PAl, CREATIVITY, REPRESENTATIONALREDESCRIPTION, INTENTIONALITY, MENTALLIFE: An Emerging Picture From: AAAI Technical Report SS-93-01. Compilation copyright © 1993, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. TERRY DARTNALLI Computingand Information Technology Griffith University Nathan Qld 4111 Australia Abstract. This paper outlines a general theory of creativity and locates the concept of creativity with respect to the conceptsof thought, knowledgeand intentionality. Thepicture that I provide is outrageouslysimplified, but, as Dennett said recently, such idealisation is the price we mustsometimespay for synoptic insight (Dennett 1992). I first provide accountof a significant and central type of creativity. ThenI showthat there is independentempirical evidencethat we are natively endowedwith this kind of creativity. Theemergingpicture throws light on what it is to have a mental life, and on what it is for a representation to meansomethingto a system. This in turn gives a broader perspective, including a general theory of creativity that, on the one hand, distinguishes betweencreative and non-creative systems,and, on the other, accounts for individual differences betweencreative systems. Thepaperis structuredas follows.Section1 arguesthat a significantandcentraltypeof creativityis the ability to ’break out’ of a mleset, or out of someother constrainingframework of ideas. Section2 looksat ’breakingout’ in moredetail. We break out whenweaccess certain representations in such a waythat wecan reflect uponand modifythem.Butthese are not anyold representations. Theyare declarative structures that expressthe proceduralknowledge that hadhitherto driven our behaviour.In articulating these structures weacquirea mentallife throughdiscoveringwhatit is that weknow,think and believe. The beaver knowshowto build a dam, but it cannot access this procedural knowledgeand express it as a declarative structure: it doesnot knowwhatit thinks, andconsequentlyhas no thoughts. Thusthere is an intimate relationshipbetweenbeingcreative andhavinga mentallife. Section 3 turns to AnnetteKarmiloff-Smith’sRepresentational RedescriptionHypothesis(RRH)(Karmiloff-Smith 1986,1990,1991,forthcoming a, forthcoming b, et al.; Clark & Kamiloff-Smith,forthcoming;Clark, forthcoming). The RRH is a theory of cognitive development that tries to explain howthe humanmindgoes beyonddomain-specificconstraints. It maintainsthat weare endogeneously drivento redescribeour implicit proceduralknowledge as explicit declarative knowledge, andto continueto redescribeour knowledge in increasinglyabstract terms. Thusweare natively endowed with the kind of creative ability outlinedin Sections1 and 2. This empiricalevidenceis independentof the earlier argument.Creativitythereforetakes centrestage in our efforts to understandhumancognition, becausewehavegroundsfor believingthat it is in our natures(and maybe uniqueto our natures)to be creative. Thispackageof creativeability, mentallife andnativeendowment appearsto be morethan a coincidence,and wemight II wish to thank AndyClark, Margaret Boden and others for helpful discussionsof this paper. 73 wonderwhetherthere is a unifyingfactor that wehavemissed. This hunchis spurredby the fact that wewouldbe surprised to find that a creativesystemcouldnot, evenin principle,have thoughts,or that a systemwitha mentallife couldnot, evenin principle,be creative. If this is correct thenwehavethe following:(1) a system is creativeif andonlyif it canredescribe, (2) a systemis creativeif andonlyif it has thoughts;therefore a systemhas thoughtsif andonlyif it can redescribe.Thought, creativity andredescriptionbeginto emergeas facets of the samething. Canwethrowlight on this? In Sections4, 5 and61 suggestthat the missinglink is that it is only throughredescriptionthat wecan have(genuinely. intentional)mentalstates. I suggestthat weinitially acquire intentionalstates by beingcausallysituated in the world.Initially wedo not haveaccessto these states, whichconstitute our implicit knowledge.Later weredescribe this knowledge in termsof explicit, accessiblestructures - that expressour knowledge, thoughtsandbeliefs. Section7 returns us to creativity. This cannowbe seen as the struggleto articulate whatit is to be (causallysituated) in the world.Thebeaverstays on its plateau of behavioural mastery,but wego beyondthis and transformour procedural knowledge into thoughtsandtheories that wecan reflect upon and change. This gives us a general theoryof creativity that consists of a phylogeniccomponent, distinguishingpeoplefromslugs and Sun4s,and an ontogenetic component that accountsfor individualdifferencesin termsof our abilities to deployour redescriptivepowers.Section8 suggeststhat rare individuals, such as MozartandPicasso, mayhavedirect access to their redescriptive powers.If machinelearning theorists can implementthis ability then machinesmaybecomemorecreative than people. 1. Boden on ’Breaking Out’ MargaretBoden(1990, forthcoming)arguesthat creativity the exploration andtransformationof conceptualspace--or morecorrectly, ofconceptual spaces. A conceptual space is a spaceof structuresgenerable,that is, defined,bythe rules of a generativesystem.Weexploresuch a space by studying the structureswithinit, andwetransformit by modifying the rules of the systemto producedifferenttypesof structures. Bodenarguesfor this by first consideringthe notionthat creativity involvesthe novelcombinations of old ideas. Creativity does involvenovelty, but Bodenobservesthat such accounts do not tell us whichcombinationsare novel, nor hownovel combinations can comeabout. Her main--and related--criticismis that manycreativeideas not onlyd/d not occur before, but could not have occuredbefore. Previous thinking wastrappedin a framework,relative to whichnew ideas wereimpossible.Consequently,creativity requires us to ’think the impossible’,to haveideas that are impossible in the present fiamework:weneedto ’break out’ of a conceptual space by changingthe rules that define it. Kekule, for instance, brokeout of the spacedefinedby the rules of nineteenth-centurychemistry, and openedup the newspace of aromaticchemistry. 2. Breaking Out and Having a Mental Life Let us look at a couple of cases of ’breakingout’. First, supposethat youare a Newtonian physicist whobelieves that light travels in straight lines. Thereis nowa sensein which it is unthinkable for youthat light wavesshouldbend,since it is logically impossiblefor Newtonian physicsto be true and for light wavesto bend:necessarily, /f the laws of Newtonlan physicsare true then light does not bend. Whilstyou remainwithin the Newtonianframeworkyou are trapped by this necessity.Or imaginethat youare followingthe rules of Euclideangeometry.Withinthe frameworkdefined by these rule, s it is logically impossiblefor the sumof the anglesof a triangle to be other than 180 degrees. Wecan break out of these frameworks by representingthe rules to ourselves. Oncewehavedoneso wewill see that the necessity lies in the hypothetical’lfthese rules thenX’--notin Xitself. This showsus howweare limited by the assumptionsthat wemake,but it does not explain whywefind it so hard to articulate the assumptions. I suggestthat wecanthrowlight on this by distinguishingbetweenrule users andrule followers. Rulefollowers are subject to rules. Theydo whatthe rules say. Computerprogramsfollow rules whenweset themthe task of (say) generatingproofs in Euclideangeometry.Rule users, onthe other hand,canaccessthe rules as a declarative structure. Sometimesweare rule followers--whenwe follow the rules of grammar,for instance--and weare trapped to the extent that weare merelyfollowers. Webreak out whenwe becomeusers--whenwearticulate the knowledge implicit in the rules wehad beenfollowing. 74 Wecan cast light on this by imagining a ’cognitiveladder’. Atthe bottomof the ladderare marshflies,hoverfliesandants. Themarshflyis exasperatinglypersistent andfollowsus about despiteour attemptsto swatit away.Hoverfliesmeetandmate in midair. Antsexhibit apparentlycomplexbehaviour.These creatures, however,havelittle or no knowledge, either proceduralor declarative.Theirbehaviouris principally driven by information that is in the environment, not in the organism (Dreyfus1979). Themarshflyfollowsthe carbondioxidethat weemit. Hoverfliesare hardwiredto transforma specific signal into a specific muscularresponse(Boden1990). Antscan detect contours,andhaveroutinesfor selectingthe mostlevel path (Simon1969; see discussions in Pylyshyn1979/1981, Winograd 1981; also Dreyfus&Dreyfus1987.) Whenwe discover these things we should abandonany suspicionsthat wemighthavehad aboutthese creatures having a mentallife. Theyare not merelymindless:they have no knowledge worth speakingabout. Theyare not evenrule followers. Midway up the ladder is the beaver. It has structured, proceduralknowledge about howto build a dam.However,it has no accessto this knowledge. It is trappedin a procedural framework, doingwhatits rules tell it to: first you put in stones, then youput in big logs, then youput in smallones. If a stormsweepsawaythe smalllogs, the beaverdemolishes what’s left of the damand starts again. (This maynot be empiricallytrue of beavers--if it is not, run the argument witha morestupidcreature.)In this respectthe beaveris like a computer program:it is a rule followerrather than a rule user. It doesnot representthe rules as an accessiblestructure. If it didit wouldbe able to directlyaccessthe rule for putting smalllogs on top of big ones. Nordoesthe beaverhaveanythoughts. Wesee it scurrying about trying to put the log there. The log keeps slipping out, and the beaver keepsputting it back. Wewantto say that the beaverthinks that the log shouMgo there--but we do not wantsay that it has the thought’the log shouldgo there’. This is a distinction that wecommonly drawwith people:the tennis playeris ’thinkingwhatshe’s doing’when she plays intelligently, but this doesnot meanthat she has explicit thoughtsaboutwhatshe is doing. (Adrian Cummins (1990) drawsa similar distinction tweenthoughtsthat have, or do not have, conceptualcontent. If Jo believesthat Bill is a bachelor,thenJo has graspedthe concept’bachelor’.But whenwesay that Fido’believesthat the noise (or the scent) comesfrom the south’, wedo not believe that Fido has graspedthe concept’south’! Cummins believesthat Fidohas no structuredor contentfulthoughts.I believethat he has nothoughtsat all.) Wetie these facts together whenwesay that the beaver ’doesn’tknowwhatit thinks’. It thinksthat the log shouldgo there, but it doesn’tknowthat it thinksthis. It doesnot have accessto its proceduralknowledge. Nowconsider Le Penseur (Rodin’s sculpture of someone engagedin deep thought--head bent, browfurrowed). Le Penseur’shumanequivalent has thoughtsby virtue of being able to expresshis knowledge as a declarativestructure, reflect uponit, andchangeit if necessary.In doingthis he is exercisingan ability that all of us have. Enterthe empiricalevidence--thatweare natively endowed to re, describeour proceduralknowledge as declarativeknowledge(and to continueto redescribeit at increasinglyabstract levels). Weare endogenously driven to go from being rule followersto rule users, thereby’breakingout’ in the sense described. 3. Representational Redescription this transcendencecomethoughtsand the mentallife. And there is independentevidencethat weare natively endowed withsuchan ability. Weare boundto ask more. Weare boundto ask whether it is only redescriberswhoare creative and whohavemental lives. In the nextsectionI arguethat this is indeedthe case, since our declarativestructurescanonly be aboutanythingif they are groundedin implicit knowledge broughtaboutby our beingcausallysituated in the world,andare thenredescribed as accessiblestructures. 4. Intentionality TheRRHis a theory of cognitive developmentproposedby AnnetteKarmiloff-Smiththat tries to accountfor the way in whichthe humanmindgoes beyonddomain-specificconstraints. It maintainsthat the mindis endogenously drivento go beyondbehaviouralmasteryandto represent its knowledge to itself in increasingly abstractforms.It doesthis, as it were, under its ownsteam--withoutneed of exogenouspressure. Initially, the system’sknowledge is embedded in procedures. It is implicitin the system’s abilities. It is notavailableto other procedures,nor to the systemas a whole.As Karmiloff-Smith putsit, it is in the system,but notavailableto the system.Later the systemredescribesit as declarative knowledge, whichis available to other procedures.Thesystemcontinuesto redescribeits knowledge on increasinglyabstract levels, all of whichare retained and maybe accessed whennecessary. Themostcommonly cited evidencefor this is the ’funny men’pictures(see FigureI). Westart with a groupthat has achievedmasteryof a task. Childrenbetweenthe ages of four and six, for instance, are able to drawhousesand stick figures of people. But when they are asked to drawa funny manor a funny house, they can do very little. Theyare lockedinto their house-drawing or man-drawing procedures:first youdrawthe head, then you drawthe body, then you drawthe legs etc. To begin with they can only modifyparts of the procedure,suchas drawing a squarehead. Butslowlythey acquirethe ability to access the proceduresas declarative structures, whereupon they can apply the rules in any order they wish. Children between eight andten are quite fluent at this, andcan drawhandson the end of legs and feet on the end of arms. Theycan even mixprocedurestogether, and drawcentaurs, andheads that have windows. ’But’, you mightsay, ’the youngerchildren could have donethings like that--it just didn’t occurto themto doso’. Tomeetthis objection, Karmiloff-Smith askedthe 4-6 yearolds to drawa manwith two heads. Commonly, the children drewa man,drewa secondhead, and then went on to drawa secondbody-and-legs:they werelocked into a man-drawing procedure. Theplot so far is this. Acentralandsignificanttypeof creativity is the ability to breakout of a ruleset, to gofrombeing subjectto rules to beingable to articulate anduse them.With 75 and Redeseription Theproblemof intentionality is the problemof howmental states, symbolstructuresor artifacts canbe aboutanything.I havearguedthat a systemis creativeif andonlyif it canaccess its knowledge structures. Butwhatis it for a structureto rapresent knowledgefor a system?Thestandard computational accountis that the structure is in the mind’s’knowledge bin’ or "thoughtbin" andthat the mindmanipulatesit according to formal rules (Dennett1986calls this "HighChurchComputationalism";see also Richardson1981,Fodor1987). The Knowledge RepresentationHypothesis(see esp. Brian Smith 1985)says that a systemcontainsknowledge if andonly if it containsa syntactic structure that meanssomething to us, and that causesthe systemto behavein an appropriateway.E.g., the systemknowsthat tigers bite if andonlyif it containsa structuresuchas ’Tigersbite’ that causesit to get up trees in the presenceof tigers. It is not clear howlocatinga structure withina systemcan enableit to knowwhatthe structure means.Andunderstanding a sentencesurelyinvolvesmorethanbeingpropelledbyits morphology. Ratherthan pursuingthese points I shall outline an accountof intentionalitythat gives a majorrole to representationalredescription,andthat throwslight oncreativity. 5. The InformationTheoretic Accountof Intentionality Myaccount is based on the InformationTheoretic account of intentionality. This is most commonly associated with Fred Dretske, though John Heil and K.M.Sayre have developedtheir ownversions (Dretske1980,1981,Heil 1983, Sayre1986). TheInformationTheoreticaccountexploits the mathematicaltheory of informationadvancedby Shannonand Weaver,whichsays that one state carries informationabout anotherjust to the degreethat it is lawfullydependent onthat other state. Dretskerealisedthat this shedslight onintentionality, since "Anyphysicalsystem,then, whoseintemalstates are lawfullydependent,in somestatistically significant way, on the valueof an externalmagnitude..,qualifiesas an intentional system."(1980,p 286). Thusaboutnessis not a unique featureof mentalstates but is foundin all causalrelationships. Now,however,Dretskefaces the problemof cognitive error (of howwecan havefalse beliefs, etc). Hemaintainsthat informationis distorted by the cognitivesystem.His critics reply that this commits himto sayingthat wecan gain knowl- ~- Joou~,4.11 - Jed. 8.7 p~- Viki 8. 7 ~- ovy 9. 6 - PkillpPo 5. 11 -He*,,k. 8. 10 H - Lee 8, 6 - Nlcoio 9. 4 -Ovy 9. g AA-PITII 6. 3 G-ANNA6. 6 ~A-OlTTIAH 10.2 ~-VOki 8. 7 A-JOSNUA 8. 8 Fig.I. A- VAI.SgInl9. 0 R-Soey,, 10. 9 O~- Jv,oi, 10. 11 edgeby removingthe errors fromour cognitivesystems.This implies that cognitive systemsmerelydistort information-andthis runs counterto our belief that morecomplex systems can gathermoreandbetter information.I shall return to this. were,have’prime’intentionality--intentionality that is dueto direct causal influence.Genuinerepresentationsare grounded by virtue of the system’beingin the world’. Areall genuinerepresenters re, describers?Considerthe beaver on the one hand, and a Sun4on the other. TheSun4 6. Combining Accounts contains datastmcturesbut has no mentalstates. Its datastructures donot haveanyintentionalityfor it, donot express Let us run the story with a redescriber. Theredescriber is knowledge for it, do not ’meananythingto it’. Let us supplaced in the world. Its peripheries are bombarded.It deposethat this is becausetheyare not redescriptionsof prime velopsinternal states that constitnteprocedural knowledge: it intentionality. Thebeaver(certainly the marshfly)is at the can build dams,drawpictures, pronouncewords,etc. This is knowledge in the systemthat is not availableto the system. other extreme.It has primeintentionality, but doesn’tknow whatit thinks. Let us supposethat this is becauseit hasn’t It consistsin the systembeingin a certain state. Because this redescribedits knowledge into accessible structures. Given state wascausally determinedby the worldin a lawlike way, these assumptions,the Sun4and the beaverhave no mental it is knowledge aboutthe world. life becausethey are not redescribers. If havingno mental ConsiderNETtalk.Whenit is bombardedwith phonemes, life is alwaysdueto oneof these twoimpediments, then only NETtalkdevelopsintemal states that are about phonemes.It redescribers havea mentallife. (Kant said that "concepts settles into internal states that (to use Dretske’swords)are without percepts are empty,percepts without concepts are "lawfullydependent,in [a] statistically significant way,on blind". Wemightsay that ’ungroundedrepresentations are the value of an extemalmagnitude".Thesestates account empty,primestates are blind’.) for its ability to pronouncewords.Of course, it requires, This, however,only restates the problem.Consequently I e.g., cluster-analysisto identifythe states that it has settled shall resort to an onus of proof argument--sometimes referred into, so that, as ClarkandKarmiloff-Smith (forthcoming)say, to as ’the best badargument in philosophy’.Let us assumethat the states are not available to NETtalk.Theyare only just (despite somecontemporary philosophicalopinions)wereally availableto us! do havementalstates. Theseare intentionalstates. Now,what Wecan provide a straightforwardlycausal accountof the groundshavewegot for thinkingthat intentional states can intentionality of such a system.Moreover,its knowledge is arise in anywayother thanthroughcausalstimulationfromthe relativelyundistorted,sinceits intemalstate is a direct reflecenvironment?If wehave no groundsthen wemust believe tion of its environment. Onthe other hand,this knowledge is that this is howintentional states comeabout in us. The limited,inflexibleandinaccessible. RRH thentells its redescriptivestory. Surelythe point about Backto our re, describer. Theredescribernowredescribes beinga physicalsymbolsystem,rather thana virtual one, is its implicit knowledge as explicit knowledge--as knowledge that it can causallyacquireintentional states. Then,if the availableto the system.Thisis aboutthe worldbecauseit is a architectureis right, it canredescribethe knowledge implicit redescriptionof knowledge that cameabout by beingsituated in these states in termsof explicit symbolicrepresentations. in the world.Its intentionalitylies in its pedigree. Cognitivescientists andmachine learningtheorists mustshow Withredescriptioncomesrisk andthe possibility of cogni- us howthis is done. tive error, whichis the price that wepayfor increasedabstraction, flexibility andan improved ability to gatherinformation. 7. A GeneralTheoryof Creativity This resolvesDretske’sproblemof howcognitivesystemscan Wenowhavethe rudimentsof a general theoryof creativity. apparently go wrong.Theydo not go wrong--butthere is a trade-off betweenrisk and flexibility. (MargaretBodenhas Sucha theory contains a phylogeniccomponentand on onpointedoutto methat skills andabilities are fallible as well-- togenetic component.The phylogenic componentconcems see her chapter on Hoverflies and Humansin Boden1990. the difference betweencreative systems(suchas people)and Hoverfliescan missoneanotherin mid-air. Beaverscan build non-creativesystems(suchas slugs andSun4s).Theontogeis concernedwith individual differencesin faulty damsby putting in the smalllogs first. Thepoint I am netic component the ability to redescribe. making is that at least someof the fallibility that is associated Thephylogeniccomponent locates creativity at whatClark withhighercognitivesystems---e.g,false belief--is a natural (forthcoming) call "a genuinejoint in the consequence of re, describingour knowledge in increasingly &Karmiloff-Smith natural order". Oneof the great evolutionarydividesappears abstract terms.) Thusredescribers can acquire intentional states and gain to be betweensystemsthat can redescribe their procedural knowledge as accessible structures, and that havethoughts knowledgethrough being situated in the world. Theythen redescribe this knowledgein terms of accessible, modifi- anda mentallife, andsystemsthat cannotanddo not. Nowlook at ontogeny.Thechild redescribesits procedural able structures that constitute genuinerepresentations,such as thoughtsand beliefs. Theyare genuinerepresentations, knowledge as declarative knowledge.Hereontogenyrecapitmoreover,becausethey are redescriptions. Theyhaveinten- ulates phylogeny.Wethen continueto update our framework tionality becausetheyare redescriptionsof states that, as it of beliefs, strugglingto giveexpressionto whatit is to be 77 causallysituated in the world. Of course, such frameworksare not everywheregrounded in re, description. Theyare only groundedas a whole.Quine andDavidson talk abouta looselygrounded webof belief. The RRH says that there are layers of (re)description, grounded (if myaccountis correct) in the bottomlayer of primeintentionality. Nolayers are lost or destroyed,andall can be accessed.Andour articulatedbeliefs, as well as a fluctuating environment,cause us to continually restructure andupdate the framework. This is mostobviousin the Arts. Art tries to expresswhat weknowor believebyarticulatingit as a declarativestructure: Munch’sScream,El Greco’sRevelation of St John, Bach’s Passions,Owen’swarpoetry--all articulate by extemalising. Wesometimessay that we do not knowwhat we believe until wehavewritten it down.In writing Sons and Lovers D.H. Lawrence articulated his complex attitude to his parents, that haddrivenhimto regardhis father as a despotandtyrant. Havingvoiced his attitude he wasable to evaluate it and changeit. "Weshedour sicknessesin books,"he said. Thetheoryof redescriptionexplainswhatis goingon here, andshowswhyit is creative. Redescriptiondoesnot give expressionto beliefs that werealreadythere: it actuallybrings theminto existence.Hithertowebelievedthat.., suchandsuch (just as the beaverbelievesthat the log shouldgo there, but doesnot havethe thought’the log shouldgo there’). Wewere in states that droveour behaviour.Redescriptionexpresses the dispositionsinherentin these states as accessiblerepresentations. Thisis not creatingsomething out of nothing--but it is the nextbestthing. This resolves an apparentproblemwith Boden’saccount. Thereis, I think, a dangerof her accountbeggingthe question by sayingthat routinecreativity is the creativesearchof conceptual space(or the searchof a limited,’creative’space). Since generative rules only determinewellformedness,we need to knowwhyMozartwas consistently moresuccessful (that is, morecreative) in searchingthroughthe musicalspace of his daythanSalieri was. I suggestthat the answerlies in distinguishing between three kinds of art. The first merely explores a space of structures--say, musicalstructures. Wemightbe inclined to regardthis as little morethana technicalexercise.Atthe otherextremewehaveart that breaksout of the confinesof the genre.Thethird kind remainswithinthe genre, but breaksout of anotherspaceby givingvoiceto feelingsandattitudes that hadnot beenvoicedbefore,either by the individualor at all (Boden’sdistinction betweenP-creativityandH-creativity). 8. Are there TwoTypesof CreativeAbility? developinghis figure-drawing programAARON, Harold Cohenfoundit necessaryto continuallyextemaliseandevaluate AARON’s ability, in order to find out whatits procedural knowledgeenabledit to do. Edmonds (forthcoming)quotes himas saying"weextemalisein order to find out whatit is that wehavein our heads... It is throughthis extemalising process that weare able to knowwhatwebelieve about the world"(Cohen,1983;see also McCorduck, 1991). A fewrare individuals, however,seemto create with consumateease. Mozartsaid that he wouldexperience a composition all at once--in a moment--both before andafter he wroteit down:"Aah,whata feast is there" he said. Wemay he sceptical, but the manuscriptscontainno errors. Thereis no apperceptiveagonisinghere, no evidenceof an extemalisation/evaluation cycle. Picasso,too, wasunableto put a foot wrong:"I do not seek--I find", he said. MozartandPicasso seemto havedirectly and unproblemmaticaUy achievedwhat the rest of us blindlystrugglefor. Mozart’s talk aboutinstantaneousnesssuggeststhat he haddirect andspontaneousaccess to a declarativestructure. In ’A Conversation withEinstein’s Brain’the tortoise/DougHofstadterinvites us to imaginewhat it wouldbe like to experiencea pieceof musicinstantaneously bylookingat the side of a long-playingrecord:"since all of the musicis on the face of the record,whydon’tyoutake it in at a glance,or at mosta cursoryonce-over? It wouldcertainly provide a muchmoreintense pleasure". And"Why don’t you paste all the pagesof the writtenscoreof someselectionupon your wall and regard its beauties fromtime to time, as you woulda painting?.., insteadof wastinga full hourlistening to a Beethovensymphony,on wakingup someroomingyou couldsimplyopenyoureyes andtake it all in, hangingthere on the wall, in ten secondsor less, andbe refreshedandready for a fine, fulfilling day?"(Hofstadter1981). Wasit like this for Mozart?(Remember that he claimsto r) The haveexperiencedit all at oncebeforehe wroteit down. RRH saysthat wehavethe ability to spontaneously redescribe, so perhapsMozarthad(almost?)full controlof this ability. If so, there are twotypes of creativity ability. Thefirst involves the extemalisation/evaluationcycle: weconstruct theories aboutour abilities by observingthemin action. The secondrests on the fact that abilities are grounded in states. Balls are able to bouncebecauseof their molecularstructure. NETtalk is able to pronounce wordsbecauseit has settled into a subsymbolic state. Ourabilities are similarly groundedin states. Nowsupposethat wecan redescribe the knowledge that is implicit in these states. Thenwewouldno longer needto construct theories about whatweknowand believe by observing our actions. TheRRHtells us that wehave exactlythis ability. Mozart,it seems,wasespeciallygoodat exercising it. For mostof us the creative process is a slow and painful one. Weengagein a cycle of extemalisation and evalua9. Conclusion tion, in whichweexternalisesomething, evaluateit, readjust our goals, and repeat the process (Edmonds,forthcoming; TheRRH is a philosopher’sstone for creativity research: it Sharpies, forthcoming).Attemptsto producecomputerisad solves problems,generatesplausibleexplanations,andleaps art and computer-assistedart havefoundprecisely this. In mightybuildingsat a single bound.Wepay a price for this: 78 the belief that the mindis endogenously drivento spontaneouslyredescribe--thatto someextent human knowledge, like the objective knowledge of Hegel’sOvermind or Absolute, ’evolvesunderits ownsteam’.Thisphraseis Pepper’s (1972),whovigorouslyobjectsto the notion.Theclaim,however, is nowan empiricalone. Assuming that the dataand analysisof human cognitionare correct,cognitivescientists andmachine learningtheoristsmustnowtry to implement this ability. References Bodcm,M.A.: 1990, The Creative Mind, Myths and Mechanisms, Weidenfeld& Nicolson, London.Revised edition, 1992, Cardinal, London. Boden, M.A.: forthcoming, Creativity and Computers, in Dartnall,T. H., forthcoming. Clark, A.C. & Karmiloff-Smith, A.: forthcoming, The Cognizer’s Innards, Mind and Language. Clark, A.C.: forthcoming, Creativity and Cognitive Development, /n Dartnall, T. H., forthcoming. Cohen,H.: 1983, Catalogue. Tate Gallery. Cited in Edmonds,E., forthcoming. Cummins,A.: 1990, The Connectionist Construction of Concepts, /n Boden,M.A. (ed.) The Philosophyof Artificial Intelligence, Oxford. Dannall, T.H.: forthcoming,Artificial Intelligence and Creativity, KluwerAcademicPublishers, Dordrecht. Denned, D.: 1986, The Logical Geographyof Computational Approaches: A ViewFromthe East Pole, in Brand, M. &Harnish, R. M. (eds,) The Representation of Knowledgeand Belief, University of ArizonaPress, Tucson. Denned, D.: 1992, Commandosof the Word, Times Higher Edw cation Supplement, 27/3/92. Dretske, F.: 1980, TheIntentionality of Cognitive States, MMwest Studies in Philosophy,5. Dretske, F.: 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information, MIT/Bradford, Cambridge Mass. Dreyfus, H.L.: 1979, What Computers Can’t Do: The Limits of Artificial Intelligence, 2nd ed., Harperand Row,NewYork. Dreyfus, H.L. & Dreyfus, S.E.: 1987, Mind Over Machine. The Power of HumanIntuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer, The Free Press, NewYork. Edmonds,E.: forthcoming, Cybernetic Serendipity Revisited, in Dartnall,T. H. (forthcoming). Fodor, J.: 1987, Psychosemantics:The Problemof Meaningin the Philosophy of Mind, MITPress, Cambridge, MA. Heil, J.: 1983, Perception and Cognition, University of California Press, Berkeley. Hofstedter, D.R.: 1981, A Conversationwith Einstein’s Brain, in Hofstadter, D. R. and DonneR,D.C. (eds) The Mind’s I, Basic Books, NewYork. Karmiloff-Smith, A.: 1986, From metaprocess to conscious access: evidencefrom children’s metalinguistic and repair data, Cognition,2: 3. Karmiloff-Smith, A.: 1990, Constraints on representational change: evidence from children’s drawing, Cognition, 34. Karmiloff-Smith, A.: 1991,BeyondModularity:Innate constraints and developmentalchange, in Carey, S. and Gelman,R. (eds), Epigenesis of the Mind: Essays in Biology and Knowledge, Laurence ErlbaumAssociates. Karmiloff-Smith, A.: forthcoming, a, Beyond Modularity: a developmental perspective on cognitive science, MIT/Bradford, Cambridge Mass. 79 Karrniloff-Smith, A.: forthcoming, b, PDP:Preposterous Developmental Postulates7 ConnectionScience. McCorduck,P.: 1991,Aaron’sCode, W.H. Freeman and Company, NewYork. Popper, K.R.: 1972, Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, ClarendonPress, Oxford. Pylyshyn, Z.W.: 1979181,Complexityand the Study of Artificial and HumanIntelligence, in Ringle, M.(ed.) PhilosophicalPerspectives in Artificial Intelligence, HumanitiesPress, Atlantic Highlands, NJ. Richardson, R.C.: 1981, Internal Representation: Prologue to a Theoryof Intentionality, PhilosophicalTopics, 12. Sayre, K.M.: 1986, Intentionality and Information Processing: AnAlternative Modelfor Cognitive Science, Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 9. Sharpies, M.: forthcoming, ComputerSupport for Creativity, in Dartnall, T. H., forthcoming. Simon, H.A.: 1969, The Sciences of the Artificial, MIT Press, Cambridge. Smith, B.: 1985, Prologue to ’Reflection and Semanticsin a Procedural Language’, in Brachman,R. and Levesque, H. (eds), Readings in Knowledge Representation, Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, California. Winograd, T.: 1981, WhatDoes it Meanto Understand Language?, in Norman,D. (ed.), Perspectives on Cognitive Science, Ablex, NJ.