marked elements can move; see Neeleman and Van De Koot (2008) for a discussion). (110) Speaker A: Who did you see yesterday? Speaker B: #The King [himself]F I saw walking down the road yesterday. In contrast to the also reading, the intensifier in (109B) does not relate to an additive inference, despite being an instance of focus. Its meaning contribution is restricted in rendering the intensified DP, the King, to be understood as central with regard to some other alternative referents35. Therefore, it cannot be the case that the focus marking of the intensifier, by itself, is the reason behind the additive inference observed in the also reading instances. Below we attempt to provide an explanation of this phenomenon. It has been observed that the also reading is extremely contextually dependent (see Siemund 2000, Gast 2006). In order to get this reading, the proposition expressed by the sentence containing the intensifier must be mentioned or implied in discourse36(with a different referent in the intensified position of course). As a consequence of this, the also reading cannot be reached when the sentence that contains it stands by itself, as shown in (111). Note that according to native speakers, the sentence in (111) is possible when interpreting the intensifier differently (i.e. alone, in person), something which shows that this kind of context dependence of the also reading is special among the various instances of the intensifier. (111) I have raised three kids [myself]F. (impossible with an also reading) Why is it possible to interpret myself in (111) as alone/in person and not also then? These two readings differ with respect to the fact that the former, but not the latter, is marked with contrast. Remember that propositions with contrastively marked constituents make reference to or saliently evoke alternative propositions which differ only in the position of the marked constituent. In cognitive terms, marking a constituent contrastively plays to the hearer‘s ability to accommodate the fact that there must be some alternative propositions that ought to be salient (if 35 The centrality effect is what distinguishes a sentence with a normally focused constituent and a sentence like (109B). This difference is visible in the example below. Whilst (i) is fine in that context, (ii) is infelicitous because John is not central in any way (in contrast to the king who is central almost by definition). a) Speaker A: Who did you see yesterday? Speaker B: i) [John]F walking down the road. ii) #John [himself]F walking down the road. It follows from the examples above that the alternative values of an intensified constituent with the pure focus and also reading are not completely unspecified as it is in the case of a normally focused constituent. Since the intensified entity is defined as central, the rest of the entities in the alternative values are peripheral. In our terms, this minor specification of the properties of the alternative values is a result of the alternative function to ID (x), DEP (x). 36 This restriction is not specific to this instance of the intensifier. As Krifka (2007) points out, the additive focus particles too and also also impose a similar restriction on discourse. UCLWPL 2011.01 124 they are not, then the hearer asks for clarification). The possibility to interpret (111) as the alone/in person reading follows from this, once we consider the fact that these readings are interpreted as such partly because of the type of their alternatives, and crucially, the fact that they are salient. For instance, there would be no way of interpreting (111) with the alone reading, if we did not have in mind the fact that the alternative is a comitative construction. However, when a constituent is not contrastively marked the hearer is not prompted to consider alternative propositions. Since the also reading is not contrastively marked, but requires the same predication as the predication of the proposition containing the intensifier to be present in discourse, the hearer is not prompted to accommodate alternative propositions (which invariably consist of the same predication), hence the impossibility to interpret (111) with the also reading. Therefore, the notion of contrast also explains its special contextual requirements and the impossibility of (111) (with the also reading). The fact that the also reading cannot be reached in out of the blue contexts further substantiates the claim that it is non-contrastively focused marked. In addition, (111) provides crucial evidence for the categorisation of the alone and in person readings as contrastively marked instances of the intensifier. (112) illustrates that (111) becomes felicitous with the also reading when inserted in a context containing a proposition expressing the same predication as the predication of the proposition containing the intensifier, raising kids. (112) Speaker A: It‘s tough to raise kids. Speaker B: Yes I know, I have raised three kids [myself]F and it was pretty hard. However, we have not yet explicitly explained why the additive inference is present. We propose that this inference is a result of the obligatory presence in discourse of the same predication as the one contained in the intensifier‘s proposition (but with a different referent). As we have seen in (109B), the intensifier can be an instance of focus and not convey the additive inference. At the same time the intensifier in (109B) does not require the interlocutors to have any other propositions under consideration (i.e. I saw an entity dependent on the king walking down the road). On the other hand, the also reading, despite being an instance of focus, obligatorily needs this alternative proposition under consideration because of its predication. Assuming that a focused constituent does not need its alternative propositions to be explicitly discourse present, the presence of an alternative proposition to the proposition containing the also reading can only be used as a signal to the interlocutors that this alternative proposition should be taken under consideration. Having two propositions with the same predication under consideration, without excluding one of them, is precisely what leads to this additive inference. Note that having the alternative proposition under consideration does not mean here that there is access to it. It simply means that the speaker using the also reading has noted the fact that there is already a proposition (i.e. Many people are poor) in the common ground expressing that its predication (i.e. being poor) is applied to a referent (many people) other than the intensified one. It is important to note that under this approach the also reading is merely a special case of the intensifier being an instance of focus. We end the discussion in this subsection with the type of alternatives that the pure focus and also readings interact with. We discovered two basic types of contextual instantiations of DEP (x) and its associate DP, namely the comitative construction expressing the participatory relation and constructions expressing the defining relation. Unfortunately, we cannot verify the type of alternatives the pure focus reading interacts with, as the set of alternative values that UCLWPL 2011.01 125 includes the intensified DP is always represented by a wh-expression. On the other hand, the fact that the also reading requires an alternative proposition to be present in discourse makes it feasible to check what type of alternatives it interacts with. As illustrated below, the also reading is incompatible with the comitative type of alternatives but compatible with the ones expressing the defining relation. (113) Speaker A: John found the way to the station with Bill. Speaker B: #Yes, John found the way to the station [himself]F. (114) Speaker A: The brother of John is a really good student. Speaker B: Yes, John is a really good student [himself]F. Should we expect another reading of the intensifier that is able to interact with the comitative type of alternatives and simultaneously exhibit the additive inference (similarly to the also one)? We think that the answer is no (this expectation is borne out by the infelicity of (113) in which we keep constant the informational structural marking of the intensifier and the presupposition that there is at least one other referent who found the way to the station, and only altered the type of alternatives). This is due to the fact that the intensified referent constitutes a separate referent in this kind of alternatives. As a result of this, both the proposition containing the intensifier and its alternative proposition constitute a statement of the fact that one and the same referent participates in the particular event described by the predication (which is the same in both propositions). This equals to a restatement of the facts, something which is pragmatically incoherent. This can be seen from a comparison of (113A) and (113B). Both propositions state the fact that John found the way to the station. Note that (113B) remains infelicitous even if we attempt to replace the intensifier with an additive particle (i.e. also, too), for the same reason. The explanation put forward here predicts that the comitative alternative should not be able to interact with an intensifier which requires its alternatives to be explicitly mentioned in discourse, like in the case of the also reading, and does not deny one of them. As we will see in the next section (3.9), this prediction is borne out by the even reading of the intensifier. 3.9. The even reading (115a) illustrates the use of this reading. The presence of the intensifier forces the characterization of the referent it interacts with as the least likely or expected member of a set of individuals that could potentially replace this referent in the sentence. This scalar inference is also exhibited by the focus particle even, hence the close paraphrase of (115a) in (115b). (115) a. John said Einstein himself could not understand Physics sometimes. b. John said even Einstein could not understand Physics sometimes. Apart from the scalar inference, the even reading (and the use of the focus particle even) is also characterized by the additive inference, similarly to the also reading. (115a) (and (115b)) is understood as to imply that some other referents, besides Einstein, could not understand Physics either. The difference between the use of the focus particle even and the even reading of the intensifier lies in the way these two constituents characterize their focus. Similarly to all other uses of the intensifier, the even reading is intuitively understood to interact with central participants in discourse, something which is not the case in (115b). In particular, the referent of the intensifier‘s associate DP is understood as central with respect to the topic of Physics. Based UCLWPL 2011.01 126 on the example in (115a) it could be argued that Einstein is defined as central against the denotation of the sentence it is contained in, namely not being able to understand Physics, and hence the general understanding of Einstein being central with regard to Physics. Of course, this is reminiscent of one of the ways the also reading characterizes the referent of the intensified DP as central. Moreover, the specification of Einstein as central is equally weak as it was in the case of the also reading. This weak specification of centrality is evident from the fact that it is impossible to exhibit a context favoring the even reading of the intensifier but not the scalar focus particle even (however, native speakers still perceive the even reading, but not the focus particle even, as centralizing its associate DP). Considering these common properties of the even and also readings (they differ only with respect to the scalar inference), it seems reasonable to analyse the two readings likewise. For instance, we could assume that the even reading together with its associate DP are understood as an instance of a focus marked constituent that is understood additively because of the presence of the same predication in context. The scalar inference is simply a result of context, and more specifically, of shared assumptions among the discourse participants regarding the (un)likelihood of the intensified referent to form part of the denotation of the proposition it occurs in. In (115a) for example, Einstein is judged as someone unlikely to be unable to understand Physics, given the shared world knowledge that he is one of the most prominent figures in the history of Physics. Attempting to replace Einstein with another central figure, (let‘s say) Obama, would result in infelicity on the intended reading because Obama is not a prominent figure in the field of Physics. If the scalar effect is a pragmatic phenomenon, then we should be able to eliminate it just by inserting (115a) in a context where Einstein is not an unexpected or unlikely referent, given the rest of the proposition and the alternative referents contained in the set. (116) illustrates that this is possible. (116) Speaker A: As far as I know, Isaac Newton and Stephen Hawking found it tough to understand Physics at first. Speaker B: Yes, I know, Einstein himself found it tough to understand it sometimes. (116) shows that by simply manipulating the set of alternative referents that are contextually present and compared to Einstein we are able to eliminate the scalar effect. World knowledge instructs us that Newton and Hawking are also prominent figures of Physics. The fact that they have also been in the situation of finding it tough to understand Physics removes the (un)likelihood of something similar happening in the case of Einstein. Note that, when the scalar effect is eliminated, as in (116), the most accessible reading that we are left with is the also one. This is certainly expected under this analysis, since it is assumed that the two readings are essentially the same and only differentiated in terms of the scalar inference, whose presence (or absence) is dependent on the set of alternative referents provided by the context. However, a closer comparison of the even and also readings suggests that the scalar inference cannot be the only factor distinguishing them. As pointed out in the discussion surrounding (111), repeated below as (117), the also reading is inaccessible when the proposition containing it does not occur in a context where there is another sentence containing the same predication (for (117) this predication must be along the lines x has raised y number of kids). (117) #I have raised three kids [myself]F. UCLWPL 2011.01 127 As pointed out, this resulted from the fact that the also reading is a non-contrastively focused constituent that cannot evoke salient alternative propositions. Since it cannot evoke alternative propositions, its requirement to occur in a context in which the same predication as the one it occurs in is present remains unsatisfied (remember that the alternatives to a sentence containing an intensifier differ only with respect to the position occupied by the associate DP and the absence of the intensifier; the rest of the predication remains the same). Contrary to these contextual restrictions of the also reading, which render (117) infelicitous, the even reading is easily accessible in (115a). Hence, it cannot be the case that it is the same as the also reading with the scalar inference added because of pragmatics. Despite the fact that the predication contained in the sentence in (115a), namely could not understand Physics, is not present contextually, we can still access the even reading and the additive inference that comes with it. Given that a) this additive inference is a result of considering the fact that the same predication is applied to some other referent, and b) the even reading is able to exhibit this additive inference in a context deprived of this predication, the even reading must be able to realize the consideration of the same predication (applied to some other referent) through other means. We propose that the even reading‘s ability to do this is a result of it and its associate DP being interpreted contrastively. The rationale behind this assumption lies in the fact that contrast provides access to the induced alternatives (see section 3.2). Since these alternatives consist of the same predication as the sentence containing the intensifier, we can explain why the even reading does not require this predication to be explicitly expressed in context in order to be accessed. Note that this reading and its associate DP must be an instance of contrastive focus, and not contrastive topic, because the associate DP can be a negative quantifier as shown below. (118) Context: Some of the members of the Olympics football team have been caught on steroids in a pre-Olympic steroid test. As a result, the whole team now has a bad name. Speaker A is the assistant manager and speaker B is the manager of the team. Speaker A: The team is doing really well. I think we will do well in the Olympics. Speaker B:Yes, I know, but no loss would be a bad result ITSELF . I bet everyone will start saying that we won all our matches because we are on steroids. (paraphrase: ... even no loss would be a bad result...). Given these considerations, we propose the following. (119) Hypothesis 5: The even reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of contrastive focus and always makes reference to dependent function(s). The reference to the dependent function, DEP (x), will deliver the intuitively correct alternative referents (consisting of a central entity and peripheral ones) contrasting with the referent of the intensified DP, similarly to the rest of the readings. Further evidence for the contrastive character of the even reading and its associate DP comes from their distributional behaviour. Before (see sections 3.3 and 3.8), we touched upon the fact that constituents marked with contrast exhibit certain grammatical effects. In particular, as we have seen in example (31), repeated below as (120), the contrastively focused constituent The Selfish Gene can be moved to the front of the clause. (120) Speaker A: John read The Extended Phenotype. UCLWPL 2011.01 128 Speaker B: No, you are wrong, THE SELFISH GENE he read. Wh-questions do not normally license focus movement in the answer, as the example in (52), repeated below as (121), shows. This is because The Selfish Gene is (focused but) not contrastively marked. (121) Speaker A: What did John read? Speaker B: #The Selfish Gene he read. The hypothesis in (119) predicts that the even reading along with its associate DP should be able to move, in parallel fashion to the rest of contrastively marked constituents. This prediction is borne out as illustrated in (123), in which the constituent Einstein himself can be pre-posed felicitously. Example (122) shows that this is not a peculiarity of the even reading of the intensifier, but in fact every constituent that denotes an unlikely referent with respect to the denotation of the sentence can be pre-posed felicitously. (122) Even EINSTEIN John said could not understand Physics sometimes. (123) Einstein HIMSELF John said could not understand Physics sometimes The hypothesis in (119) has proved sufficient to explain why the even reading and its associate DP can move, as well as certain interpretative aspects of this use. However, there is an obvious incompatibility of the interpretation of the notion of contrastive focus and the interpretation of the even reading (or the focus particle even). Until now, we have been assuming that the proposition that contains a contrastively focused constituent evokes alternative propositions and simultaneously negates (at least) one alternative proposition. On the other hand, we described the even reading‘s interpretation as evoking alternative propositions and ranking them in terms of likelihood or expectancy, out of which the least likely one is selected, hence the scalar proposition. Crucially, there is no negation of any alternative propositions. After all, if this were the case, the additive inference that characterizes this reading would be impossible. In order to overcome this problem, which lies in the core of our general proposal, we adopt a different conceptualization of the notion of contrast than that described by Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010) (see section 3.2). In particular, following Frey (2010), we perceive the function of the notion of contrast to be the ordering of the set of alternatives according to various criteria including truth value, likelihood, and expectancy. In practice, this does not change much. What we perceived until now as being the function of a contrastively marked constituent (denial of alternatives) is now a subcase of the largest family of phenomena involving this notion, whose effect is the ordering of the alternatives in the relevant set according to some criterion. For instance, in corrective contexts or in the cases of the in person, alone and as for readings, the notion of contrast ranks the propositions/utterances contained in the set according to the criterion of truth value. In (120) for example, speaker B expresses that the proposition he/she expresses is ranked as true and the alternative proposition expressed by speaker A is ranked as false in a scale of truth. This interpretation is essentially the same as the one expressed by Neeleman and Vermeulen (2010), hence there is no problem with the analysis of all the previous instances of the intensifier involving the notion of contrast. UCLWPL 2011.01 129 Once we adopt this view of the notion of contrast, the scalar inference of the even reading falls out naturally. Also, the additive inference expressed by this reading is not incompatible with the notion of contrast anymore. The intensifier and its associate DP are indeed interpreted as a contrastive focus, however the presence of contrast, instead of ordering the propositions contained in the given set according to the criterion of truth value, it orders them in terms of the criterion of likelihood or expectancy. Hence, the interpretative effect of the even reading, namely to render the referent of its associate DP as the least likely or expected candidate with respect to the rest of the denotation of the proposition, is an effect of contrast ordering the set of referents in a scale of likelihood or expectancy. Below, we provide the formalization of the interpretation of the even reading in (115a) (we leave out parts of the sentence irrelevant to the point)3738. (124) a. <x[x could not understand Physics], Einstein, {DEP_1_(Einstein), DEP_2_(Einstein), ..., DEP_n_(Einstein)}> b. x [x {DEP_1_(Einstein), DEP_2_(Einstein), ..., DEP_n_(Einstein} [Einstein could not understand Physics] <c [x could not understand Physics] ]. (124) expresses to what extent the set of contextually relevant individuals (i.e. Einstein, someone studying Physics, etc) is contained in the set of individuals that could not understand Physics. It is asserted that one member of this set, namely Einstein, is also a member of the set of individuals that could not understand Physics. In addition, it is asserted that, given the common ground c, Einstein is less likely not to understand Physics than any other member of the contextually given set. The presence of alternatives and the first assertion are the result of the semantics of focus, whereas the second assertion corresponds to the semantics of contrast. Contrary to any other contrastively focused constituent with this particular semantics, however, the even reading of the intensifier in (115a) constrains the members of the set of alternatives in such a way that only certain variants of the asserted proposition can be included. The position 37 <c indicates that the proposition on the left of it is less likely to be true than the one on the right of it, given the common ground c. 38 It is true that the semantics of the type of contrast that ranks the alternatives in terms of likelihood differ considerably from the semantics of the type of contrast that ranks the alternatives in terms of truth values. Hence, it could be argued that subsuming both instances of semantics under the notion of contrast is something which is conceptually satisfactory but nevertheless does not follow from the level of semantics. Formally, it is hard to maintain the conclusion that the two instances of semantics are representations of the same notion (contrast). Setting aside the arguments (i.e. movement) tying together the notions represented by the two different instances of semantics under the label of contrast, as spelled out above, we would like to offer an informal rationale for this discrepancy at the level of semantics. The two instances of semantics differ in two respects. In the case of the truth value ranking there is negation of at least one alternative, whereas in the case of the likelihood ranking there is the assertion that all the alternatives are more likely than the one asserted. Hence, there is difference in the type of assertion (negation vs more likely) and the reference to alternatives (all vs at least one). We think that the latter property is a direct result of the former. In order to be able to make an assertion regarding the least likelihood of a given alternative, there must be reference to the more likelihood of all the alternative propositions in context. It cannot be asserted that an alternative is the least (notice the superlative) likely just by making reference to the more likelihood of some alternatives, hence the use of the universal quantifier. On the other hand, negating alternatives is not as demanding in terms of making reference to alternatives. The requirement to negate is still satisfied by making reference to one alternative, hence the use of the existential quantifier. Of course both instances of contrast involve opposing of alternatives, and that is precisely the function of contrast as we have been arguing up to now. At the level of semantics this translates into the fact that we get a second assertion (the (b) part in every semantics that involve contrast). UCLWPL 2011.01 130 held by Einstein in these variants can only be filled by constituents denoting referents peripheral to Einstein (i.e. someone studying Physics), and nothing else. Following the new view on the notion of contrast we adopted above, the question arises as to which particular instantiation of the semantics of contrast is relevant in a given instance of the intensifier. Or, to put it differently, what makes the hearer decide according to which criterion (i.e. truthfulness, likelihood) the speaker contrastively marks a particular constituent? The answer to this question will be the same as the one given in section 2, regarding the choice of the interpretation of the intensifier. The main factor distinguishing which interpretation of the intensifier is selected is context. According to our theory, both the in person and even readings are contrastively focused, but with different semantics, hence a sentence like (115a) should be able to take either interpretation of the two (in fact, it can take more than these two readings, again depending on the context; see for instance example (116)). The reason that the even reading is preferred here is the predication it occurs in, could not understand Physics, which forms part of the context of course (hence the contribution of pragmatics, as outlined at the beginning of this subsection, is indeed significant). As shown below, (115a) can be interpreted as the in person reading when inserted in different context (corrective context) that overrides the effect of the predication. (125) Speaker A: John said Einstein‘s son could not understand Physics sometimes. Speaker B: No, John said Einstein HIMSELF could not understand Physics sometimes. The negation used by speaker B, characteristic of corrective context, is an indicator towards the hearer to interpret the contrastively focused constituent according to the criterion of truthfulness (see also Frey 2010 for a similar point), and hence the interpretation of the intensifier as in person (and the respective semantics). Being marked as contrastive focus, we would expect the even reading to exhibit the same requirements (as the rest of the readings marked as such) regarding the alternative values it interacts with, namely to not be able to interact with indefinite pronouns found in certain configurations (see for instance example (88) illustrating this for the in person reading). However, as illustrated below, this is not the case as it can interact with many people, which is arguably interpreted as a specific indefinite pronoun, similarly to the also reading (a noncontrastively marked reading). (126) Many people could not understand Physics. Einstein HIMSELF could not understand Physics sometimes. What differentiates the two instances of contrast is the criteria according to which the alternatives are ranked. Whereas the in person, alone and as for readings rank their alternatives in terms of truth value, the even reading ranks them in terms of likelihood or expectancy. This is evident from the semantics of each instance of contrast. According to the semantics of the former instance, there is negation of an alternative proposition/utterance. In the semantics of the latter instance, it is stated that the proposition expressed is the least expected from the relevant set. Notice that no direct reference to, or assertion regarding, alternative propositions is made in this latter instance of contrast. The part of the semantics which expresses unlikelihood is primarily concerned with the proposition expressed by the speaker, and the fact that, given the context, this proposition is an unlikely candidate. This semantics matches our intuition regarding the function UCLWPL 2011.01 131 of this instance of contrast. When uttering (126), we have the general understanding that Einstein is an unlikely individual to not understand Physics. The reason for this is because Einstein is a Physicist with many achievements. What will come to mind is the fact that Einstein is a great Physicist, and because of this he is unlikely to have not been able to understand Physics. Notice that no reference to other individuals is made but only to the reason behind this unlikelihood. Of course there is a sense of comparison between Einstein and other individuals, which results from the common assumption made by speakers that for someone to not understand Physics, he/she should have at least less abilities in Physics compared to Einstein. Since other individuals could not understand Physics, their level of understanding Physics must have been at least lower than Einstein. On the other hand, in the case of contrast specified in terms of the scale of truth, there is a clear assertion regarding an alternative proposition/utterance. As pointed out before (see section 3.3), in order to be able to do this, clear access to alternatives is required. In a nutshell, the two types of contrast behave differently in terms of their access to alternative propositions. We can say that the negation type of contrast gives full access to alternatives, because there must be negation of one of them39, whereas the likelihood type of contrast gives limited access to alternatives, because there is only some kind of indirect comparison between them (and for this comparison to happen it is sufficient to know the individual that is intensified and the criterion of this comparison). It follows that the even reading and its associate DP are not predicted to impose similar (to the rest of the contrastively marked readings) restrictions regarding the identifiability of the interacting alternative referents. This is because contrast defined in terms of likelihood does not provide clear access to alternatives, and hence DEP (x) is not saliently evoked. This also explains the otherwise unexpected weak centrality effect imposed by this reading on its associate DP. In section 3.8 we were unable to find a reading of the intensifier exhibiting an additive inference and at the same time interacting with the comitative type of alternatives. As explained (see section 3.8), this is due to the fact that the entity that is subsequently intensified constitutes a separate referent in the alternative. As a consequence, we pointed out, an intensifier which does not deny the salient alternative containing the comitative construction cannot interact with the central entity in this construction because it would constitute a (partial) repetition of the alternative proposition already expressed. What is expected then is that there should not exist a reading with the scalar inference interacting with the comitative type, because the scalar inference does not deny the evoked alternatives. In fact scalarity encompasses the addition of alternatives. Needless to say that we also expect the even reading of the intensifier and its associate DP to contrast with the type of alternatives that express the defining relation (similarly to all the previous readings except the alone one), and not the comitative type that expresses a the participatory relation. Indeed, as shown below in (127) and (128), an intensifier characterized with the scalar inference cannot interact with type of alternatives expressing the participatory relation but only with the ones expressing the defining relation. This interaction delivers the even reading. (127) Context: John is not good with finding his way around. Speaker A: John found the way to the station with Bill. Speaker B: #So what? Finding the station is not hard nowadays. John (HIMSELF ) found 39 This is in accordance to what has already been pointed in section 3.3, namely that the saliency of alternatives (propositions or utterances) is a by-product of their negation. UCLWPL 2011.01 132 the way to the station (HIMSELF ). (128) Context: John is not good with finding his way around. Speaker A: John‘s brother found the way to the station. Speaker B: So what? Finding the station is not hard nowadays. John (HIMSELF ) found the way to the station (HIMSELF ). Note that (127) remains infelicitous even if we attempt to replace the intensifier with the scalar focus particle even, for the same reason that the intensifier is infelicitous. According to the new view of the notion of contrast adopted in this section, whenever the intensifier is marked as contrastive focus, the realisation of contrast can have two different semantics. These semantics are defined in terms of the scale of truth or the scale of likelihood. The in person reading is an instantiation of the former scale and the even reading an instantiation of the latter, both being a contrastively focused constituent though. Based on this approach, one would expect that there should exist at least one reading marked as contrastive topic realising the semantics of the scale of truth and another one realising the semantics of the scale of likelihood. The as for reading is an instantiation of the former scale. To our knowledge, a reading of the intensifier which expresses some sort of scaling in terms of likelihood and is simultaneously marked as contrastive topic does not exist. The reason for this is the general incompatibility of the notion of topic and the ranking of alternatives in terms of a scale or likelihood/expectancy (no one talks about emphatic topic or scalar topic, but only about emphatic focus and scalar focus). We remain agnostic as to why this is the case. 3.10. The aboutness reading As pointed out before, owing to the existence of the notions of contrast, topic and focus a constituent in English can be marked with the following four ways: a) contrastive focus, b) contrastive topic, c) focus, d) topic. Until now, we have seen the intensifier being an instance of the first three notions. The theory proposed here predicts the existence of another reading of the intensifier, namely that which is an instance of topic. The example given below confirms this prediction. (129) Context: It’s the royal wedding and the Prime Minister along with other people are walking past in a procession. A BBC commentator is describing the various outfits worn by the PM and the rest of the people. a. The PM [himself]T is wearing a blue suit and a yellow tie. b. As for the PM [himself]T, he is wearing a blue suit and a yellow tie. c. [The PM]T is wearing a blue suit and a yellow tie. (129b) is added in order to ensure that the constituent The PM himself in (129a) can be introduced by the construction as for. As pointed out before, the constituents introduced by this construction are always topics. (129c) is added for comparison purposes. All three possible utterances of the commentator converge to the point that they introduce the PM as the topic of discourse and provide new information about him/her. Since it is an instance of topic, the intensifier in (129a-b) renders the sentence it is contained in to be associated with a set of alternative utterances, which differ only in the value of UCLWPL 2011.01 133 the position occupied by the DP the PM himself. However, since this reading is not contrastive, there is no access to these alternatives as is evident from the fact that when (129a-b) are uttered, alternative utterances about the outfits of other guests (i.e. the PM‘s secretary is wearing a yellow dress) do not necessarily come to mind40. In contrast to a constituent marked as contrastive topic, the hearer does not get the impression that the speaker is unwilling (or unable) to make alternative assertions about someone else. This is confirmed by the fact that there is not a trigger of a request for clarification on behalf of the hearer (i.e. Who else is wearing what?). The difference between a normal topical construction like (129c) and a topical intensified construction like (129a-b) lies in the fact that the latter characterises the intensified referent, the PM, as central, against some alternative referents41. For the case of (129a-b), this centrality effect is achieved through world knowledge regarding the high political status entailed by the position of the PM. The peripheral referents do not have to be identifiable though (i.e. the PM‘s wife, the PM‘s secretary etc). The non-identifiability of the alternative referents follows from the fact that the intensifier is not marked with contrast, as explained in previous sections, which in turn makes it felicitous in a context like (129), in which there are no explicit alternatives42. In accordance with the suggestion made for the case of the focus readings, the nature of alternative referents this reading interacts with is a result of the function it denotes, ID (x), interacting with the dependent function DEP (x). Therefore, we assume the following. In order to be able to distinguish this reading from the rest, let us call it the aboutness reading. (130) Hypothesis 6: The aboutness reading of the intensifier is invariably an instance of topic and always makes reference to dependent function(s). Since the aboutness reading is an instance of topic, a sentence like (129a) is analysed as in (131). Note that the representation below is in accordance with the intuition (as it was for the case of a 40 This is a similar case to the focus readings we have seen above. Even though it is assumed that there is inducing of alternative propositions, these propositions are not accessed. 41 This is why the commentator can utter something like (a) below, and not (b) (same context as in (129)). Mary cannot be intensified in (b) because it is not central to any other alternative referents in that context. a) [Mary]T is wearing a blue dress. b) #Mary [herself]T is wearing a blue dress. Note that the centrality effect in this reading is equally weak as in the case of the pure focus, also and even readings. As the reader may have noticed however, in the case of the pure focus and aboutness readings we have been able to give examples showing that they are infelicitous because of this centrality requirement. We have not been able to do something similar for the also and even readings. Despite this we still think that the specification of centrality is in all these readings equally weak. The reason for not being able to give infelicitous examples in the cases of the also and even readings is because there is always an alternative proposition induced, or present, in discourse with the same predication, and importantly a referent being part of it. This referent is immediately accommodated as peripheral to the intensified based on the rest of the denotation of the proposition (the predication). Hence, it is impossible to provide an infelicitous example (however native speakers are positive about the existence of centrality in these readings). On the other hand, in the cases of the aboutness and pure focus readings, we can verify the existence of centrality because there are no alternative referents present in discourse. Therefore, the referent resorts into other (than the predication it occurs in) ways to be central (i.e. through social/political status). This allows us to give infelicitous examples with referents that are not generally considered as central. 42 Similarly to the case of the pure focus reading of the intensifier, the fact that the alternative referents are not explicit in discourse makes it impossible to check what type of alternatives (i.e. comitative) the aboutness reading of the intensifier and its associate DP interact with. UCLWPL 2011.01 134 normal topical constituent) that speaker B performs the following speech acts when uttering (129a): a) Consider the PM out of a set of possible topics (i.e. an entity dependent on the PM), b) I assert that the PM is wearing a blue suit and a yellow tie. (131) <λx ASSERT [x is wearing a blue suit and a yellow tie], the PM, {the PM, DEP_1_ (PM), DEP_2_ (PM), ..., DEP_n_ (PM)}> We stress the point that the above representation differs from a topical constituent with regard to the alternative utterances induced. When the intensifier is present, the constituents replacing the intensified DP in the alternative utterances are peripheral to the intensified referent, precisely due to the application of the dependent function. 3.11. The incompatibility of the intensifier and true indefinites In section 2 we pointed out that all the readings of the intensifier cannot be associated with true indefinite DPs. We concluded that the intensifier can in fact interact with indefinite DPs, but these DPs are obligatorily interpreted as generic or specific as illustrated with examples (19b), (20), (23), (24) for the in person, alone, also/even, and as for readings respectively. (132) – (135) below illustrate that this conclusion is also valid for the rest of the readings we discussed. In (132), we have an instance of the delegative reading. The only way of felicitously interpreting the sentence is when there is a specific woman participating in the action described by the predicate. In (133) we also have a specific reading of the indefinite DP interacting with the without x’s help reading. In (134 the intensifier takes the aboutness reading and is interpreted as generic. In (135) the intensifier takes the pure focus reading and is interpreted as specific43. (132) A woman dyed her hair HERSELF. (133) A general has commanded the whole army HIMSELF. (134) Context: The lecturer begins his lecture on democracy with the sentence below A politician [himself]T is the main representative of democracy. (135) Context: Politicians are considered very important figures in the society that the following conversation takes place. Speaker A: Who did you see yesterday? Speaker B: A politician [himself]F walking down the road. As we have seen, the (only) common property of all the readings of the intensifier is the central status of its associate DP. Therefore, we expect that this property should be held responsible for the inability of the intensifier to interact with true indefinites. As pointed out before, the centrality status of the intensified DP is nothing else than the asymmetric relation holding between the entity denoted by this DP and another entity, in the alternatives. Having this in mind, we can now understand why definite DPs and specific and generic indefinite DPs can interact with the intensifier. Definite and specific indefinite DPs denote a particular individual; 43 Remember that there is no reading of the intensifier that interacts with a coordination alternative (the reading that we call only). Hence, its inability to render an indefinite DP generic or specific, as shown in footnote 14. UCLWPL 2011.01 135 therefore there should be no problem with them entering into a relation with some other individuals. Generic DPs on the other hand denote a group/set of individuals in the world that have some properties in common. It is conceivable for a group to enter into a relation with some other group or referent (in (135) for instance, the group of politicians are defined as central with respect (thus related) to the rest of the citizens in the context of democracy) hence the possibility of generic indefinite DPs to be intensified. True indefinite DPs, however, denote a bundle of properties and not a particular individual in the world. (136) for example, expresses that the subject referent wants to buy an entity that consists of certain properties (i.e. it has four wheels), a car. The phrase a car can be seen as a way of grouping these properties. (136) I want to buy a car. Since one of the intensifier‘s basic functions is to interact with central referents, and since centrality is an asymmetric relation holding between the intensified entity and another entity (within the alternative values), a true indefinite DP cannot be intensified for the reason that its denotation cannot be related to something else. This is because the very concept of relation requires, by definition, at least two individuals to ‗connect‘ them together. This way of thinking also explains why the intensifier, in contrast to other constituents serving similar functions such as the focus particles (i.e. even, only), cannot interact with predicates (i.e. verbs), once we adopt the well-accepted assumption that predicates denote a bundle of properties, similarly to true indefinite DPs. 4. Conclusion The analysis developed in this paper does not only account for the well-documented readings of the intensifier (i.e. in person, alone, also) but goes one step further in predicting the existence of more readings, which have, to our knowledge, remained undiscovered (i.e. aboutness). Following Eckardt‘s (2001) proposal about the denotation of some of the readings of the intensifier, we suggested that every instance of the intensifier has the same denotation (ID (x)). The interpretational differences between the different readings essentially reduce to one factor, namely the nature of the intensifier‘s marking (with the notions comprising a specific component of information structure; see table in (27). We think that this theory is superior to previous ones in terms of accounting for the interpretation of the intensifier for the following reasons; (137) a. It is superior from an explanatory point of view in the sense that it assumes only one lexical entry for the intensifier and derives its different readings from an independently well-studied phenomenon. b. It is flexible enough to account for the existing data in the literature (descriptive adequacy), and furthermore predicts, correctly, the existence of more instances of the intensifier (predictive power). c. It is restrictive enough to limit, through the employment of the alternative function DEP (x), the kind of alternatives the intensifier can interact with, and hence the possible readings we can find. d. It exposes how other factors (i.e. syntactic position, pragmatics) may come into play for the realisation of a particular reading. UCLWPL 2011.01 136 The table below summarizes our findings with regard to the different readings of the intensifier44. Reading Denotes Interacts with Marked as In person, delegative, even, ID (x) alone, without x‘s help DEP (x) CF As for ID (x) DEP (x) CT Also, pure Focus ID (x) DEP (x) F Aboutness ID (x) DEP (x) T References Baker, C. (1995). Contrast, discourse prominence, and intensification, with special reference to locally free reflexives in British English. Language , 73.1, 63 - 101. Bergeton, U. (2004). The Independence of Binding and Intensification (Ph.D. thesis). University of Southern California. Browning, M. A. 1993. Adverbial Reflexives. NELS 23.1: 83-94. Büring, D. (2001). Let‘s phrase it! – focus, word order, and prosodic phrasing in German double object constructions. In G. Müller, & W. Sternefeld (Eds.), Competition in Syntax, no. 49 in Studies in Generative Grammar (pp. 101 – 137). Berlin & New York: de Gruyter. Chafe, W. L. (1976). Givenness, contrastiveness, definiteness, subjects, topics and points of view. In C. N. Li (Ed.), Subject and topic (pp. 25 - 55). New York: Academic Press. Cohen, D. (1999). Towards a unified account of intensive reflexives. Journal of Pragmatics , 31, 1041 - 1052. Constantinou, H. (2011). The Syntax of IDensification. Ms. UCL Dirven, R. (1973). Emphatic and reflexive in English and Dutch. Leuvense Bijdragen , 63, 288 – 299. Eckardt, R. (2001). Reanalysing selbst. Natural Language Semantics , 9(4), 371 -412. Edmondson, J., & Plank, F. (1978). Great expectations: an intensive self analysis. Linguistics and Philosophy , 2, 373 – 413. Féry, C. (2010). Prosody and information structure of the German particles selbst, wieder and auch. In T. Borowskyi, K. Shigeto, S. Takahito, & S. Mariko (Eds.), Prosody Matters: Essays in Honor of Elisabeth O. Selkirk. London: Equinox Press. Fraurud, K. (1990). Definiteness and the processing of noun phrases in natural discourse. Journal of Semantics , 7, 395–433. Frey, W. (2010). A-bar-Movement and conventional implicatures: About the grammatical encoding of emphasis in German. Lingua , 1416 - 1435. Gast, V. (2009). A contribution to ‘two-dimensional’ language description: the Typological Database of Intensifiers and Reflexives. Ms. Freie Universität Berlin. Gast, V. (2006). The Grammar of Identity. Intensifiers and Reflexives in Germanic languages. New York: Routledge. Hankamer, J. (1973). Unacceptable ambiguity. Linguistic Inquiry 4: 17–68. Hawkins, J. A. (1978). Definiteness and Indefiniteness: A Study in Reference and Grammaticality Prediction. London: Croom Helm. Hawkins, R. (1981). Towards an account of the possessive constructions: NPs and the N of NP. Journal of Linguistics , 17, 247—269. Hole, D. (2002). Agentive selbst in German. In G. Katz, S. Reinhard, & P. Reuter, Sinn und Bedeutung VI – Proceedings of the 6th Annual (pp. 133 - 150). Osnabrück: Institute of Cognitive Science. Jackendoff, R. (1972). Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kiss, K. (1998). Identificational focus versus information focus. Language , 74, 245 - 273. 44 CF= contrastive focus, CT= contrastive topic, F=focus, T=topic UCLWPL 2011.01 137 König, E. (2001). Intensifiers and reflexives. In M. Haspelmath, E. König, W. Oesterreicher, & W. Raible (Eds.), Language Typology and Language Universals – An International Handbook of Contemporary Research (pp. 747 - 760). Berlin & New York: Mouton. König, E. (1991). The Meaning of Focus Particles: A Comparative Perspective. London: Routledge. König, E., & Siemund, P. (1999). ‗Intensifiers and reflexives: A typological perspective. In Z. Frajzyngier, & T. Curl (Eds.), Reflexives. Forms and Functions (pp. 41-74). Amsterdam: Benjamins. König, E., & Siemund, P. (2011). Intensifiers and Reflexive Pronouns. The World Atlas of Languages online: http://wals.info/ (date accessed: 27/3/2011). Koptjevskaja-Tamm, M. (2004). ―Maria‘s ring of gold‖: adnominal possession and non-anchoring relations in the European languages. In J. Y. Kim, Y. Lander, & B. H. Partee (Eds.), Possessives and Beyond: Semantics and Syntax (pp. 155 - 181). Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications. Koptjevskaja-Tamm, M. (2000). Romani genitives in cross-linguistic perspective. In V. Elsik, & Y. Matras (Eds.), Grammatical Relations in Romani: The Noun Phrase (pp. 123 – 149). John Benjamins. Krifka, M. (2007). Basic Notions of Information Structure. In C. Fery, & M. Krifka (Eds.), Interdisciplinary Studies of Information Structure 6. Potsdam. Lambrecht, K. (1994). Information Structure and Sentence Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Langacker, R. W. (1995). Possession and possessive constructions. In J. R. Taylor, & R. E. MacLayry (Eds.), Language and the Cognitive Construal of the World, Trends in Linguistics, Studies and Monographs (pp. 51 – 79). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Langacker, R. W. (1993). Reference-point constructions. Cognitive Linguistics , 4, 1 - 38. Larson, R. (1988). On the Double-Object Construction. Linguistic Inquiry , 19, 335 - 391. Lehmann, C., & Shin, Y. M. (2005). The functional domain of concomitance. A typological study of instrumental and comitative relations. In C. Lehmann (Ed.), Typological Studies in Participation. Language Typology and Universals (pp. 9 - 104). Berlin. Molnar, V. (2002). Contrast – from a contrastive perspective. In H. Hallelgard, S. Johansson, B. Behrens, & C. Fabricius-Hansen (Eds.), Information Structure in a Cross-Linguistic Perspective (pp. 147 - 161). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi. Moravcsik, E. (1972). Some crosslinguistic generalizations about intensifier constructions. CLS, 8, pp. 272 – 277. Neeleman, A., & Van de Koot, H. (2008). Dutch scrambling and the nature of discourse templates. Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics , 11 (2), 137 – 189. Neeleman, A & Vermeulen, R (2010). Introduction. In Ad Neeleman & Reiko Vermeulen (eds.), A flexible theory of topic and focus movement. Ms. UCL. Nikolaeva, I., & Spencer, A. (2010). The Possession-Modification Scale: A universal of nominal morphosyntax. Ms. Ning Zhang, N. (2007). The syntax of English comitative constructions. Folia Linguistica, 41/1–2, 135 – 169. Primus, M. (1992). Selbst – variants of a scalar adverb in German. In J. Jacobs (Ed.), Informationsstruktur und Grammatik (pp. 54–88). Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. Reinhart, T. (1981). Pragmatics and Linguistics: An analysis of sentence topics. Philosophica , 27, 53-94. Rizzi, L. (1997). The fine structure of the left periphery. In L. Haegeman (Ed.), Elements of Grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics , 1, 75 – 116. Rooth, M. (1985). Association with Focus (Ph.D. thesis). University of Massachusetts at Amherst . Sayers, D. L. (1986). Murder Must Advertise. New York: Harper and Row. Selkirk, E. (1984). Phonology and Syntax: The Relation between Sound and Structure. Cambridge: MIT Press. Selkirk, E. (1996). Sentence prosody: Intonation, stress and phrasing. In J. A. Goldsmith (Ed.), The Handbook of Phonological Theory. Oxford: Blackwell. Siemund, P. (2000). Intensifiers in English and German. A comparison. New York: Routledge. Tavano, E. M. (2006). A bound-variable analysis of the adverbal emphatic reflexive, or How I wrote this paper myself. Ms. University of Southern California . Vallduví, E. (1992). The Informational Component. New York: Garland. Vallduví, E., & Vilkuna, M. (1998). On rheme and konstrast. Syntax and Semantics , 29, 79 - 108. Vermeulen, R. (2010). The syntax of topic, contrast and contrastive topic in Japanese and Korean. Short paper prepared for the presentation at the On Linguistics Interfaces II (OnLI II) conference at the University of Ulster.