3 AN INTRODUCTION TO VECTOR CALCULUS A - Introduction I n t h e same way t h a t w e s t u d i e d n u m e r i c a l c a l c u l u s a f t e r we l e a r n e d n u m e r i c a l a r i t h m e t i c , w e c a n now s t u d y v e c t o r c a l c u l u s s i n c e we have a l r e a d y s t u d i e d v e c t o r a r i t h m e t i c . Q u i t e simply (and t h i s w i l l be e x p l o r e d i n t h e remaining s e c t i o n s of t h i s c h a p t e r ) , w e might have a vector quantity t h a t v a r i e s with respect t o another variable, e i t h e r a scalar or a vector. I n t h i s c h a p t e r w e s h a l l b e most i n t e r e s t e d i n t h e c a s e where w e have a v e c t o r which v a r i e s w i t h r e s p e c t t o a s c a l a r . A r a t h e r s i m p l e p h y s i c a l s i t u a t i o n of t h i s c a s e would be t h e problem where w e measure t h e f o r c e on an o b j e c t a t d i f f e r e n t times. . That i s , f o r c e ( a v e c t o r ) i s t h e n a f u n c t i o n of t i m e ( a s c a l a r ) I n t h i s cont e x t w e can a s k whether o u r f o r c e i s a c o n t i n u o u s f u n c t i o n of t i m e , a d i f f e r e n t i a b l e f u n c t i o n o f t i m e , and s o f o r t h , A t t h e same t i m e , t h i s t y p e of e x p l o r a t i o n opens up new avenues of i n v e s t i g a t i o n and s u p p l i e s u s w i t h e x c e l l e n t p r a c t i c a l r e a s o n s f o r exp l o r i n g t h e r a t h e r a b s t r a c t n o t i o n of h i g h e r dimensional s p a c e s . More s p e c i f i c a l l y , l e t u s keep i n mind t h a t it i s a r a t h e r overly-simple s i t u a t i o n i n r e a l l i f e when t h e q u a n t i t y under c o n s i d e r a t i o n depends on o n l y one o t h e r v a r i a b l e . For example, w i t h r e s p e c t t o our above i l l u s t r a t i o n of f o r c e depending upon t i m e , l e t u s n o t e t h a t i n a r e a l l i f e s i t u a t i o n t h e o b j e c t w e a r e s t u d y i n g h a s n o n - n e g l i g i b l e s i z e and f o r t h i s r e a s o n a f o r c e a p p l i e d a t one p o i n t on t h e o b j e c t h a s d i f f e r - e n t e f f e c t s a t o t h e r - p o i n t s . ~ h u s ,w e might f i n d t h a t o u r v e c t o r f o r c e depends on t h e f o u r v a r i a b l e s x , y, z , and t . That i s , t h e f o r c e may be a f u n c t i o n of b o t h p o s i t i o n ( t h r e e dimensions) and t i m e . I n terms of a f u n c t i o n , o u r i n p u t i s a 4 - t u p l e ( t h a t i s , an o r d e r e d a r r a y [sequence] of f o u r r e a l numbers x , y , z , and t ) . P i c t o r i a l l y , Now w e have a l r e a d y used 2 - t u p l e s t o a b b r e v i a t e v e c t o r s i n t h e p l a n e and w e have used 3 - t u p l e s t o a b b r e v i a t e v e c t o r s i n s p a c e . T h a t i s , w e have l e t ( a , b ) d e n o t e <i + gj and ( a , b , c ) d e n o t e c?i + g j + gk. In t h i s c o n t e x t , w e may t h i n k of a 4 - t u p l e a s d e n o t i n g a 4-dimensional " v e c t o r , " even though we may n o t be a b l e t o v i s u a l i z e it i n t h e u s u a l sense. We have e a r l i e r come t o g r i p s w i t h t h i s problem i n t h e form of exponents. Namely, if we look a t b l , b2. and b 3 w e can i n t e r p r e t each of t h e s e p i c t o r i a l l y v e r y n i c e l y . That i s , b 1 i s a l e n g t h of b u n i t s , 2 3 b i s t h e a r e a of a square whose s i d e has l e n g t h b , and b i s t h e volume of a cube whose s i d e has l e n g t h b . But while b 4 does n o t have such a simple geometric i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , it i s j u s t a s meaningful t o m u l t i p l y f o u r ( o r more) f a c t o r s of b a s i t i s t o m u l t i p l y one, two, or three. In o t h e r words, we a r e back t o a fundamental t o p i c of P a r t 1 of our c o u r s e - a p i c t u r e i s worth a thousand words i f you can draw it. - I n any e v e n t , what w e a r e saying i s t h a t when we s t u d y f u n c t i o n s of n v a r i a b l e s we a r e i n e f f e c t looking a t an n-dimensional space. I n f a c t t h i s o f f e r s u s a r a t h e r s t r a i g h t - f o r w a r d , non-mystic i n t e r p r e t a t i o n a s t o why t i m e i s o f t e n r e f e r r e d t o a s t h e f o u r t h dimension. Namely, i n most p h y s i c a l s i t u a t i o n s t h e v a r i a b l e we a r e measuring ( a s we d i s c u s s e d e a r l i e r ) depends on p o s i t i o n and time. P o s i t i o n i n g e n e r a l i n v o l v e s t h r e e dimensions and time i s then t h e f o u r t h dimension ( v a r i a b l e ) . Notice t h a t i n t h i s r e s p e c t we can have a s c a l a r (as w e l l a s a v e c t o r ) f u n c t i o n of n-dimensional v e c t o r s (meaning t h e i n p u t c o n s i s t s of n v a r i a b l e s w h i l e t h e o u t p u t i s a number). For example, we might be studying temperature ( a s c a l a r ) a s a f u n c t i o n of p o s i t i o n and t i m e , i n t h e sense t h a t temperature i n g e n e r a l does v a r y from p o i n t t o p o i n t and a t t h e same p o i n t it u s u a l l y v a r i e s from t i m e t o time. I n o r d e r n o t t o i n t r o d u c e t o o many new i d e a s a t once, w e s h a l l devote t h e remainder of t h i s c h a p t e r o n l y t o t h e c a l c u l u s of 2 and 3dimensional v e c t o r s . Once we g a i n some f a m i l i a r i t y with t h i s b a s i c concept, we s h a l l extend our f r o n t i e r s t o i n c l u d e t h e more g e n e r a l s t u d y of n-dimensional v e c t o r s , T h i s t o p i c w i l l be d i s c u s s e d i n a l a t e r c h a p t e r of supplementary n o t e s which w i l l be covered d u r i n g our s t u d y of Block 3 . b Functions R e v i s i t e d When we f i r s t introduced t h e concept of f u n c t i o n s , we mentioned t h a t a f u n c t i o n was a r u l e which assigned t o members of one s e t members of another s e t . W e p o i n t e d o u t t h a t t h e two s e t s involved could be a r b i t r a r y b u t t h a t i n t h e study of r e a l v a r i a b l e s our a t t e n t i o n , b y d e f i n i t i o n , i s confined t o t h e case i n which both s e t s a r e s u b s e t s of t h e r e a l numbers. W e a l s o developed t h e v i s u a l a i d of t h e f u n c t i o n machine, wherein i f f :A+B, w e had f -machine (elements (elements The p o i n t of t h i s c h a p t e r i s t h a t , i n t h e r e a l w o r l d , w e a r e o f t e n c o n f r o n t e d w i t h s i t u a t i o n s i n which w e a r e d e a l i n g w i t h v e c t o r s r a t h e r t h a n s c a l a r s , whereupon w e have t h e s i t u a t i o n t h a t e i t h e r t h e i n p u t o r t h e o u t p u t of o u r f-machine could be v e c t o r s . I n o u r e a r l i e r example, w e spoke of f o r c e ( a v e c t o r ) a s a f u n c t i o n of t i m e ( a s c a l a r ) . I n t h i s c a s e o u r f-machine l o o k s l i k e input t (scalar) f -machine + More c o n c r e t e l y , w e might have a f o r c e F d e f i n e d i n t h e xy-plane by From (1) it i s c l e a r t h a t d i f f e r e n t v a l u e s of t h e s c a l a r t y i e l d d i f + f e r e n t v a l u e s of t h e v e c t o r F. F o r i n s t a n c e , i f t = 3 t h e n 8 = 3 1 + $j Moreover, i t s h o u l d seem f a i r l y obvious t h a t w e might l i k e t o a b b r e v i a t e t h e above i n f o r m a t i o n i n the form . Notice how t h e language i n ( 2 ) c l o s e l y p a r a l l e l s t h e n o t a t i o n t h a t w e have a l r e a d y used f o r " r e g u l a r " f u n c t i o n s . The o n l y d i f f e r e n c e i s t h a t b e f o r e w e were t a l k i n g a b o u t s c a l a r f u n c t i o n s ( i . e . t h e " o u t p u t s " were s c a l a r s ) of s c a l a r v a r i a b l e s ( i . e . t h e " i n p u t s " were a l s o s c a l a r s ) , w h i l e i n t h i s c a s e we a r e d e a l i n g w i t h v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s ( i . e . t h e o u t p u t s a r e v e c t o r s ) of s c a l a r v a r i a b l e s . I n t h i s same v e i n , we might w r i t e t o i n d i c a t e t h a t we have a s c a l a r f u n c t i o n ( i . e . t h e o u t p u t of f i s a s c a l a r ) of a v e c t o r v a r i a b l e ( i . e . t h e i n p u t of t h e £-machine i s a v e c t o r ) . A s an example i n " r e a l i i f e " ~f e q u a t i o n ( 3 ) , c o n s i d e r a s i t u a t i o n i n which a l l we were i n t e r e s t e d i n was t h e magnitude of -+ v a r i o u s f o r c e s being considered. I n t h i s c a s e , given a f o r c e F we + would compute i t s magnitude I F ( . I n t h i s way our procedure i s t o t a k e a v e c t o r ( f o r c e ) and c o n v e r t i t t o a s c a l a r (magnitude of t h e f o r c e ) . Pictorially, input 8 (vector) 1 8 ( -machine .output 191 ( s c a l a r ) . The f i n a l p o s s i b i l i t y i s t h a t we have Equation ( 4 ) denotes a v e c t o r f u n c t i o n of a v e c t o r v a r i a b l e . An example of t h i s s i t u a t i o n might be t h a t a t any g i v e n i n s t a n t we know t h e f o r c e ( a v e c t o r ) being e x e r t e d on a p a r t i c l e from which we want t o determine t h e a c c e l e r a t i o n of t h e p a r t i c l e ( a c c e l e r a t i o n i s a l s o a v e c t o r - i n f a c t i n Newtonian physics t h e d i r e c t i o n of the a c c e l e r a t i o n i s t h e same a s t h a t of t h e f o r c e , which means t h a t t h e "lawH f = ma + Again p i c t o r i a l l y , remains c o r r e c t i n t h e v e c t o r form f = mg) . input 3 (vector) ";-machine " output + a (vector) / I n summary t h e n , i f w e allow v e c t o r s a s w e l l a s s c a l a r s t o be our v a r i a b l e s , t h e n t h e s t u d y of f u n c t i o n s of a s i n g l e v a r i a b l e reduces t o one of f o u r t y p e s I n t h i s b l o c k we s h a l l , when d e a l i n g w i t h v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s , assume t h a t w e have a v e c t o r f u n c t i o n of a s c a l a r v a r i a b l e . T h a t i s , w e s h a l l d e a l w i t h f u n c t i o n s of t h e form Pictorially, x ( s c a l a r1 -t f -machine (x, (vector) * The key o b s e r v a t i o n t o b e made from t h e p i c t u r e above i s t h a t i f t h e a r r o w s a r e o m i t t e d o u r diagram i s i d e n t i c a l w i t h o u r p r e v i o u s diagram of a f u n c t i o n machine i n t h e s t u d y of r e a l v a r i a b l e s . Namely, T h i s o b s e r v a t i o n i s t h e backbone of t h e n e x t s e c t i o n . C The "Game" Applied t o V e c t o r C a l c u l u s I n d e f i n i n g l i m f ( x ) = L , w e used o u r i n t u i t i o n t o make s u r e t h a t w e x+a knew what w e wanted t h e e x p r e s s i o n t o mean, and we t h e n proceeded t o make t h e d e f i n i t i o n more r i g o r o u s u s i n g E ' S and 6 ' s . The r i g o r o u s way seemed q u i t e f r i g h t e n i n g a t f i r s t , b u t , a f t e r a w h i l e , w e began t o n o t i c e t h a t it o n l y s a i d i n p r e c i s e m a t h e m a t i c a l terms what we a l r e a d y believed t o be t r u e i n t u i t i v e l y . What may have gone u n n o t i c e d was t h a t once we had t h e r i g o r o u s d e f i n i t i o n , e v e r y proof we gave c o n c e r n i n g l i m i t s c o n s i s t e d of a p p l y i n g t h e r u l e s of mathematics t o t h e mathematical d e f i n i t i o n of a l i m i t . In t e r m s of o u r game i d e a , we d e f i n e d what a l i m i t was, used t h e a c c e p t e d r u l e s of n u m e r i c a l a r i t h m e t i c , and t h e n proved theorems a b o u t l i m i t s . The key p o i n t h e r e i s t h a t i f it should happen t h a t our d e f i n i t i o n of l i m i t i n our d i s c u s s i o n of v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s of a s c a l a r v a r i a b l e h a s t h e same s t r u c t u r e a s our d e f i n i t i o n of l i m i t when w e were d e a l i n g with s c a l a r f u n c t i o n s of s c a l a r v a r i a b l e s , and i f i t happens t h a t every accepted r u l e of numerical a r i t h m e t i c t h a t was used i n t h e e a r l i e r p r o o f s of our l i m i t theorems a l s o happens t o be a n accepted r u l e f o r v e c t o r a r i t h m e t i c , . th e n , i n terms of t h e philosophy of our game concept, e v e r y theorem about l i m i t s t h a t was v a l i d i n t h e s t u d y of "numerical l i m i t s n w i l l remain v a l i d i n t h e study of " v e c t o r i a l The purpose of t h i s s e c t i o n i s t o e x p l o r e t h i s i d e a i n more limits." computational d e t a i l . How can we t e s t whether t h e v e c t o r s i t u a t i o n p a r a l l e l s t h e numerical c a s e ? There i s a v e r y e l e g a n t y e t simple technique t h a t we s h a l l employ h e r e . W e s h a l l begin by w r i t i n g t h e d e f i n i t i o n of l i m i t i n t h e s c a l a r c a s e . We s h a l l t h e n go through t h e d e f i n i t i o n and i n s e r t arrows over those symbols t h a t w i l l now denote v e c t o r s r a t h e r t h a n s c a l a r s (and, a d m i t t e d l y , w e must t a k e c a r e i n determining what i s s t i l l a s c a l a r and what has become a v e c t o r ) . I n t h i s way, we a r e s u r e t h a t t h e b a s i c s t r u c t u r e cannot be d i f f e r e n t s i n c e t h e o n l y changes we made were i n t h e names of t h e v a r i a b l e s . We t h e n check t o s e e i f t h e r e s u l t i n g d e f i n i t i o n obtained from t h e s c a l a r d e f i n i t i o n by t h i s "arrowizing" technique i s s t i l l meaningful. For example, i f we t r i e d t o v e c t o r i z e t h e numerical statement t h a t a/b = c , we would o b t a i n - + + -b a / b = c which makes no s e n s e , s i n c e v e c t o r d i v i s i o n i s undefined. (Of c o u r s e , had we v e c t o r i z e d a l l b u t b , t h e r e s u l t i n g s t a t e m e n t would make sense b u t t h i s i s n o t t h e p o i n t w e a r e t r y i n g t o make h e r e . ) I n any e v e n t , c a r r y i n g o u t o u r i n s t r u c t i o n s s o f a r , f i r s t w e w r i t e t h e o r i g i n a l d e f i n i t i o n of l i m i t i n t h e s c a l a r c a s e , namely l i m f (x) = L x+a means given any E > O , w e can f i n d 6>0 such t h a t whenever then Next, we r e w r i t e t h i s d e f i n i t i o n p u t t i n g i n arrows wherever a p p r o p r i a t e . R e c a l l t h a t we a r e d e a l i n g w i t h v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s of s c a l a r v a r i a b l e s . Hence, x i s a s c a l a r . But f and L should be r e p r e s e n t e d a s v e c t o r s s i n c e w e have a l r e a d y agreed t h a t we a r e d e a l i n g with vect o r f u n c t i o n s and t h i s i m p l i e s t h a t our o u t p u t , i n t h i s c a s e f ( x ) and L, a r e a l s o v e c t o r s . Notice, however, t h a t even though we have now introduced v e c t o r s , E and 6 are s t i l l s c a l a r s . The reason f o r t h i s i s t h a t E and 6 denote a b s o l u t e v a l u e s (magnitudes) of q u a n t i t i e s , and t h e magnitude of both s c a l a r s and v e c t o r s a r e non-negative r e a l numbers. I n any e v e n t , i f w e now r e w r i t e our o l d d e f i n i t i o n with t h e a p p r o p r i a t e "arrowi z a t i o n n w e o b t a i n means given any E > O we can f i n d 6 > 0 such t h a t whenever then Our f i r s t o b s e r v a t i o n of t h i s d e f i n i t i o n should show t h a t i t i s mean+ + i n g f u l . That i s , e v e r y p a r t of t h e e x p r e s s i o n i s d e f i n e d ( u n l i k e a / b ) . Ou,r next t a s k i s t o see whether t h e d e f i n i t i o n c a p t u r e s what we would -+ + l i k e l i m f ( x ) = L t o mean. A f t e r a l l , what good i s it i f our d e f i n i x+a t i o n i s meaningful b u t it d o e s n ' t c a p t u r e t h e meaning we have i n mind? To t h i s end, it i s probably f a i r t o assume t h a t we would l i k e + + -+ l i m f (x) = L t o mean t h a t i f x i s " s u f f i c i e n t l y c l o s e t o " a- then f ( x ) x+a -+ i s " s u f f i c i e n t l y c l o s e t o " L. Notice t h a t f o r two v e c t o r s t o be " n e a r l y " e q u a l t h e i r d i f f e r e n c e must be small. I n o t h e r words, f o r any p a i r of v e c t o r s A and B , i f we assume t h a t t h e y o r i g i n a t e a t a common p o i n t then t h e i r d i f f e r e n c e i n magnitude i s t h e l e n g t h of t h e v e c t o r t h a t goes from t h e head of one t o t h e head of t h e o t h e r . C l e a r l y , t h e s m a l l e r t h i s v e c t o r i s i n magnitude t h e more " t o g e t h e r " a r e t h e heads of t h e two v e c t o r s . I n terms of our above d e f i n i t i o n , -+ -+ n o t i c e t h a t f ( x ) - L means p i c t o r i a l l y t h a t The s m a l l e r t h e d i f f e r e n c e between -+ t h e c l o s e r i s t h e head of f f ( x ) and + t o t h e head of L which means t h a t i s more n e a r l y e q u a l t o t. 2 ( . . I n o t h e r words, t h e n , i n terms of what t h e a n a l y t i c e x p r e s s i o n s mean g e o m e t r i c a l l y , w e s h o u l d be convinced t h a t t h e f o r m a l d e f i n i t i o n a g r e e s w i t h o u r i n t u i t i o n . Again, i n t e r m s o f a p i c t u r e @ If x i s i n h e r e / > x-axis ( C i r c l e of r a d i u s J @ of E c e n s e r e d a t t h e head of I.) -b t h e n f ( x ) t e r m i n a t e s i n h e r e ( p r o v i d e d it o r i g i n a t e s a t t h e t a i l 2,. So f a r , s o good, b u t i f w e want t o be a b l e t o c a p i t a l i z e on o u r game i d e a , t h e c r u c i a l t e s t now l i e s ahead. R e c a l l t h a t a l l o u r f o r m u l a s f o r d e r i v a t i v e s stemmed from c e r t a i n b a s i c p r o p e r t i e s of l i m i t s (such a s t h e l i m i t of a sum i s t h e sum of t h e l i m i t s , and s o o n ) . These p r o p e r t i e s of l i m i t s followed m a t h e m a t i c a l l y from c e r t a i n p r o p e r t i e s of r e a l numbers. The k e y now i s t o show t h a t t h e p r o o f s a p p l y v e r b a t i m when w e r e p l a c e t h e s c a l a r s by a p p r o p r i a t e v e c t o r s . For example, what w e r e some of t h e p r o p e r t i e s w e used a b o u t a b s o l u t e v a l u e s i n d e a l i n g w i t h o u r p r o o f s a b o u t l i m i t s ? W e l l , f o r one t h i n g , w e used t h e p r o p e r t y t h a t f o r any numbers a and b The i m p o r t a n t t h i n g i s t h a t i f we now v e c t o r i z e (1) t o o b t a i n we s e e t h a t ( 2 ) i s a l s o t r u e . Pictorially, The l e n g t h of one s i d e of a t r i a n g l e c a n n o t exceed t h e sum of t h e l e n g t h s of t h e o t h e r o t h e r two s i d e s . a W e a l s o used such f a c t s a s la1 3 0 and la1 = 0 i f and o n l y i f a = 0 . obtain + la1 3 0 and 121 I f w e now v e c t o r i z e ( 3 ) a p p r o p r i a t e l y , w e = 0 i f and on'ly i f 2 = 8 . R e c a l l i n g t h a t 1; 1 means t h e magnitude of i s t r i v i a l t o see t h a t ( 4 ) i s a l s o a t r u e s t a t e m e n t . g, it W e must b e c a r e f u l n o t t o become t o o g l i b i n o u r p r e s e n t approach. T h a t i s , w e must n o t f e e l t h a t i t i s a t r u i s m t h a t we c a n j u s t v e c t o r i z e e v e r y t h i n g i n s i g h t and o b t a i n t r u e v e c t o r s t a t e m e n t s from t r u e s c a l a r s t a t e m e n t s . One p l a c e where w e must be v e r y c a r e f u l , f o r example, i s when w e v e c t o r i z e any n u m e r i c a l s t a t e m e n t t h a t i n v o l v e s p r o d u c t s . Consider t h e p r o p e r t y of a b s o l u t e v a l u e s t h a t f o r any numbers a and b I f we t r y t o v e c t o r i z e ( 5 ) by b r u t e f o r c e we f i n d f o r one t h i n g t h a t t h e r e s u l t i n g e q u a t i o n may w e l l b e meaningless. F o r i n s t a n c e , t h e statement i s meaningless ( i . e . , undefined.) s i n c e w e have n o t y e t d e f i n e d an That i s , t h e l e f t s i d e of-: " o r d i n a r y n p r o d u c t of two v e c t o r s -)a$. Equation ( 6 ) i s u n d e f i n e d . I f we i n t e r p r e t t h e m u l t i p l i c a t i o n a s s c a l a r m u l t i p l i c a t i o n and v e c t o r i z e Equation ( 5 ) a c c o r d i n g l y , we obtain : (where on t h e r i g h t s i d e we mean t h e u s u a l m u l t i p l i c a t i o n s i n c e both 1 ;Iand I g ] a r e numbers) . The c r u c i a l p o i n t i s t h a t both forms of equation ( 8 ) a r e meaningful b u t they both happen t o be f a l s e . Namely, - -+ + a-b = (;I IS( cos Hence, since lcos<l< 1, ( 9 ) y i e l d s the i n t e r e s t i n g , b u t perhaps s h a t t e r i n g result that I n a s i m i l a r way, laxbl = If1 ( 1 If b Isin' . \; 1;1 lgl (since Isin I n o t h e r words, any l i m i t proof t h a t involved t h e r e s u l t t h a t t h e a b s o l u t e v a l u e of a product i s t h e product of t h e a b s o l u t e v a l u e s might w e l l be f a l s e i n a b s o l u t e v a l u e o r l i m i t problems involving e i t h e r t h e d o t o r t h e c r o s s product of v e c t o r s . Rather t h a n b e l a b o r t h i s p o i n t , l e t us i l l u s t r a t e our i d e a s by means of a few examples; and t o emphasize t h e i r importance, l e t us u t i l i z e a new s e c t i o n t o d i s c u s s them. Some L i m i t Theorems f o r Vectors Theorem 1 Suppose l i r n x+a Then l i r n x+a a. f (x) (f ( x ) + + + + = Ll and l i r n g ( x ) = L2 x+@ G(x)) = Zl + t2 . . To prove t h i s theorem, w e w r i t e down t h e analogous proof i n t h e s c a l a r ( W e w i l l n o t motivate t h i s proof s i n c e t h i s was a l r e a d y done i n case. P a r t 1 of o u r course. However, it w i l l be an i n t e r e s t i n g check f o r you t o s e e how " n a t u r a l n t h e proof now seems t o you.) W e had : Suppose l i r n f (x) = L1 and l i r n f (x) = L2 x+a x+a . Then l i r n [ f ( x ) + g ( x ) l = L1 + L2 x+a The proof went a s f o l l o w s (1) Let h ( x ) = f (x) + g (x) . W e must show t h a t l i m h ( x ) = L1 x+a (2) Let E > 0 be a r b i t r a r i l y given. 6 2 such t h a t + L~ . Then t h e r e e x i s t numbers 61 and and (3) Let 6 = min {61,62) . T h e r e f o r e , 0 < I x - a1 < 6 (4) But I f ( x ) - L1l + (5) T h e r e f o r e , 0 < Ix + Ig(x) - a1 If(x) - - ~~1 > I[f(x) < 6 + L1l + I[f(x) - Ig(x) - L1l L1l - E L21 < E E + [(?(XI- 1 2 1 1 + [g(x) - . (=T+2) L21I < E . - a1 < 6 17) Therefore, 0 < Ix Therefore, l i m h ( x ) = L1 + L2 x+a . + Ih(x) - (LL - + L~)I < t The key now i s t o observe t h a t e v e r y s t e p i n o u r proof remains v a l i d when v e c t o r s a r e introduced. Why? W e l l , f o r example, t h e v a l i d i t y of s t e p (1) r e q u i r e s t h a t t h e sum of two numbers be a number; o t h e r w i s e , h ( x ) = f (x) + g ( x ) would be meaningless. To c o n v e r t t h i s i n t o a v e c t o r s t a t e m e n t we only r e q u i r e t h a t t h e sum of two v e c t o r s be a v e c t o r , and t h i s w e know is t r u e . The v a l i d i t y of s t e p ( 2 ) depends o n l y on t h e d e f i n i t i o n of l i m i t and w e have taken c a r e t o m i m i c t h e s c a l a r d e f i n i t i o n i n forming t h e v e c t o r d e f i n i t i o n . S t e p (3) remains v a l i d by " d e f h u l t H s i n c e only s c a l a r p r o p e r t i e s a r e being used. That i s , both + I f ( x ) - LII and I$(x) LII a r e s c a l a r s . The v a l i d i t y of s t e p ( 4 ) hinges on t h e " t r i a n g l e i n e q u a l i t y ; " l a + bl 6 la1 + lbl, b u t t h i s , a s w e have s e e n , i s a l s o v a l i d f o r v e c t o r s . S t e p ( 5 ) is merely s u b s t i t u t i o n of s c a l a r q u a n t i t i e s . A s f o r s t e p ( 6 ) , t h i s f o l l o w s from t h e com- - mutative and a s s o c i a t i v e p r o p e r t i e s of numerical a d d i t i o n , and, a s w e have s e e n , t h e s e p r o p e r t i e s a r e a l s o obeyed i n v e c t o r a d d i t i o n . ~ n ' o t h e rwords, i f we n v e c t o r i z e " t h e s c a l a r p r o o f , t h e r e s u l t i n g proof i s a v a l i d v e c t o r proof. When w e do t h i s ( j u s t f o r p r a c t i c e ) we o b t a i n : (1) L e t g ( x ) = 3 (x) + 6 (x). W e must show t h a t l i m x+a h (x) = tl + t2 . , (2) Let E t h e r e e x i s t numbers 61 and > 0 be a r b i t r a r i l y given. 6 2 such t h a t and . Let 6 = min {61,62) Therefore, 0 < I x - a / < 6 (3) + + ~ f ( x )- L 1 l + I;(x) + -121 < E (4) I ~ ( x ) - +~~1 (5) Therefore, 0 < Ix (7) Therefore, 0 - I;(x) + B U ~ - a1 < 6 Ix-a1 C + Therefore, l i r n B(x) = L1 x+a i212 I [ % ( X I- + + < 6 + + L2 . i l l + [;(XI I[%(x) - ill lg(x) - ( i l + i 2<)El + [;(XI - i21 I . - t 2 1 ~ <E . I t i s , of c o u r s e , important t o n o t i c e t h a t our v e c t o r proof a s i t stands i s self-contained. That i s , it e x i s t s i n i t s own r i g h t even It's just that had w e n o t o b t a i n e d it from an e a r l i e r s c a l a r proof. by observing t h e s i m i l a r i t y i n s t r u c t u r e , we may deduce t h e p r o p e r t i e s of c e r t a i n v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s from t h e corresponding p r o p e r t i e s of t h e s c a l a r f u n c t i o n s , and i n t h i s way, we again b e n e f i t from t h e p a r a l l e l structure. Theorem 2 + I f l i m ? ( x ) = L1 and i f l i m g ( x ) = x+a x+a t2, then i f h(x) = f (x) a x )I Before proceeding w i t h t h e proof of Theorem 2 , we should n o t e t h a t t h e r e i s more than one way t o form a product of two v e c t o r s . We have a r b i t r a r i l y e l e c t e d t o t a l k about t h e d o t product. A s i m i l a r proof holds f o r t h e c r o s s product and w i l l be l e f t a s an e x e r c i s e . I t i s worth n o t i n g t h a t t h e f a c t t h a t we can form a product of two v e c t o r s i n more than one way w i l l cause c e r t a i n complications i n v e c t o r calcul u s t h a t d i d n o t e x i s t i n s c a l a r c a l c u l u s , s i n c e t h e r e , a product of two numbers could be i n t e r p r e t e d i n only one way. Proof Had t h i s been w r i t t e n i n terms of s c a l a r s r a t h e r than v e c t o r s , o u r proof would have taken t h e form f (x) = [f (x) - L1] + L1 therefore, If (x) g(x) - L1 L21 = IL2[f (x) + [f(x) - - + L1l Ll[g(x) Lll [g(x) - L2] - L~II - - Since 1 Ll 1 and1 L2 1 are bounded and both 1 f (x) Ll 1 and1 g (x) L2 1 can be made arbitrarily small by choosing x sufficiently near 5, the right a. This guarantees that side of (1) gets arbitrarily small as x + - L1 L2) = 0 lim (f(x) g(x) x+a lim f (x) g(x) = L1 L2 x+ a . If we now repeat this argument with the appropriate "vectorization," we have Therefore, ftx) 3 (XI = 113(XI - tl1 iCElot.ice t h a t w h i l e , ' f o r -exampl'e, + ILl[g(x)' - t21 1 '11 - L2] I . I' + F. 1 1 g ( x ) 221 - L2 I our s t r i n g of i n e q u a l i t i e s r e q u i r e s only t h e weaker r e s u l t t h a t T h i s , a s we s h a l l s o o n s e e , i s ILl [ g ( x ) L2] 6 lg(x) L2 + v e r y i m p o r t a n t b e c a u s e o f t h e v e c t o r p r o p e r t i e s t h a t la bl d - and ;1 x I i~~1 - I. 1:1 I ~ I 61 < 121 161. **We p u t t h i s s t e p i n t o e m p h a s i z e t h e f a c t t h a t t h e r u l e s o f o r d i a a r y algebra carry over very nicely here t o dot products. therefore, If (x) -+ g(x) - -+ Ll -+ L21 - it2 [f (x) - tl] + El [;(XI - 221 (This last step is independent of any vector arithmetic since all dot products are numbers not vectors.) 61 ,< 121 161 (observe that we don't need Now since 1; our last inequality yields (Notice that there are no dot products here since are numbers.) 1; 9 ) = 121 1611, 1 t21 , I 'E(x) - El1 etc. Our last equation has the same properties as (1) and so the desired result follows. Additional examples are left for the exercises. Our aim in this section was simply to illustrate that our limit theorems for scalars do indeed carry over, and in a rather natural way, to vectors. E Derivatives of Vector Functions of Scalar Variables In the study of ordinary calculus, we mentioned that the study of differentiation could be viewed as an application of the limit theorems. That is, when we defined f' by f' (xl) = lim Ax+O f(xl + Ax) A-x - 1 f (xl) every property of f' was then computed by the use of the limit theorems applied to (1) . The point is that we now do the same thing for vectors. that the expression T(xl + Ax) - T(xl) We observe is well-defined since it involves the quotient of a vector and a scalar and this may ve viewed as scalar multiplication. That is, scalar vector Without belaboring this point, this expression can indeed be thought of as representing an average rate of change, and, if we then proceed to the limit, we may think of this as an instantaneous rate of change. With this as motivation, all we are saying is that it is meaningful to define f ' by f v (xl) = $(x1 + Ax) lim AX +O - f (xl) 1 AX The key point now is that since the usual recipes for derivatives follow from the basic properties of limits and since the same limit theorems are true for vectors as for scalars, it follows that there will be recipes for vector derivatives similar to those for scalar derivatives. For example, it is provable that the derivative of a sum is the sum of the derivatives. The proof is again verbatim from the proof in the scalar case. Without bothering to copy the scalar proof, we write down the vector proof with the hope that you can recognize that it is the scalar proof with appropriate vectorization. We have Let S(x) = ?(XI + . ;(XI [h(xl + Ax) - s(xl) ] -b Then if' (xl) = lim Ax+O = lim Ax+O bx.. + . (xl + AX) Ax) + + Ax) - f (xl) [f (xl) + - 1 AX Ax+O lim Ax+O - (xl)I AX *(xl = . [f (xl + AX) AX - x ] g(xl + AX) AX + lim Ax+O [$ 1 - g(xl) -t (xl + Ax) AX -~(Ic~) (since the limit of a sum is the sum of the limits, as shown in the previous section). 3.16 I n a s i m i l a r way (and t h e d e t a i l s a r e l e f t a s e x e r c i s e s ) , t h e same product r u l e a p p l i e s t o v e c t o r s . The only d i f f e r e n c e i s t h a t we now have s e v e r a l t y p e s of products. For example, w e may have t h e product of a s c a l a r f u n c t i o n w i t h a v e c t o r f u n c t i o n , o r we may have t h e d o t product of two v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s , o r w e may have t h e c r o s s product of two v e c t o r f u n c t i o n s . I n any c a s e , we o b t a i n t h e r e s u l t s ( I n t h i s l a s t c a s e beware of changing t h e r o l e s of t h e f a c t o r s + + a x b = - 6 x ;).I We even have a form of t h e q u o t i e n t r u l e pravided t h a t our q u o t i e n t i s a v e c t o r f u n c t i o n d i v i d e d by a s c a l a r . f u n c t i o n ( f o r , otherwise, t h e q u o t i e n t i s n o t d e f i n e d ) . The formula i s These formulas have a n i c e a p p l i c a t i o n t o C a r t e s i a n c o o r d i n a t e s . Suppose F i s a v e c t o r f u n c t i o n of t h e s i n g l e r e a l v a r i a b l e t. For example, we -k may be c o n s i d e r i n g f o r c e a s a f u n c t i o n of time. Suppose F has t h e form -b and we d e s i r e t o compute d$/dt. Since t h e d e r i v a t i v e of a sum i s t h e sum of t h e d e r i v a t i v e s , we have 2~: : y,L' ,,i ,..- :.. = I L* 3.y- 5, -1. '.L, \ . . s ri- *- g . US". *.. . ;r ' Then s i n c e a c o n s t a n t times a v a r i a b l e has a s i t s d e r i v a t i v e t h e c o n s t a n t t + times t h e d e r i v a t i v e of t h e v a r i a b l e , and s i n c e 1, J , and k a r e c o n s t a n t s , we o b t a i n : While this was a specific example, it should be fairly easy to see that, in general, the derivat-ive is obtained by differentiating the components. Further details are left to the text and the exercises, but we want to emphasize again the fact that our definition of limit for vectors, being so closely modeled after the scalar situation, guarantees that the differentiation formulas with which we are already familiar in the scalar case are also valid in the vector case. MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu Resource: Calculus Revisited: Multivariable Calculus Prof. Herbert Gross The following may not correspond to a particular course on MIT OpenCourseWare, but has been provided by the author as an individual learning resource. For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.